A Note on Nicod's Postulate

  • 83 15 1
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up

A Note on Nicod's Postulate

W. V. Quine Mind, New Series, Vol. 41, No. 163. (Jul., 1932), pp. 345-350. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici

859 28 163KB

Pages 7 Page size 595 x 792 pts Year 2007

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD FILE

Recommend Papers

File loading please wait...
Citation preview

A Note on Nicod's Postulate W. V. Quine Mind, New Series, Vol. 41, No. 163. (Jul., 1932), pp. 345-350. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0026-4423%28193207%292%3A41%3A163%3C345%3AANONP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-E Mind is currently published by Oxford University Press.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/oup.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

http://www.jstor.org Sun Jun 17 05:03:59 2007

A NOTE ON NICOD'S POSTULATE.

I N Prof. Jorgen Jijrgensen's recent work, A Treatise of Formal Logic,l the deduction of Russell's calculus of elementary propositions from Nicod's single formal postulate

=

rp I (2 I r)l I {[t I (t I t)l I [ ( s I 2) I ( ( P I s) I (P I $))I1 is presented in detail. In the introduction to the second edition of Princzpia Mathematica2 Russell stated merely that the deduction could be made, and referred his readers to Nicod's original article3 for the actual performance. Nicod's presentcqtion of the argument thus remained the sole published record of the deduction until the appearance of Prof. Jorgensen's work. Nicod's paper presents the deduction in question in a rather brief and elliptic form. Prof. Jorgensen's rendering of the argument is, superficially at least, just that a t which one arrives when one carries out in full the intermediate steps which Nicod summarily indicates. Now the occasion for the present paper is the fact that Pmf. Jijrgensen's deduction involves two fallacies, and is in actuality no deduction a t all.. Misgivings a t once arise as to whether these fallacies are essential as well to the original work by Nicod, which has seemingly served as Prof. Jorgensen's guide. Were this the case, Nicod's condensation of Russell's postulates would be exploded ; happily, however, it is not. My conviction is that the fallacies in question have arisen only through misinterpretation of Nicod's argument ; in any event, as I shall subsequently show, they can be corrected without sacrificing the result. Nicod's thesis was that Russell's entire calculus of elementary propositions, as presented in the first edition of Principia Mathematica,4 could be generated from the single formal postulate expressed above, with the aid of two non-formal rules : (I)If p and q are elementary propositions, then p I q is also an elementary proposition, and hence can be substituted for a propositional variable in any true proposition. (11)Given the truth of p and of p I (r I q), we may infer the truth of q. It was his task, therefore, by means of (I)and ( I I ) , to generate from

Vol. ii., pp. 150 sqq.

PTOC.Cnmb. Phil. Soc., vol. xix., pp. 32-41. 93

"01.

i., p. xix. Vol. i., pp. 91 sgq.

346

.-

.

w. v.

QUINE :

the five formal postulates "1.2 to "1.6 of Principia Mathernatica, together with theorems equivalent to definitions "1.01 and "3.01 of Principia Mathernatica. This much deduced, the remainder of the calculus of elementary propositions of course follows immediately by virtue of the demonstrations given in Principia Mathernatica itself. The first theorem which Nicod proceeds to derive from (111) is the principle of identity, t I ( t I t), which, by the definition of 3 ,is the same as t 3 t. This theorem is not among the seven mentioned above ; i t is needed in preparation for them, however, as a lemma. Indeed. as the deduction is conducted by Nicod (and accordingly by Prof. Jorgensen), the principle of identity t 1 (t 1 t) is presupposed mediately or immediately in the proof of every one of the seven 'theorems in question. This lemma t I (t I t ) , therefore, constitutes the keystone of the whole structure. Hence i t is of some moment t h a t the two fallacies with which I am concerned both occur in Prof. Jorgensen's demonstration of this particular lemma. If this lemma collapses, one is left in the situation of not having proved a single one of Russell's postulates. The deduction of t I (t I t) as set forth by Nicod is not only brief, but obscurely enough presented to admit of misinterpretation : a too facile interpolation of the intermediate steps which he indicates, or might be interpreted as indicating, is likely to lead to fallacy. Since the literature appears to contain no detailed presentation of t h e deduction of t I (t I t), with the sole exception of the fallacious one by Prof. Jorgensen, my present object is to fill this hiatus. The remainder of the deduction of Russell's calculus of elementary propositions, from the proof of t I (t I t) forward, is adequately and satisfactorily presented both by Nicod and by Prof. Jorgensen, and hence needs no repetition here. Before presenting the deduction of t I (t I t), I shall point out briefly the fallacies which I have found in Prof. JGrgensen's presentation. This presupposes a few remarks on the matter of notation. Prof. Jijrgensen adheres to the general usage of Principia Mathernatica in employing groups of dots instead of parentheses, brackets and braces. I shall follow him in this convention, which is a valuable one in formule of high complexity. Prof. Jorgensen, howeverlike Nicod-reduces the number of dots needed by availing himself of three different typographic styles of stroke. I shall dispense with this device both jn my own work and in my transcriptions from Prof. Jorgensen, and depend upon the method of dots exclusively. Prof. Jorgensen, furthermore, adopts Nicod's bar notation : p 1 q, for example, would mean p 1 q . I .p I q. I shall do away with this abbreviation, and adhere to the latter form alone. I n any lengthy deduction in terms of the stroke, there is danger of becoming inextricably involved in a veritable labyrinth of stroke functions. Therefore Prof. JGrgensen follows Nicod in introducing certain single letters as temporary abbreviations for specified complex expressions. His conventions follow :

P=p.

