4,500 575 994KB
Pages 273 Page size 432 x 648 pts Year 2002
CRITICAL THEORY AND WORLD POLITICS
CRITICAL THEORY AND WORLD POLITICS EDITED BY
RICHARD WYN JONES
b o u l d e r l o n d o n
Published in the United States of America in 2001 by Lynne Rienner Publishers, Inc. 1800 30th Street, Boulder, Colorado 80301 www.rienner.com and in the United Kingdom by Lynne Rienner Publishers, Inc. 3 Henrietta Street, Covent Garden, London WC2E 8LU © 2001 by Lynne Rienner Publishers, Inc. All rights reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Critical theory and world politics / edited by Richard Wyn Jones. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 1-55587-802-4 1. International relations—Philosophy. 2. Critical theory. I. Wyn Jones, Richard. JZ1305.C75 2001 327.1'01—dc21 00-062564 British Cataloguing in Publication Data A Cataloguing in Publication record for this book is available from the British Library. Printed and bound in the United States of America
∞
The paper used in this publication meets the requirements of the American National Standard for Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials Z39.48-1984. 5
4
3
2
1
Contents
Preface Acknowledgments
1
vii xi
Introduction: Locating Critical International Relations Theory Richard Wyn Jones
1
Part One: The Contours of Critical International Relations Theory 2
3
4
The Changing Contours of Critical International Relations Theory Andrew Linklater
23
The Way Ahead: Toward a New Ontology of World Order Robert W. Cox
45
Critical Theory and the Democratic Impulse: Understanding a Century-Old Tradition Craig N. Murphy
61
Part Two: Critique in Critical International Relations Theory 5
The Nature of Critique in Critical International Relations Theory Kimberly Hutchings
v
79
vi
6
7
8
Contents
Negative Dialectic? The Two Modes of Critical Theory in World Politics N. J. Rengger
91
Global Realism: Unmasking Power in the International Political Economy Jeffrey Harrod
111
What’s Critical About Critical International Relations Theory? Mark Neufeld
127
Part Three: The Practice and Praxis of Critical International Relations Theory 9
10
11
The Practice, and Praxis, of Feminist Research in International Relations Sandra Whitworth
149
Deliberative Politics, the Public Sphere, and Global Democracy Kenneth Baynes
161
Creating Cosmopolitan Power: International Mediation as Communicative Action Deiniol Lloyd Jones
171
Part Four: Commentaries 12
13
“Our Side”? Critical Theory and International Relations Chris Brown
191
What Is International Relations For? Notes Toward a Postcritical View Alexander Wendt
205
References The Contributors Index About the Book
225 249 253 259
Preface
Critical Theory and World Politics is a book about the dialectical engagement of critical theory and the study of world politics. It also represents a moment—one hopes a significant one—in that engagement. A critical theory–inspired strand of thinking has been apparent within international relations since the early 1980s. It has formed a key part of a wider tendency—now known under the rubric of postpositivism—that has sought to challenge the metatheoretical assumptions of traditional international relations thinking and attempted to articulate and operationalize other principles and precepts in their place. But despite its many links, both intellectual and disciplinary, to other postpositivist strands of international relations thought such as poststructuralism and constructivism, critical international relations theory is seen by both proponents and opponents as representing a distinct and distinctive set of views and concerns. Simultaneously, and strikingly mirroring developments within international relations, critical theorists working within their more traditional domains of social theory and sociology have become increasingly aware of and engaged with the sphere of the international. This direction, in turn, has led to a significant break with the state-bound, and almost invariably Eurocentric, patterns of thought associated with traditional critical theory— a break whose radical implications are still being worked through. This book represents the first attempt to bring together key figures in these parallel moves to discuss the implications of their work both for the study of world politics and for critical theory. That this is the first such attempt despite almost twenty years of intellectual activity is a somewhat curious anomaly. Nevertheless, it remains the case that proponents of critical theory seem to be better at engaging with those who hold to very different intellectual viewpoints than with those with whom they share, ostensibly at least, common ground. This noninteraction, in turn, may well reflect the intractability of both inter- and intradisciplinary boundaries, even vii
viii
Preface
among those who are intellectually committed to their supersession. Whatever the explanation, the relative lack of dialogue among critical theorists has most certainly hampered the development of critical international relations theory. Critical Theory and World Politics is an attempt to kick-start just such a dialogue concerning the evolution and future direction of critical international relations (IR) theory. It was organized to encourage the greatest possible degree of engagement among the contributors. Initially, all were invited to present draft versions of their chapters at a conference held at the Department of International Politics, University of Wales, Aberystwyth. The chapters were subsequently reworked in light of the specific reaction they engendered from the other participants in the project and the themes brought out by more general discussion. The elements of interaction—and reflexivity—were further strengthened by an invitation to two figures prominent in the discipline of international relations, but not identified with critical theory, to comment on the arguments in the other chapters and on critical IR theory more generally. Because of the pioneering nature of this venture, it was felt important not to impose a preordained set of questions or issues on the participants. As far as possible, therefore, the themes as well as the structure of the book have emerged organically from the concerns of the contributors and from the interactions among them. That said, the decision of whom to invite to participate in the project clearly affected the shape of the final outcome and in turn reflected certain editorial concerns and preconceptions about what critical IR theory is and yet might become. It is important to make these premises explicit at the outset. The relationship between critical theory and other schools of thought in international relations has already been extensively discussed, and that discussion, of course, continues in this volume. However, the distinctiveness of the various strands within critical theory—and the possible implications of these differences for the coherence of critical IR theory—has not yet been sufficiently recognized or explored (at least within international relations). These issues are brought into focus in this book by ensuring that the main strands are all given a voice. The aim has been to represent critical IR theory in its diversity. It is, of course, a matter for the contributors—as well as the reader—to judge how significant these differences in intellectual inspiration and orientation prove to be. Another central concern in the design of the project is the extent to which critical theory–inspired themes can illuminate both the analysis and practice of world politics. Whereas metatheoretical questions are undoubtedly important, this volume is predicated on the view that they are only part of the story and only part of the possible contribution of critical interna-
Preface
ix
tional relations theory. Thus several of the chapters focus on more praxisoriented issues. Following an introductory chapter wherein I seek to locate critical IR theory within broader trends in social theory and international relations, the book has been organized into four parts. In Part One, three of the figures most prominently associated with the critical theory intervention in international relations, Andrew Linklater, Robert W. Cox, and Craig N. Murphy, trace the contours of critical IR theory. All three chapters not only reflect in different ways on the development of contemporary critical IR theory but also set out agendas for its future development. In Part Two, Kimberly Hutchings, N. J. Rengger, Jeffrey Harrod, and Mark Neufeld discuss the various forms of critique in critical IR theory. The discussion ranges from immanent critique to negative dialectic, from Kant to Marx, and serves to underline the diversity of approaches and opinions prevalent among contemporary critical theorists. In Part Three, “The Practice and Praxis of Critical International Relations Theory,” Sandra Whitworth, Kenneth Baynes, and Deiniol Lloyd Jones illustrate the potential payoffs—and problems—associated with thinking about world politics from perspectives informed by critical theory. In the fourth and final part, “Commentaries,” Chris Brown and Alexander Wendt provide penetrating discussions of the preceding chapters and offer their own views on some of the central concerns of critical IR theory. The focus in each of the four parts is not mutually exclusive of the others. Rather, by the very nature of their subject matter, the discussions in the chapters inevitably tend to overlap to some extent. Taken together, they testify to the intellectual vibrancy of critical international relations theory. The primary purpose of this collection is not, however, simply to demonstrate that interesting work is being generated under the rubric of critical IR theory. Rather it is to encourage critical dialogue and interaction with and within this work. It is this aim that has underpinned the organization of Critical Theory and World Politics from the outset. The ultimate success of the project will thus be measured by its ability to inspire or incite further responses. —Richard Wyn Jones
Acknowledgments
This project was made possible by the Cadogan Research Initiative of the Higher Education Council for Wales. Its financial support allowed those involved to be brought together for an initial conference at the University of Wales, Aberystwyth. The initiative subsequently supported the production of the manuscript. I would like to offer my sincere thanks to the trustees of the fund for their vision and generosity. Steve Smith was the main catalyst for the project and has remained centrally involved throughout. He has been unstinting in his support and sagacious in his advice. I am very grateful to him. Two other people have played key roles in the project. Eurwen Booth provided invaluable editorial assistance. Eli Stamnes gave selflessly of her time and expertise in order to help the manuscript take its final shape. I am grateful to them both. This volume was originally to have been edited jointly by Roger Tooze and myself. Sadly, however, Roger was forced to withdraw from involvement as a result of illness. I would like to thank him for his contribution to the overall success of the project. I would also like to thank Paul Williams, who produced the index, and all at Lynne Rienner Publishers for their usual good-humored efficiency. —R. W. J.
xi
1 INTRODUCTION: LOCATING CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY Richard Wyn Jones
When as an undergraduate student I attended my first international relations lecture, the professor commenced by announcing baldly that there were two kinds of theory, positive theory and normative theory. The former was concerned with facts and certainties and was the proper business of scholars of international relations (IR). The latter dealt with values, opinions, and aspirations and should be left to philosophers, theologians, and other “moralizers.” Since then, however, the subject of international relations, and indeed the object of its study, world politics, have been transformed. It is certainly hard to credit that the current head of any intellectually respectable department of international relations could introduce students to the discipline in quite the same way as I encountered it in the 1980s. Nevertheless, the professor’s introduction did capture one of the central elements in the discipline’s self-image from at least the mid-1960s onward, if not before. During this period international relations was almost completely in thrall to the attempt to develop and formulate a theory of world politics along positivist, scientific-objectivist lines (see Smith 1992). True, as highlighted in Craig Murphy’s rendering of an alternative history of the discipline in this volume, there were always other voices; true, as Murphy also reminds us, the commitment to the rigors of positive science was often more notional than actual, and indeed, the tools of positivism could be turned against the mainstream to some effect. But those who dissembled from the dominant approach were always a marginalized minority. There was no doubt where the center of gravity lay. In retrospect, however, it appears that the publication of the book that marked the high point of the endeavor to develop international relations as 1
2
Introduction
a positive science, Kenneth Waltz’s Theory of International Politics (1979), also marked the point at which the dominant approach began its decline. G.W.F. Hegel, for one, would not have been surprised by this turn of events. For since then the hegemonic understanding of international relations has come under sustained assault from a variety of alternative approaches. The cumulative effect has been to cast doubt on many of the verities so confidently—and complacently—propounded over so many years in so many lecture theaters and conference halls by members of the IR community. This is not to say that the scientific-objectivist, or positivist, epistemology that underpinned my erstwhile professor’s remarks has been cast aside completely. Far from it. Many, indeed almost certainly the majority of those actively engaged in the study of world politics through the discipline, continue to adhere to the supposed tenets of positive social science. But undeniably, doubt has been introduced. Those who remain faithful to those metatheoretical ideals are increasingly forced to argue for them rather than simply assert their “obvious” superiority. Thus although the dominant approach may still be dominant in simple numerical terms, its dominance has been denaturalized. The center of gravity has perceptively shifted. One of the approaches that has helped bring about this shift is critical theory, the subject of this book.
On Contribution and Confusion Since its arrival was heralded in 1981 by the publication of Robert W. Cox’s seminal essay “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory,” critical theory has not only contributed to the critique of the mainstream but has also made substantive contributions of its own to the study of world politics (see Linklater 1996b). These span the subfields of international political economy (Murphy and Tooze 1991 provides a good introduction), so-called normative theory (Linklater 1998 represents a landmark in this regard), and security studies (see Wyn Jones 1999). Moreover, as Andrew Linklater argues in this volume, the critical theory move within international relations runs parallel to and is wholly complementary with the development largely beyond the discipline of a wider literature “on the prospects for new modes of human governance and new forms of political community” (an overview of which is provided by Baynes in Chapter 10 of this volume). But despite this contribution, it is undeniably the case that critical theory remains the source of deep confusion in international relations circles. How and where does it fit in? Can critical theory be defined as, say, embodying a particular set of epistemological claims or a particular onto-
Introduction
3
logical standpoint? Can we even speak of a critical theory approach in the singular, or are there two or even more distinct approaches laboring under the label “critical theory” active in international relations? And if so, what if anything binds them together? Furthermore, how does critical theory relate to the alternative approaches such as poststructuralism and postmodernism or the new, and already seemingly ubiquitous, kid-on-the-block constructivism? Where are the points of overlap and areas of distinctiveness? The degree of confusion that critical theory engenders, and the degree of misunderstanding to which it is subjected, are apparent in some of the more recent and influential state-of-the-discipline surveys. To cite one well-known example, over a decade ago Robert Keohane distinguished between two approaches to international relations, the rationalist and the reflectivist (Keohane 1988). The former utilizes the principles and precepts of positive social science; into the latter category he lumped all their theoretical opponents, including critical theorists. It is clear that the reader is meant to infer from the labeling of the two approaches that members of the reflectivist camp are somehow hostile to rationality—or at a minimum, less committed to reason and rationality in scholarship and in human life in general. But as far as critical theory is concerned, nothing could be further from the truth. Keohane seems unaware of the fact that in recent years, Jürgen Habermas has been the most vocal and persistent defender of the Enlightenment commitment to reason in the polemics that have surrounded postmodernism (see, for example, Habermas 1987). The critical theory objection to the kind of positivist social science that Keohane advocates is not its commitment to rationality per se but rather that its conception of rationality is too narrow, indeed atrophied (see Wyn Jones 1999: chs. 1–3). Similarly, confusion reigns in Ted Hopf’s survey of what alternative approaches “bring to an understanding of world politics” (Hopf 1998: 172). Hopf distinguishes between mainstream critical theory and its constructivist critics, but he also further distinguishes between the two types of constructivism, conventional and critical. There is no need to elaborate further on these categories here. What is relevant for our purposes is that in illustrating them, Hopf seemingly manages to locate the Habermasian critical theorist Mark Hoffman within the “conventional constructivist” camp, whereas Linklater, equally heavily influenced by Habermas, is placed among the “critical constructivists” (Hopf 1998: 183, 185). A close reading of their work may well uncover some subtle differences between the critical theory of Hoffman and Linklater, but we can be less than sanguine that Hopf’s categorization of their work is based on such attentiveness to detail. This lack is underlined when he also seems to argue that one of the characteristics of critical constructivism—a category that includes postmodernist scholars—is an unequivocal commitment to human emanci-
4
Introduction
pation (Hopf 1998: 185) when this emancipation is precisely one of the central points at issue between critical theorists and postmodernists (see below). But should critical theorists be concerned by these and other examples of confusion and misinterpretation? It is tempting, perhaps, to conclude not. After all, critical theory can hardly claim to have been singled out for special treatment in this regard: All the alternative approaches have suffered the same fate (for what Checkel [1998: 339f.] has described as a particularly “egregious piece of caricaturing” see Mearsheimer 1994–1995; the treatment of postmodernism in Katzenstein, Keohane, and Krasner 1998 represents another low point). Indeed, in a discipline where the creation of typologies is so often a substitute for rather than a prelude to real analysis and engagement, it may be that the apparent ability of critical theory to escape easy categorization should be considered a positive advantage. N. J. Rengger (in this volume) suggests that the lack of any real response from the mainstream to Linklater’s criticisms of neorealism reflects the difficulties that the keepers of the positivist flame have had in pigeonholing his standpoint. And after all, it was Theodor Adorno, one of the founding fathers of Frankfurt School critical theory, who attempted to write in such a way as to avoid easy categorization (Jameson 1990). But it would be foolish to draw too much comfort from these observations. Adorno notwithstanding, confusion, let alone caricature, is clearly a barrier to understanding and intellectual development. Furthermore, I would argue that it would also be a mistake to conclude that all misunderstanding and misrepresentation is somehow part of a deliberate strategy to blunt the challenge of alternate approaches (a view implicit in Weber 1994a; cf. Neufeld in Ch. 8, this volume). In the case of critical theory at least, my contention is that there is already enough scope for confusion inherent both in the wider (extradisciplinary) tradition itself and in the specific ways it has developed within international relations. Reflecting on these somewhat tangled roots is necessary not only to understand how we have come to the present stage of development but also to allow the critical theory approach to grow and mature further into the future. In the first part of this introductory chapter, I seek to locate critical theory–inspired writing on international relations—critical IR theory—in relation to the critical theory tradition more broadly drawn. The reading offered suggests that rather than understand critical theory as a particular approach, it is more appropriate to view it as a constellation of rather distinctive approaches, all seeking to illuminate a central theme, that of emancipation. Working from this basis, I then explore the relationship between critical theory and two alternative approaches, namely poststructuralism and constructivism. The chapter concludes with a discussion of the distinctive con-
Introduction
5
tributions that critical IR theory makes—and can make—to the study of world politics.