I.qlr r = t . [ . t [ t Q = s l q . [ : P I S .1 . ~ & , = s i t . [ : t [ s .I . t [ s

Df Df 1Df ~ Df

The first non sequitur in Prof. Jorgensen's deduction occurs in

the derivation of his lemma (14).l This lemma takes the form

(14) Q [ r . l : : . Q l [ r . l . r : 1

: : ~ .[ : r l Q l :

I.QIr.:[:.r.I.r[Q1:I.Q[r.

Prof. Jiirgensen informs us in the margin that it is derived by substitution of Q [ r for s in lemma (13). Lemma (13) runs as follows : (13)

S .

[ : : . Q l l r . 1 . r : 1 : : ~l .. r l Q l : 1 . s . : : Q , :

1..

Now it must be kept in mind that r and Q, are mere shorthand for

two complex expressions, whose values are given explicitly above.

If a substitution be made for s throughout (13), therefore, such

occurrences of s as may lie concealed within r 'and Q, must not be

overlooked. Referring to the above definitions, we see that r does

not involve s, but only t, wherefore it may be dropped from con-

sideration in the present connection. Q,, on the other hand, contains

three occurrences of s. In the three occurrences of Q, in (13), there-

.* fore, nine occurrences of s lie concealed. In passing from (13) to (14)) Prof. Jorgensen has thus committed the fallacy of partial substitution, replacing three occurrences of s by Q I r and leaving nine occurrences of s untouched. If the substitution of Q ( r for s in (13), which he . signalises, were actually performed, the correct result would be Q [ r . [ : : : : . Q l r .1 . t : [ : . t . I . Q [ r : [ : t . [ . Q l r : : I . r . : : [ . r : : : I : : : : r . [ : : . r . l : : Q 1 . t[: r[ :. . t . [ . Q [ r : [ : t . [ . Q [ r : : : I . Q [ r . : : : [ : : : . r . [I::: :&. Irn. .1 . t : I : . t . [ . Q I r : [ : t .[.&IT::: [.&IT,

which is a useless theorem, incapable of playing the r61e for which (14) was designed.

This error would of course never have occurred if s I t : t 1 s I . t s

in (13) had been expressed in full instead of in the abbreviated form

Q,. The above abbreviations have proved a pitfall, designed though

they were to facilitate deduction. The reader will find, however,

that the present fallacy can easily be eliminated without violence

to the remainder of the deduction. Prof. Jorgensen obtained his

lemma (10) by the following substitution upon Nicod's formal

postulate : r I . r I Q, for p, and Q, r . I . r for both q and r . Let

this substitution be discarded in favour of the following one :

~.~.r~Q,forpandQ,[r.~.rforqandrasbefore,andufors.

Lemmas (lo), ( l l ) , and (13) will thus give way to similar lemmas

.

.

.

Throughout this discussion, l?f. Jijrgensen: op. cit., vol. ii., pp. 150-151.

w. v.

348

,

QUINE :

(lo'), (ll'), and (13'), which differ from the former ones only in exhibiting u's instead of the explicit occurrences, of s. Then (14) can be derived from (13') by 'substitution of Q I n for u in (13'). The fallacy which remains to be pointed out arises, like the preceding one, from failure to analyse the abbreviated expressions. This second fallacy occurs in the derivation of Prof. Jorgensen's lemma (16) : This is supposed to emerge by substitution of Q, I n