Locating Critical International Relations Theory in Social Theory Broadly speaking, there are two main sets of influences acting upon critical international relations theory. The first is Frankfurt School critical theory, whose leading lights include Habermas, Adorno, and Max Horkheimer. They are surrounded by an extraordinarily talented supporting cast composed of such luminaries as Herbert Marcuse, Walter Benjamin, Eric Fromm, and, more recently, Albrecht Wellmer, Karl-Otto Apel, and Axel Honneth (for good overviews see Wiggershaus 1994, Bronner 1994, and Hohendahl 1991). The second is the work, perhaps more correctly the life and work, of Antonio Gramsci. But if Gramsci and the Frankfurt School are both influences on critical IR theory in general, an important point is that they do not, on the whole, influence the same scholars. That is, some critical theorists working in international relations draw on Gramsci, others on the Frankfurt School, but very few draw on both. To take some of the authors in this book as examples, Cox and Harrod are clearly influenced by Gramsci and Gramscian concepts and modes of analysis, but not apparently by the ideas of the Frankfurt School (Cox’s brief intellectual autobiography [1996a: 18–38] certainly makes no mention of any Frankfurt School influence). Linklater, Jones, and Baynes draw explicitly on the intellectual resources of the Frankfurt School but have little or no debt to acknowledge to Gramsci. Moreover, the division between these scholars is not only one of influences but also tends to be one of intellectual orientation: The Gramscian-influenced scholars are primarily concerned with political economy; those influenced by the Frankfurt School are interested primarily in political and normative theory. Of course, this distinction can be overdrawn. Linklater, to give but one example, engages with political economy in his 1990 book Beyond Marxism and Realism: Critical Theory and International Relations. And even if the distinction exists, the question remains, How significant is it? After all, it is clear that the Gramscian and the Frankfurt School approaches share a common ancestry both in the Hegelian-Marxist tradition and, as Kimberly Hutchings stresses in Chapter 5 of this volume, in the broader Kantian tradition of critical philosophy. One could even argue, utilizing the now venerable but still powerful base-superstructure model of society, that the difference in focus should be regarded as a strength. For if the
6
Introduction
Gramscians concentrate on understanding the economic base and the Frankfurtians concern themselves with the superstructure, is not the end result a more rounded analysis of the whole? In this sense Gramsci and the Frankfurt School might be construed as two sides of the same coin. But whereas such an argument might have a superficially pleasing plausibility as well as a certain symmetry, to accept it would be to undersell and oversimplify both elements. Gramsci was much more than a theorist of the economic base. He was among the first in the mainstream Marxist tradition to recognize the relative autonomy of the superstructure and to (re)emphasize the dialectical nature of the base-superstructure relationship. He was also interested in issues of culture and identity. Moreover, through his development of concepts such as hegemony and historic bloc, his legacy is a series of powerful analytical tools through which social orders and social transformations may be understood (Augelli and Murphy 1988 and Rupert 1995 are powerful exemplars of how concepts derived from Gramsci’s work can illuminate concrete issues and problems). Gramsci’s was an incredibly broad-ranging intellectual project and should not be confined or consigned to one side of any theoretical coin. When we turn to the Frankfurt School, the problem we encounter is that the very name implies far more coherence and consistency than is actually the case. Apart from a common intellectual heritage, personal relationships (which were often difficult), and a tenuous relationship to Frankfurt itself, little unites the members of this particular “school” (Wiggershaus 1994). Indeed, the differences in intellectual standpoints are fundamental and exist both among different members and even within the work of individual members across time (Wyn Jones 1999, chs. 1–3). To trace the various twists and turns in the intellectual biography of the Frankfurt School is an enormously complex task and clearly beyond the scope of this chapter. Nevertheless, it is necessary to gain some sense of the various strands that make up the Frankfurt School tradition of critical theory if we are to understand the relationships among the various elements that make up critical IR theory. This understanding is also a prerequisite for any attempt to gain a clearer picture of the relationship between the critical theory approach to international relations and alternative approaches to the subject. To these ends, it is useful to differentiate between three distinct strands. The first is the original conception of critical theory as a critical social theory—as a broad framework within which the insights of the traditional social science disciplines can be integrated with and through Marxian theory to produce an analysis of society that aims, eventually, to facilitate and support a process of emancipatory social transformation. Horkheimer’s essay “Traditional and Critical Theory,” first published in 1937, is the key statement of this view (Horkheimer 1972).
Introduction
7
The second strand of critical theory is concerned to trace why the possibilities for emancipatory transformation had (apparently) been extinguished. Its main elements were first elaborated in the now classic study Dialectic of Enlightenment, published in 1944 (Adorno and Horkheimer 1944/1979). This work reformulated critical theory as a critique of instrumental rationality and argued that the civilizational process itself had created a “hermetic society” suffused with a domination and terror from which escape—in any social sense—was impossible. The third, and almost certainly the most influential version of critical theory, has attempted to develop a critical theory of society within the context of a theory of communicative action (Habermas 1984, 1989a). Much more obviously post-Marxist than the other two strands, this approach claims to transcend the Marxian focus on productive relations and their immanent problems and to highlight instead the emancipatory potential inherent in communication. As a shorthand the three strands will be identified with three thinkers, namely Horkheimer, Adorno, and Habermas, respectively. This shorthand is not entirely accurate inasmuch as Horkheimer collaborated in the development of Adornian critical theory through his coauthorship of Dialectic of Enlightenment, but it is nevertheless a reasonably fair reflection of where the intellectual center of gravity has lain for each of the three strands. Given the major differences among these three strands in critical theory, the question arises, What, then, is the unifying thread that allows us to talk of a school at all? This issue is explored in Stephen Eric Bronner’s marvelous study of the Frankfurt School tradition, Of Critical Theory and Its Theorists (1994). His argument is that in the final analysis, the only thing common to all critical theorists, and fundamental to all critical theories, is a concern to explore the barriers to and possibilities for human emancipation—hence Bronner’s definition of critical theory as “a cluster of themes inspired by an emancipatory intent” (Bronner 1994: 3). Where does this leave our discussion of critical IR theory? The first point is that the same threefold distinction can also be usefully applied to the work of those seeking to utilize the insights of Frankfurt School critical theory in the field of international relations. Whereas the majority of those theorists are best understood as Habermasians, some are much closer to both the letter and spirit of Horkheimer’s model of critical social theory. (As will be discussed in the next section, Adorno’s critique of instrumental rationality also resonates in contemporary international theory, but in the work of poststructuralists.) Again, using some of the authors in this book as examples, Linklater, Baynes, and Jones are Habermasian critical theorists. To their number we can also add another influential proponent of critical IR theory, Mark Hoffman (1987, 1991, 1992, 1993, 1995). Neufeld’s work is arguably much more Horkheimerian in spirit. This is also the case for some of those writers working in the field of critical security studies. Ken
8
Introduction
Booth’s discussion of “utopian realism,” for example, contains many striking overlaps with Horkheimerian critical theory, even though Booth did not at that stage draw on the work of the Frankfurt School (Booth 1991b). More recently, I (1999) write explicitly within the problematique established by Horkheimer’s “Traditional and Critical Theory” (1972). But again, it would be wrong to overdraw these distinctions. Linklater has certainly used the work of Horkheimer and the early Frankfurt School, although less so in his more recent work (cf. Linklater 1990b and 1998), and indeed is now noticeably more radical than the increasingly liberal Habermas. Similarly, Neufeld has drawn on Habermas (for example, in this volume), whereas none of the contemporary Horkheimerians share the expectations of the revolutionary proletariat that underpinned “Traditional and Critical Theory.” Nevertheless, the categorizations do capture important differences in orientation and outlook. Habermas, after all, views his own work as representing a fundamental break with that of Horkheimer and Adorno (see Habermas 1984: 366–399; 1987: 106–130). It is not surprising, therefore, that this break is also manifested in critical IR theory. So, for example, in his chapter in this volume, Rengger utilizes some of the core ideas developed in Adorno’s critique of instrumental rationality to outline far-reaching objections to Linklater’s Habermas-inspired project. Once we view Frankfurt School critical IR theory not as a unified whole but as a series of different and indeed contradictory strands, it is then possible to clarify its relationship(s) with Gramscian critical theory. The fundamental point here is that Gramscian critical theory is much closer to one Frankfurt School strand than the others. Specifically, the differences between Gramsci’s work, especially in the way it has been interpreted in international relations, and Horkheimer’s critical social theory are small. True, the latter abjures the former’s concern with political economy to concentrate almost exclusively on superstructural phenomena. Nevertheless, both approaches are rooted in the same Marxian productivist paradigm, and both seek to develop a social theory orientated toward social transformation. They are recognizably variations on a theme rather than different in any fundamental way. (More work remains to be done on the commonalities and differences between the work of Gramsci and that of the Frankfurt School; in the interim see Holub 1992.) It might be added, parenthetically, that it is this convergence between the Horkheimer of “Traditional and Critical Theory” and Gramscian critical IR theory—as if to emphasize the point, Cox (1981) makes an almost analogous distinction between problem solving and critical theory—that initially made critical IR theory (as a whole) appear to many observers to be more unified and coherent than has actually proven to be the case. The distance between Gramscian critical theory and work conducted in the Adornian or Habermasian veins is much greater. Gramsci and Adorno
Introduction
9
are separated by a vast gulf. Through the critique of instrumental rationality, Adorno “rephilosophized” critical theory (Dubiel 1985). He effectively abandoned all hope in the possibility of developing a critical social theory and instead posited that the purpose of critical theory is to interpret the capacity of avant garde art to mimetically transmit those echoes of humanity’s emancipatory impulses that have now completely fled the social realm (Wellmer 1983; Zuidervaart 1991; Bronner 1994). Even if Gramsci was a drama critic of some distinction, this is not a formulation with which he could ever have sympathized! In the case of Habermasian critical theory, the situation is more complex, but in the final analysis, Gramsci and Gramscians are working in a paradigm fundamentally different from that of Habermas and the Habermasians. Even if Gramsci was concerned with linguistics, communication, and the construction of intersubjective understanding (hegemony)— all familiar Habermasian themes—his concern was situated within the context of a social theory that regarded productive relations as (ultimately) determinant and that viewed humanity’s emancipatory capacity as being immanent within the productive sphere rather than in language. The communicative turn in critical theory pioneered by Habermas represents as fundamental a break from the ideas of Gramsci as it does from those of Horkheimer. Given differences and distinctions among the different strands of critical IR theory that have been identified here, we are left with the same fundamental question raised earlier in the context of the Frankfurt School. What, if anything, unites or links these strands? The answer is substantially the same as in the former case. Those developing critical IR theory clearly share in, and partake of, the same broad intellectual heritage of Hegelian or Western Marxism (Anderson 1979). Beyond that, however, as has already been made clear, little positively unites them. Whereas critical IR theorists may largely agree with each other in terms of their critique of the mainstream, there is little agreement among them as to what should take its place. Critical IR theory is not characterized by a commitment to a particular epistemology (contra S. Smith 1996) or to a specific ontology. Neither do its proponents subscribe to a common political program. Ultimately rather, as in the case of Frankfurt School critical theory, the ties that bind are a shared commitment to exploring and elucidating the theme of human emancipation as it is highlighted in the study of world politics. Critical IR theory is thus best understood as a constellation of different approaches, all seeking to illuminate the question of emancipation in world politics. The constellation metaphor first developed by Adorno and Benjamin, and later utilized to great effect by Martin Jay (1984a) as an organizational device for his short introduction to the ideas of Adorno, is particularly apposite (see also Bernstein 1991). Its usage—then as now—
10
Introduction
seeks to facilitate the thinking through of relationships between various “elements” that “resist reduction to a common denominator, essential core, or generative first principle” but that are, nonetheless, linked in significant ways (Jay 1984a: 15). Critical IR theory certainly resists reduction to a particular set of principles and precepts, but the shared concern with and commitment to emancipation does allow its proponents to identify—and to be identified—with the same broad intellectual project.
Locating Critical IR Theory Among the Alternative Approaches Having argued that critical IR theory should be viewed as a constellation of approaches rather than as an approach, I seek in this section to utilize this understanding to briefly explore the relationship between it and some of the alternative approaches to international relations. I will focus on two different approaches in particular, poststructuralism and constructivism. Poststructuralism Habermas, as has already been mentioned, has been at the center of recent debates concerning the poststructuralist move in social theory. These debates, which have often been decidedly polemical in tone, have pitted critical theory as the defender of the modernist tradition against its postmodern detractors. To many, including perhaps a number of those involved in the exchanges, critical theory and poststructuralism have appeared as implacable foes. These conflicts and disagreements in social theory have been replicated to some extent in international relations. The debate between Hoffman and Rengger, which is discussed by Rengger in Chapter 6, highlighted many of the differences, and these have been further and forcibly underlined by Chris Brown (1994a; also Ch. 12 in this volume). Neufeld (in Ch. 8) has also attempted to clarify the distinctions between poststructuralism and critical IR theory, as well as their implications. Another view of the critical theory–poststructuralist relationship is in evidence. Linklater (1990a: postscript; also Ch. 2 in this volume) has focused on the commonalities—on the points of intersection—between critical theory and poststructuralism (his attitude has not, however, always been reciprocated by the poststructuralist camp; see Walker 1999). In Chapter 5 in this volume, Hutchings calls for a halt in the ultimately futile “wars of reason” between critical theorists and poststucturalists and seeks to move the debate from the level of metatheory to that of political analysis, where both may well find that more unites than divides them. Implicit
Introduction
11
in Murphy’s (Ch. 4 in this volume) alternative history of international relations is the view that critical theory and poststructuralist international relations theory are both manifestations of the same radical sensibility—what he describes as the “democratic impulse” in international relations. How are we to understand these two apparently contradictory views of the relationship? Are those who stress differences to be dismissed as sectarian dogmatics, or are those who focus on commonalities simply engaged in a more or less sinister exercise in co-option? I would argue that to pose the question in this way is to succumb to a form of binary thinking that in this case, as in most others, is distinctly unhelpful. Rather, when critical IR theory is understood in terms of a constellation, it is clear that both views of the relationship are, in a sense, correct. Some elements in the constellation of critical IR theory do have a great deal in common with some of those in the constellation of poststructuralism (poststructuralist thought is no more unified than critical theory and is also best understood in these terms). So, for example, when the poststructuralist R.B.J. Walker writes that “it is important to recognize that ideas, consciousness, culture, and ideology are bound up with more immediately visible kinds of political, military and economic power,” in this case at least, his thinking is in complete harmony with Gramscian critical theory (Walker 1984: 3). The congruence between key elements of Adorno’s critique of instrumental rationality and Foucault’s genealogies of domination are even more striking and were remarked upon by Foucault himself (see Foucault 1991: 115–129). Indeed, it is plausible to argue that writings on international relations in a Foucauldian vein are the closest we have at present to an Adornian critical IR theory. There is also substantial convergence between some poststructuralists and Habermasians. As Linklater persuasively argues, for example, little of substance separates the Habermasians’ normative stress on “unconstrained communication” and Lyotard’s support for “equal rights of participation in a universal speech community” (see Ch. 2 in this volume). Of course, there are also differences in influences, in focus, and in orientation. Most fundamentally perhaps, poststructuralist writing in international relations remains deeply suspicious of the critical IR theory stress on emancipation (see Wyn Jones forthcoming). But when we understand critical IR theory and poststructuralism in terms of constellations, it remains a moot point whether the differences between them are any greater than the differences within them. Moreover, it must be remembered that it is only a very attenuated version of modernism that has been defended by any of the strands within the critical theory tradition, and that version has become more attenuated over time. When one also considers Jacques Derrida’s refusal to “renounce the great classi-
12
Introduction