. I . n for P in

Here we are dealing in abbreviated complex expressions to the exclusion of all else. If Q, I n . I . rr can be substituted for the complex expression P , it must of course be of the form of P , i.e., of the form p . 1 . q 1 r. This condition, we find, is fulillled. For, turning to the list of abbreviations, we see that &, I n . I . n means and is thus of the form p . I . q I r. " The substitution of Q, I T . I . T for P in (9) " thus merely means the substitution of &,In for p, t for q, and t I t for r, throughout (9). At this point the fallacy appears -a fallacy, again, of partial substitution. For, the Q in (9) exhibits within itself one occurrence of q and two occurrences of p, as our definitions bear out. Yet Prof. Jorgensen, in passing from (9) to (16), has substituted Q, In only for the one occurrence of p in P , and has left unchanged the two occurrences of p in Q ; similarly he has substituted t only for the p in P, and has not dealt with the occurrence of q in Q. The nature of the error is obvious when (9) is written out in the unabbreviated form Substjtution herein of &,In for p, t for q and t I t for r would clearly yield, not (16), but The reader will find upon investigation that this fallacy cannot be eliminated with so slight a modification of the general argument as was adequate in the preceding case ; the roots of the present difficulty penetrate more deeply into the general structure of the -deduction. I have, therefore, deemed it advisable to present the deduction of t . / t I t anew in the present pages. I shall refer to Nicod's non-formal rule of inference and formal postulate as (11) and (111) respectively, in conformity to the numbering used earlier in the present paper. Explicit reference will not be made to (I), the non-formal rule dealing with substitution ; like Nicod and Prof. Jorgensen, I shall indicate substitutions in the

.

manner of Principia Mathernatica.

Thus, (n)

a, b, c, . . .

means that y, 2, . . . a, b, c, . . . have been substituted respectively for x, y, z, . . . throughout the true, proposition (n). I shall avail myself of the following abbreviations, retaining T and Q, but dropping P and Q in favour of A, B, and T :

To proceed with the demonstration of t

(ii) T . ] : : T ]. : S .

(iii) (iv)

.SIT.

.--

. I . t I t, or

T

I:T]

1.71(s

1 . ~ 1 ~ I.T~s.:]::. 5 7 . 1 ::u. 1 .7rls: ] : . s1 T . 1 . u : I : s l n - . 1.u

S ~ T . ] : T ~ S .

SIT.

2,

] : T ] S .

(v) u . 1 . , r I s : I : . s I 7 r .1 . u : I

[(i). (ii) . (11)]

[(III)

S1~,~1S,~1S,U p, q? 7 , s

[(iii) . (iv) . (II)]

1.u (vi) T . ] . A l A : S I T .

(vii) T . 1.-4 I A : l : : . n .1 : : B I

T . ~ . A : ] : . T . ~ . B ~ T : ~ : T .].BIT

(viii) A . 1 . T 1 B



(ix) A . I . T ~ B I: : . B l n . 1 . A

: [ : B I T 1. . A

(x) B I T . 1 . A (xi) Bin-.].A:]:.T. l . B ] T : I : T .] . B I T (xii) T . 1 . B 1 T (xiii) n

[(viii) . (ix) . (1111 [(vi) . (vii) . iII)] [(x) . (xi) (11)l [(i) . (xii) . (11)]

The reader will note on effecting a comparison that the first six steps of the above proof are identical with as many steps of Prof. Jijrgensen's argument,l aside from accidents of notation and sequence. He

Cf. Jijrgensen, loc.

cit.

will note further that the only additional point of convergence is the conclusion. We can very quickly assure ourselves a priori that the above proof is free fron such fallacies as have been discussed earlier-namely, fallacies of incomplete substitution arising from 'the presence of abbreviations in the formula in which the substitutions are made. For, the only lemmas in the above proof which arise from substitution are (i), ( i ) (iv), ( v ) (vii), ( i ) and (ix). Of these (i), (ii), (iv), (vii), and (viii) are derived by substitution for p, q, and r, or for,p, q, r , and s, in (111). Now (111),written in the most abbreviated form which my above definit,ions permit, is

.-

.

The sole abbreviated expression here-montains neither p, q, r nor s, but only t , and hence presents no danger in any of these substitutions. As to (vi) and (ix), these are obtained by substitution for u and s in (v). Since (v) involves no abbreviated expression but T , which is free from both u and s, we need have no misgivings in this quarter. We are assured, therefore, against fallacies of the type uncovered in Prof. Jorgensen's deduction. As to the legitimacy of my proof in other respects, the reader can verify this only by performing the indicated operations for himself. This can be done at a glance in the case of the derivations of (iii), (v), (x), (xi), (xii) and (xiii), all of which proceed by the application of (11) to pairs of earlier lemmas. Lemmas (iv) and (vii) can also be verified a t a glance, being the obvious results of the indicated substitutions upon Similarly in the case of (ix), which comes of merely writing A and B for u and s in (v). But each of the remaining four lemmas, (i), (ii), (vi) and (viii), can be checked only by carrying out the indicated substitution in detail and then introducing the proper abbreviations into the result. Parenthetically, it is interesting to note that the five expressions which I have abbreviated in the above definitions are themselves all truths of logic, and can be readily inferred from the above lemmas. T and T are already proved, in lemmas (i) and (xiii) respectively. By the rule of inference, (11), Q, follows from (xiii) and (i), and similarly A follows from (i) and (vi). From the truth of A in turn, together with (viii), we can infer B. Let me add that the above proof of t . I . t I t is intended merely as the correct interpretation of Nicod's original argument,' inverted to normal order, cleared of ambiguities of exposition, expanded into its details, and modified slightly with a view to elegance.