cal discourse of emancipation” (Derrida 1996: 82) and recognizes further the existence of a general ethical turn within poststructuralist social theory (Honneth 1995a), it may well be that over time, the differences among other elements within these constellations will become increasingly imperceptible. Constructivism Since constructivism’s emergence onto the international relations stage in the late 1980s (Kratochwil 1989 and Onuf 1989 remain important basic statements), there is no denying its very substantial impact. One of the points at issue in the overviews of the constructivist literature that have begun to appear (e.g., Checkel 1998; Hopf 1998; Price and Reus-Smit 1998; Katzenstein, Keohane, and Krasner 1998; Zehfuss 1997) has been the relationship between the “constructivist turn” and the other alternative approaches, including critical theory. As yet at least, no consensus has appeared. Hopf, for example, argues that constructivism has “its origins in critical theory” (1998: 181), a category into which he conflates both critical theory and postmodernism with his focus firmly on the latter (his confusion concerning the former has already been noted). Jeffrey Checkel, in contrast, argues that one of the benefits of the constructivist intervention in international relations is that “constructivists have rescued the exploration of identity from postmodernists” (1998: 325)—and, one suspects by extension, from critical theorists. A more nuanced and more interesting analysis is proffered by Richard Price and Christian Reus-Smit. Their core argument is that constructivism is best understood as the empirical or applied wing of postpositivist international relations theory. That is, it represents an attempt to move beyond the metatheoretical concerns of critical IR theory (which, in their usage, is a spectrum encompassing the work of both modernists and postmodernists) to apply the “ontological propositions, conceptual frameworks, and methods” of postpositivism to a substantive analysis of world politics proper rather than simply to the discourse of international relations itself (1998: 264). They go on to differentiate between modernist and postmodernist forms of constructivism (267–270). The former category, which presumably (though the links are not spelled out) is the closest to the critical theory strand within postpositivist theorizing, is further subdivided between “systematic constructivism,” a category that apparently contains only one person, namely Alexander Wendt, and “holistic constructivism,” two of whose leading proponents are Friedrich Kratochwil and John Gerard Ruggie (268–269). But these distinctions notwithstanding, the authors seem to claim that all constructivism is consistent with critical theory in the sense used in this book:
Introduction
13
Constructivism problematizes both agents and structures, it explores the dynamics of change as well as the rhythms of stasis, and it calls into question established understandings of world politics, it is analytically open not closed. For these reasons, it is necessarily “critical” in the sense meant by Habermas and Cox. (288)
They, however, also concede that constructivists have had comparatively little to say about the “normative orientation” of their work and that “constructivism contains no philosophy of the good life or the ideal political order per se” (287, 288). As a result, they strongly imply that the role of critical theory in the “new phase” that they claim constructivism represents is to supply the normative orientation toward which constructivists, because of their “underlying ontological and epistemological assumptions,” are predisposed but are apparently unable to generate themselves (288). Given their approving comments about the normative framework developed in Linklater’s work, it is perhaps not too fanciful to suggest that, in this regard at least, it is with one of the strands of critical IR theory already discussed in this chapter—namely the Habermasian—that Price and ReusSmit wish to bring constructivism into dialogue (284–288). When these comments are taken in conjunction with Wendt’s explicit commitment to emancipation (Ch. 13 in this volume), and bearing in mind also that Price and Reus-Smit strongly imply that Wendt is among the least radical of the constructivists, a very interesting picture emerges. Granted, the constructivism label encompasses a variety of disparate scholars and many different and indeed contradictory viewpoints on matters epistemological, ontological, and methodological. But the fact remains that a group of scholars who are usually identified as constructivists in international relations are apparently seeking to identify themselves with key aspects— the key aspect?—of critical IR theory. What are we to make of this? Are they somehow wrong? Are they not really critical theorists, despite what they seem to think? Or rather, do we need to redraw our disciplinary maps and reassess our ideas as to who or what constitutes critical IR theory? In an important sense, it may well be too early to attempt to come to any definitive conclusions. The discipline of international relations, as has already been noted, is in a considerable state of flux, and constructivism is a relatively recent intervention. It is also undoubtedly the case that the mainstream exerts a strong gravitational pull on many constructivists, and this pull may yet serve to blunt the force of many of the more heretical notions to which they currently adhere. Nevertheless, utilizing the model of critical IR theory developed here, we can begin making some tentative suggestions as to the points of commonality and difference between constructivism and critical theory, as well as their implications. Elements in the constellation of critical IR theory clearly overlap with elements in the constructivist constellation. Price and Reus-Smit claim a
14
Introduction
fundamental convergence between their project and both that of Cox and of Habermas, but it is with the latter rather than the former that common ground can most easily be identified. Cox, as has been noted, remains fundamentally rooted in a productivist paradigm, and most constructivists would almost certainly demur from the historical materialist premises of his work even if they might agree with aspects of his critique of the mainstream. The same is arguably the case for Horkheimerian critical theory. When we turn to Habermasian critical theory, commonalities become much more apparent. Thinkers such as Kratochwil and Nicholas Onuf are recognizably ploughing the same furrow as Habermas (Kratochwil 1989, Onuf 1989; see also Zehfuss 1997). They too are concerned with speech acts, communicative action, and, in the case of Kratochwil, communicative rationality (1989: 15–16). Of course, that they use the same literature as Habermas, and Kratochwil, at least, quotes Habermas’s work approvingly, does not necessarily mean that these authors—or other constructivists who share their intellectual concerns—are Habermasians (see Kratochwil 1987: 304). Nevertheless, it does make it difficult to draw any hard and fast lines between them and other critical theorists who have followed Habermas’s communicative turn. Moreover, if the argument is accepted that the only common theme among the disparate strands of critical IR theory is a concern with emancipation—and I readily acknowledge that this is a big if and that others, including contributors to this volume, will almost certainly wish to set more exclusive or demanding criteria for entry into the critical camp—then it is hard to see how Wendt, for example, might be excluded if (another big if!) he chose to identify himself as a critical theorist. True, his description of his project as involving a commitment to “emancipation and science” will certainly grate with almost all self-identified contemporary critical theorists to the extent that science is still conceived of in traditional mainstream terms. But Wendt is surely correct to argue that his formulation is roughly analogous to that employed by the Frankfurt School (Bonß 1993 provides a most insightful discussion; see also Dubiel 1985). And at any rate, Wendt, like the many of his constructivist colleagues (see Price and Reus-Smit 1998), is apparently well aware of the arguments of contemporary critical theorists—and other postpositivists—that theory as well as practice (of the early Frankfurt School, among many others) suggests that when normative concerns are simply bolted on to analysis conducted according to the principles and precepts of positive social science, the presumptions as to what constitutes knowledge underpinning the latter will eventually undermine the former. The question that both critical IR theory and constructivism have to face is how to move beyond this insight. Again, as Rengger’s discussion of Adorno suggests (Ch. 6 in this volume), there is no consensus among critical theorists as to how to answer that question.
Introduction
15
But to the extent that contemporary critical theorists eschew the Adornian “great refusal,” the kind of discussion that ensues is exemplified by Sandra Whitworth’s thought-provoking meditation (in Ch. 9) on fieldwork. This is also an issue where proponents of critical IR theory can benefit from the work of the constructivists, even if the claims by Price and Reus-Smit (1998) that critical theorists have failed to “produce the goods” in terms of empirical work are overstated (cf. Linklater 1996b). Thus there are clearly overlaps—and striking ones at that—between the key elements in the constellation of critical IR theory and the equally central elements of constructivism. Moreover, to the extent that some constructivists seek to illuminate the question of emancipation in and through the study of world politics, it is valid to consider their work as part of the broad constellation of critical IR theory. As Wendt’s insightful discussion of emancipation (in Ch. 13) indicates, they have much to contribute to the enterprise.
What Is Critical International Relations Theory For? This chapter has stressed the heterogeneous nature of critical IR theory by identifying distinctive and, indeed, contradictory strands within it and has posited an apparently minimalist definition of what unites these strands, namely, a concern with the question of emancipation. It has gone on to underline the commonalities between elements in the constellation of critical IR theory and elements in the constellations of poststructuralism and constructivism. Given this, it is legitimate to ask what purpose critical IR theory serves in the study of world politics. Would anything be lost if critical IR theory simply dissolved with elements being absorbed into other constellations? Habermasians, for example, might like to consider a future that provides some normative backbone for constructivist IR relations theory. All this is rendered especially piquant not so much for the essentially trivial reason that international relations has more than its fair share of competing paradigms and approaches but because the study of international political economy is increasingly being constituted as a discipline separate from international relations. If this trend continues—and given that increased specialization (and atomization) is one if the most baneful manifestations of the domination of positivism in the social sciences, this seems likely—Gramscian critical theory may well become progressively more detached from the other strands of critical theory. To reiterate, would anything of value be lost should this occur and the constellation of critical IR theory disintegrate? My answer is most definitely yes, and this for at least two reasons: The first relates to what critical IR theory already contributes, namely a focus on emancipation; the second to what it can potentially con-
16
Introduction
tribute in the future, that is, a forum in which attempts can be made to bridge the gap between the productivist and communicative paradigms. To elaborate, this discussion has highlighted that although concern with emancipation may well be compatible with forms of constructivism and is almost certainly implicit in poststructuralism, it is foregrounded by neither. Even such stalwart defenders as Price and Reus-Smit are forced to concede that constructivism has provided little in the way of normative direction, and poststructuralist IR theory has, generally speaking, failed to move beyond denaturalization and deconstruction to the kind of reconstructive politics that a concern with emancipation eventually requires. By relentlessly focusing on the question of emancipation and by questioning what this might mean in terms of the theory and practice of world politics, critical IR relations theorists are playing a currently irreplaceable role. It is also important to recognize that by focusing on emancipation, critical theorists (of all strands) are setting themselves extraordinarily demanding targets. Implicit in the orientation toward emancipation—in the recognition, after Marx, that the point is not only to understand the world but to change it—is that it is “in the crucible of practice that critical theories meet the ultimate test of vitality” (Fraser 1989a: 2). For critical theorists, therefore, the ultimate criteria by which the adequacy of a theory is measured is extradisciplinary. Thus it is all too easy for the concern with emancipation to fall by the wayside, especially given that the disciplinary mainstream is quick to measure alternative approaches by its own standards of adequacy (as evidenced in Checkel 1998, among many others), and some alternative thinkers are apparently more than willing to adapt to the criteria set out for them (witness, for example, the extraordinarily conciliatory way in which Price and Reus-Smit [1998: 282–283] respond to the demands that Checkel seeks to place on constructivism). To orientate theorizing toward emancipation is, necessarily, to raise a series of difficult and intractable questions concerning audiences and agency. The question is not just, after Wendt, What is international relations for? but also, Who is it for? and, How can a process of dialogue with that audience be initiated? Craig Murphy (Ch. 4 in this volume) is almost certainly correct in arguing that critical IR theory has supplied less convincing answers to these questions than previous manifestations of the democratic impulse in the study of world politics. In all honesty, proponents of critical IR theory have barely begun to ask them (for an attempt to think through some of the issues involved, see Wyn Jones 1999: ch. 6). Nevertheless, it is only the orientation toward emancipation that renders these questions worth asking in the first place, and it is precisely that orientation that critical theory can and does bring to a consideration of world politics. The argument for the continuing importance of critical IR theory as a broad project also spans metatheory and matters of more immediate practi-
Introduction
17
cal and political import and concerns the potential of critical IR theory to act as a site in which the insights of the paradigms of communication and production can be better integrated. Nancy Fraser (1995) has argued lucidly that contemporary political struggles are conducted along two main axes, redistribution and recognition. Redistributionary struggles are concerned primarily with issues of economic welfare. They form the arena of “class struggle” (a phrase whose very quaintness is eloquent testimony to the success of the theory and practice of neoliberalism since the early 1980s). Struggles for recognition involve attempts by members of various groups—identified by sex, sexuality, race, national identity, language, and so on—to gain justice as members of those groups. These latter types of struggle are often considered to be a more recent phenomenon than old-fashioned redistribution politics—there are regular references in the literature to the rise of identity politics. Those of us who, for example, inhabit the Celtic periphery of the British Isles might beg to differ from this analysis. Be that as it may, the point I want to emphasize here is that there is a tendency in critical theory (and, I think, social theory more generally) to analyze and understand these two different types of political struggle through two different metatheoretical paradigms. Work conducted through the paradigm of production—that is, the paradigm that underpins the Gramscian and Horkheimerian strands of critical IR theory—tends to focus on redistributory struggles. Work based on the paradigm of communication—Habermasian critical IR theory, for example—is concerned with questions of identity and community. The fundamental problem is that neither paradigm is adequate for the task of understanding the problematique of the other. The arguments as to why identity cannot simply be reduced to questions of productive relations have been well rehearsed by feminists and many others. Very few would now argue that patriarchy, racism, and the domination of one nation or linguistic group by another are simply the epiphenomena of particular sets of productive relations that would somehow disappear should those relations be swept away or fundamentally reconfigured. Neither, by extension, can these phenomena be understood solely through focus on relations of production and political economy more generally. (This is not, however, to suggest that such an analysis could not shed important light on these issues—merely an argument that they reveal nothing like the whole story.) Arguments as to why work conducted through the communicative paradigm (as it is presently understood) is inadequate to the task of understanding redistributionary struggles—and the emancipatory impulses that are undoubtedly a key element within them—have been heard less frequently (but see Honneth 1982, 1994, 1995b; Postone and Brick 1993; Calhoun [1995] even questions the usefulness of Habermasian theory for
18
Introduction
understanding particular manifestations of the politics of identity). They are, however, no less compelling. Briefly, Habermas in his “reconstruction of historical materialism” has distinguished between work and interaction and argued that the locus of humanity’s emancipatory potential lies in the latter and not (as Marxists have understood) in the former (a sphere that Habermas regards as being dominated by instrumental rationality). Thus Habermas and his followers have tended to bracket questions relating to work (political economy) and have concentrated instead on exploring interaction through the development of the theory of communicative action. However, to view relationships of work solely in terms of instrumentality seems unwarranted reductionism (Wyn Jones 1999: 62–63). Moreover, even on Habermas’s own terms, it is apparent that economic structures have major distorting effects on the process of communication. Yet the social theory that Habermas has attempted to develop on the basis of his theory of communicative action has no way of analyzing the causes of these distortions or any concrete suggestions as to how they might be overcome beyond a commitment to the continuation of the welfare state in the West (global inequalities are something of a closed book). It is striking in this regard that democratic theory developed in the Habermasian vein has abandoned all hope of fulfilling the old left project of extending democracy into the economic realm. Cognizance of the need to bridge the gap between both paradigms abounds. Linklater, for example, stresses the need to yoke the “defense of dialogue” to a critique of asymmetries of wealth and power, and Cox recognizes the need to move beyond a focus on class-based identities (in Chs. 2 and 3, respectively). The question remains, however, How, theoretically speaking, is this to be accomplished? Some critical theorists working in the field of social theory have begun to work on this problem. Axel Honneth, working from the basis of the communicative paradigm, is attempting to refocus critical theory onto the intuitive expectations that human beings have in any social encounter that “they receive recognition as moral beings and for their social achievements” (1994: 262). His work, and in particular his Struggle for Recognition (1995b), involves a self-conscious attempt to bridge the work-interaction divide. Moishe Postone (1993), working from a productivist standpoint, has attempted to recast the Marxist concept of labor (in a way he regards as more faithful to the meaning deployed in Marx’s own work) so that it moves beyond a focus on instrumentality to include also those features that Habermas has separated out under the heading of interaction. These developments are welcome, and they should surely continue. My own hope is that they can be echoed within the constellation of critical IR theory. Indeed, for both theoretical and pragmatic reasons, it seems to me that critical IR theory forms an ideal site for an attempt to begin a dialogue
Introduction
19
between those working in both paradigms. Both “sides” recognize the need for such a dialogue and, crucially, recognize themselves to be part of the same intellectual project. Moreover, one of the most pleasing aspects of the critical move in international relations has been its open, undogmatic quality, and as such the dialogue will almost certainly prove to be fruitful. But even more fundamentally, the most striking feature in contemporary world politics is the rapid increase in global inequality. For the poor and defenseless the results are nothing less that cataclysmic. And yet despite this, those forces that resonate to the progressive democratic impulse are apparently catatonic. With very few exceptions, the left has little to offer. It has no credible alternative to an inhuman and environmentally catastrophic global economic order, no way beyond the most transient of linking different particularized struggles concerning issues of identity, and no conception of how to link or synthesize elements on the axes of recognition and redistribution to facilitate the development of a broader progressive politics. Although bridging the gap between the paradigms of production and communication can play only a very small part in answering some of the very difficult questions that those committed to emancipatory politics currently face, it is an important and necessary task, and proponents of critical IR theory have the opportunity to make a significant contribution. Critical IR theory may well have already helped to disrupt some of the complacency of professors of international relations, but that achievement, such as it is, pales into absolute insignificance beside the challenges that it—that we— face in the real world of world politics.
Notes I would like to thank Ken Booth, Tim Dunne, Eli Stamnes, and Michael Williams for their perceptive comments on earlier drafts of this chapter. My thanks also to Maja Zefuss for her advice. All the usual disclaimers apply.
PART ONE THE CONTOURS OF CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY
2 THE CHANGING CONTOURS OF CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY Andrew Linklater
When Frankfurt School critical theory first made its mark on the study of international relations (IR) in the early 1980s, the terms of the debate were narrower than they are today. At that time, the advocates of critical theory were mainly concerned to refute the principal arguments of neorealism. Drawing on Marxian themes, critical perspectives offered an account of the nature of social inquiry with explicitly normative goals; they proposed modes of sociological inquiry oriented toward enlightenment about, and emancipation from, unnecessary constraints. Unsurprisingly, given the intellectual debt to Marxism, much of the analysis criticized global inequalities of economic and political power. Critical theory started from the paradigm of production and, in so doing, reflected the influence of the broad problematic, but not the detailed argument, of the neo-Marxian analyses of global dominance and dependence, which enjoyed their greatest influence in the late 1960s and early 1970s. A robust alternative to the neorealist analysis of immutable geopolitical imperatives was built on these theoretical foundations (Ashley 1981; Cox 1981). Critical theory has not stood still in the intervening years, but the nature of its foundations has been keenly debated since the mid- to late 1980s. As a result, Frankfurt School critical theory no longer represents the main challenge to orthodoxy within the field. It is important to recall that members of the first generation of the Frankfurt School criticized the paradigm of production over a half-century earlier and that Adorno, in particular, foreshadowed some of the more recent moves to the paradigm of identity and difference (see Coles 1995). However, the parameters of the debate have shifted even more dramatically in the past decade. Postmodern critical theory, which has taken the initiative in developing the paradigm of identity 23
24
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
and difference, does not try to reconstruct historical materialism or to complete the emancipatory project as defined by Western Marxism, although it is worth noting Derrida’s observation that strategies of deconstruction proceed in the spirit of Marxism (Derrida 1994). But far from championing that project, postmodernism is generally thought to challenge or problematize the conceptions of enlightenment and emancipation favored by those who belong, however loosely, to the Marxist tradition (Devetak 1996a, George 1994). Above all else, disputes surrounding the project of modernity or the project of the Enlightenment have transformed the disciplinary debate (Devetak 1995). A great deal has been written in the wake of Foucault’s writings about the extent to which modernity contributes to the progress of human autonomy or simply reconfigures social confinements and constraints; and much has been written about how far the language of critical social theory—universality, rationality, autonomy, progress, enlightenment, and emancipation—actively empowers the marginalized or sows the seeds of new structures of social power and political domination. Postmodern responses to these questions strike at the heart of many of the aspirations of critical theory within the broadly Marxian tradition, although they also aim to uncover and criticize the dark side of modernity. Most of the key issues in these debates have been thrashed out in a series of encounters between Habermas and his critics. These debates continue, but as Foucault argued early on, it would be erroneous to assume that one must be either for or against the project of the Enlightenment (Rabinow 1986). The more Marxian of contemporary writers do not dispute this point. Habermas is reported to defend an “enlightened suspicion of the Enlightenment” in which partial redemption from the dark side of modernity remains possible, but all notions of historical finality and completion are abandoned (Roderick 1986: 134). There are some parallels here with Foucault’s project, which defended local rather than globalizing critical projects and was ever mindful that everything may not be bad, but everything is potentially dangerous (Rabinow 1986: 343). Those shifts within radical thinking indicate that the classic pretensions of Marxian critical theory, including the belief in irreversible and unilinear progress toward the fully autonomous society, have been cast aside. An awareness of the ambiguities of modernity, which has its origins in Hegel’s reflections on the modern state and revolutionary terror and in Marx’s writings on industrial capitalism, is pronounced across the critical spectrum. From that premise, the goal of critical theory is to release the progressive side of modernity from stifling constraints. But the critical project forgoes the assumption that practices of liberation are innocent or unambiguous and guaranteed to remove rather than reconstitute the forms of power; it dispenses with the
The Changing Contours
25
perfectionist supposition that the project of modernity or the Enlightenment could ever be finalized or brought to completion. Different forms of critique occupy some common ground; arguably, they have more in common with each other than with the perspectives they oppose. Even so, one of the major achievements of postmodernism is to invite all perspectives to reconsider their standpoint from the ground up. Accepting that invitation, the following argument considers the legacy of critical theory that reflects Frankfurt School concerns and borrows from the ethical and cultural forms of Western Marxism rather than from Marxist political economy. Following previous discussions about the nature of the approach, the aim is to consider the normative, sociological, and praxeological dimensions of the critical-theoretical enterprise (Linklater 1992a, 1998). A comment about each of these domains is in order before proceeding further. The normative realm refers to the nonarbitrary principles that can be used to criticize existing social practices and to imagine improved forms of life; the sociological realm refers to the analysis of the historical development of these principles in past intersocietal systems and in the contemporary society of states; the praxeological realm considers the moral capital that has accumulated in the modern era and that can be exploited to create new forms of political community. The argument seeks to explain how critical theory continues to evolve beyond the paradigm of production to a commitment to dialogic communities that are deeply sensitive about all forms of inclusion and exclusion—domestic, transnational, and international. A post-Marxist critical theory of this kind can build upon the normative, sociological, and praxeological dimensions of classical Marxism without perpetuating its theoretical fallacies or generating its political consequences and dangers.
The Normative Domain The observation that there are no disembodied cognitive subjects who can acquire objective knowledge of external reality is a crucial theme running through all critical standpoints, and the related contention that knowledge invariably has a political purpose has acquired considerable prominence in recent years. The critique of neorealism, whether critical-theoretical, postmodern, or feminist, attacks its assumption that theory can provide objective knowledge of an immutable reality to which rational subjects should resign themselves. The immutability thesis, it has been argued, imputes properties to anarchy that truly belong to its constitutive parts, the more powerful of which have sufficient power to modify the dominant patterns of political interaction and principles of association, should they so wish
26
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
(Wendt 1992; Linklater 1995a). One consequence of this weakness is that international relations theory contributes to the reproduction of asymmetries of power, wealth, and opportunity. Put differently, notions of immutability conspire against those who have already lodged serious complaints about the injustices and deficiencies of the prevailing world order. All branches of critical theory have been keen to stress this important theme. A high level of self-consciousness about the nature of the relationship between the subject and the object, accompanied by the ambition to overcome the limitations inherent in problem-solving approaches to allegedly unmovable structures, is one thread uniting the different critical standpoints. Where to go from here is the intriguing question, and critical theory has been internally divided about the appropriate response. The early stages in the development of critical international relations theory reflected the influence of Marx’s vision of the whole of humanity associated in a universal society of free and equal producers. Whether that vision assumed that the main tendencies of modernity were universalizing and homogenizing need not detain us here. Suffice it to add that although Marx was notoriously vague about the place of the nation in the future socialist world order, he clearly believed that socialism represented the beginning rather than the end of history. This was the point at which greater individual creativity would distinguish the emancipated society from all previous forms of life. Objections to this conception of history and progress are far from new. Various nineteenth-century writers, including Mikhail Bakunin, argued that deeply exclusionary properties resided at the heart of Marx’s project of universal emancipation. Their main objection was that romantic images of the industrial proletariat already contained the possibility of new forms of state domination of marginal groups, a criticism that Marx and Lenin’s disparaging view of the peasantry did nothing to dispel. More recent radical perspectives, including postmodernism and feminism, renew this assault on projects of universal emancipation, noting how various conceptions of abstract universalism have contributed to the subjugation of non-Western peoples and the long exclusion of women from the public realm. Whether any notion of ethical universality and project of universal emancipation survives these criticisms is a point to return to in a moment. What has been clearly established in the critical literature is that some, but not necessarily all, forms of ethical and political universalism may be just as exclusionary as the arrangements they criticize. Recent critiques of universality are intimately linked with the greater awareness of unjust exclusion that shapes the politics of all contemporary societies. Many current political struggles contest the ways in which the development and reproduction of social bonds rest on and require systems of unjust exclusion. Much contemporary critical theory endeavors to
The Changing Contours
27
answer the question of how systems of exclusion should be legitimated. Far from attempting to reconstruct ethical universalism from some Archimedean point (a project that has been almost universally abandoned), critical theory reflects on the tests to which all modes of exclusion— domestic, transnational, and international—should be subject. At the forefront of these discussions is the normative commitment to create more openly dialogic social arrangements. An important shift beyond Marxist critical theory is evident in this development. It is well known that Marx and Marxism were preoccupied with the critique of class-based exclusion anchored in the unequal distribution of ownership of the means of production. Post-Marxist critical theory has enlarged the scope of the inquiry to include all known forms of unjust exclusion. It has been concerned not only with the plight of subordinate classes but with the overlapping forms of exclusion experienced by women, minority nations, and the racially and culturally different, including indigenous peoples. Invariably, critique proceeds by challenging hierarchies of class, culture, ethnicity, gender, sexual identity, or race that have been granted a natural status. It emphasizes that it is society or at least its most powerful groups that impute this power to nature and alienates social power and agency to natural processes. A central feature of critical theory is this assault on efforts to naturalize all modes of social exclusion that disempower members of subjugated groups. The critical project aims to demonstrate that some of the differences among human beings do not have the moral relevance that they have been assumed to possess, and often by the disempowered as well as by hegemonic groups. A primary moral goal is lifting “scope restrictions,” in which morally irrelevant distinctions based on class, gender, race, or ethnicity are used to deny groups access to the rights the privileged already enjoy (Bernstein 1995: 193). Whether reliant on genealogical techniques or the method of immanent critique, different forms of critical theory aim to deprive these systems of legitimation of their traditional authority and sacrosanct status (Hoy and McCarthy 1994). Efforts to make morally irrelevant differences between human beings central to social life might have failed had those whose interests were harmed in consequence been in a position to contest these suppositions in unconstrained dialogue, and systems of unjust exclusion will be that much harder to introduce in the future if the legitimacy of social practices is decided in open tribunal. Many different schools of critical theory imply at the very least that decisions about morally relevant differences among persons cannot be decided by those who stand to benefit most from them. The upshot is that all modes of exclusion have to be tested in dialogue that is open to the included and excluded alike. Habermas’s account of undistorted communication is the most frequently discussed example of this perspective. His approach endorses the view that all conceptions of ethics that
28
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
assume the existence or possibility of an Archimedean point from which it is possible to derive some substantive and universalizable conception of the good life have dissolved into thin air. What survives the critique of substantive visions of the good life, according to Habermas (1990a, 1993), is a rational normative commitment to the universal procedures of the ideal speech community. Many who take this standpoint subscribe to a conception of dialogue that is in principle open to all human beings, that accepts the prima facie equal legitimacy of all claims, and that proceeds on the assumption that in true dialogue, no one can be sure of who will learn from whom—these being central elements of Habermas’s discourse theory of morality. But what many reject is the supposition that these normative commitments can be grounded in some universal conception of communicative action or linked with the belief that the unity of the whole species was already anticipated by the first speech act. Habermas has often been criticized for positing the ideal of a fully transparent and homogeneous society, but many of his formulations defend modes of communication that affirm the right to radical otherness and argue that the first test of universalism is the seriousness of its commitment to deep diversity as a normative ideal (Habermas 1992a: 240). There is much to be said, in consequence, for Richard Rorty’s observation that “merely philosophical differences” separate the foundationalists from the postfoundationalists (Rorty 1989: 67). It is arguable, without trivializing the importance of these differences, that the different strands of contemporary critical theory share similar conceptions of the virtues of dialogic communities and the preconditions of their successful existence. The belief that the legitimacy of systems of exclusion ought to be decided in open dialogue is the common ground. Allegiance to this ethical goal is apparent in certain forms of feminism that reveal a Habermasian influence, as Seyla Benhabib’s defense of “post-conventional contextualism” or “interactive universalism” reveals (Benhabib and Cornell 1987: ch. 4; Benhabib 1993: 151, 163–164). It is just as evident in the feminist commitment to a dialogic communitarianism that affirms the solidarities and sentiments that bind social groups together while denying that tradition and convention can be immune to the scrutiny of open dialogue (Frazer and Lacey 1993). Though far removed from Habermas’s defense of ethical universalism, Jean-François Lyotard’s support for equal rights of participation in a universal speech community strikes a remarkably similar chord to the Habermasian conception of undistorted communication (Lyotard 1993). Similar trends are evident in, or compatible with, Foucault’s claim that he was not for consensus but “anti anti-consensus” (Rabinow 1986), as well as in postmodern writing influenced by the work of Mikhail Bakhtin (Der Derian 1994). There are also similarities with Hans-Georg Gadamer’s
The Changing Contours
29
philosophical hermeneutics, which celebrate conversation as the means by which the radically different can enter into one another’s worldviews and fuse cognitive horizons without merging identities or assimilating otherness within dominant perspectives (Shapcott 1994). Minor philosophical differences aside, these approaches share a broadly similar conception of the dialogic ideal. In authentic dialogue, as Lyotard has argued, one speaks only inasmuch as one listens, and in a related passage, he suggests that dialectical discourse in the Platonic sense may not escape the operation of power (Haber 1994: 42; Lyotard and Thebaud 1985: 4). The crucial question, Rorty has suggested, is what it would mean to take part in unconstrained communication (Rorty 1991: 634). Habermas raises similar concerns by admitting that his earlier notion of ideal speech is misleading because it suggests that unconstrained dialogue could exist in practice (Habermas 1994a: 102, 112–113). The relevant conclusion is that authentic dialogue can never be anything other than an ideal to be aimed for, a goal that can be approximated, because there may always be forms of exclusion that human beings have still to discover. They could never be sure they had reached the end of history and that all systems of unjust exclusion or constraints on human autonomy had been identified and removed. One of the more important implications of these comments about authentic dialogue is that it is insufficient simply to remove scope restrictions on participation in dialogic arrangements. Removing indefensible restrictions grants additional parties an equal right to participate in the speech community, but it may not secure equal respect for all the positions brought before the tribunal of open dialogue. As the sociologist Benjamin Nelson, put it, authentic dialogue requires the radical expansion of permissible expressions and disagreements (Nelson 1973). Increasing access to participation involves the eradication of systems of exclusion based on morally irrelevant differences among human beings; but this is not the same as concluding that the differences between them do not matter at all. The essential point, which various writers on gender, ethnicity, and indigenous peoples have advanced with considerable sophistication, is that often those who belong to systematically excluded groups have no desire to be included in the political community on exactly the same terms as everyone else (Kymlicka 1989, 1995; Phillips 1993). Demands for group-specific citizenship rights and local autonomy often express this point particularly well, since they show that the drive to universalize certain rights may represent significant progress for some groups but fail to address the concerns of those for whom securing the public recognition of their cultural differences is the primary concern. From the latter perspective, progress toward universality by conferring the same legal and political rights on all members of society constitutes limited progress beyond unjust exclusion. Still more
30
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
radical measures require advances in the public recognition of cultural diversity that may take the form of the devolution of political power or the creation of group-specific rights. The commitment to dialogue therefore requires communities that are more universalistic and more respectful of human differences than they have been in the past: It requires the development of societies that regard the differences between human beings as less important than their shared experience of pain and suffering (Rorty 1989: ch. 9). No less important is the need to ensure that these communities do not efface human differences in the search for agreement and understanding (Habermas 1994a: 120). Support for this dual process of development spans the different branches of contemporary critical theory that affirm the dialogic ideal. Interestingly, and conceivably in response to the postmodern defense of diversity, Habermas has suggested a preference for understanding as opposed to emancipation, which is best reserved for describing personal biographical developments (Habermas 1994a: 104). Limiting the concept of emancipation to the personal domain may not be the best move to make, and in a more compelling formulation, Karl-Otto Apel has described the project of emancipation as “the progressive implementation of the standard of ideal communication and nonrepressive deliberation” (Apel 1979: 98–99). As previously noted, progress in this direction involves the lifting of scope restrictions and greater sensitivity to radically different worldviews. But it also requires collective efforts to create a more equal distribution of power and influence; otherwise, greater access to the speech community simply grants individuals and their associations formal rather than substantive rights. For this reason, the thin morality that substitutes the defense of open dialogue for classical efforts to define a universalizable conception of the good life is, in Michael Walzer’s words, already “pretty thick” and laced with substantive content (Walzer 1994: 12). An account of the ethical procedures specific to the dialogic community does not extend very far unless it links up with the neo-Marxist critique of asymmetries of wealth and power (Apel 1980: 283; Cohen 1990). The defense of dialogue that is so pronounced across the critical spectrum is incomplete without this emancipatory component in which the basic ethical aspirations of the Marxist tradition are reaffirmed (see also Derrida 1994). Critical theory in the Marxian mode has been opposed because its project of universal emancipation is host to totalizing potentials. Efforts to reconstruct that position have culminated in the case for a procedural ethic that abandons the quest for some global conception of the good life, but universalistic commitments in the form of lifting restrictions on access to the speech community remain central to the critical project. In response to postmodern and feminist critiques, the normative focus of contemporary critical theory reveals a greater sensitivity to radical differences, realizing,
The Changing Contours
31
perhaps belatedly, that this is one key to an improved universality. Retaining the Marxian critique of the asymmetries of power and wealth is the remaining side of the triangle. The normative aim of critical IR theory can therefore be summed up in this way: It is to increase the spheres of social interaction that are governed by dialogue and consent rather than power and force; to expand the number of human beings who have access to a speech community that has the potential to become universal; and to create the socioeconomic preconditions of effective, as opposed to nominal, involvement for all members of that community.
The Sociological Domain The discussion thus far is a reminder of the extent to which the recent history of the discipline has been shaped by complex philosophical discussions, but not every member of the profession welcomes these developments with enthusiasm. Some responses to the critical turn lament the level of abstraction, even obfuscation, and invite critical scholars to produce useful social analysis (Wallace 1996; see also Halliday 1996: 325; Mann 1996: 221). From the time Robert Keohane introduced the distinction between reflectivist and rationalist approaches to the subject, postmodern writers have borne the brunt of this criticism (Keohane 1988). Complex questions about what counts as a strong empirical research agenda arise at this point, but they must be passed over here (Walker 1989). Nor is this the appropriate moment to compile an inventory of the postpositivist contribution to recent sociological analysis. Perhaps it is sufficient to add that a complete inventory would doubtless include the studies of the “doors to otherness,” in Taylor’s felicitous phrase, which have been closed because of the assumed moral relevance of racial, ethnic, gender, or civilizational differences (see Taylor 1985). Related to this, a substantial literature has appeared about how the West forged its “civilized” identity through a series of negative contrasts with non-Western peoples and about how national identity has been created and national purposes sustained through similar exclusionary practices (Dalby 1990; Campbell 1992, 1993). Writers within the Marxian tradition, particularly the neo-Gramscian school, have brought a sophisticated political economy to bear on the analysis of world order and global hegemony (Cox 1996a). The many different tendencies that constitute the postpositivist turn are also evident in the project of reworking security studies from the ground up (Krause and Williams 1997). Others have enumerated many of these empirical developments in some detail, and there is no reason to retrace their steps here (see George 1994; Devetak 1996a, 1996b). The main point is that even a brief analysis of the evolution of the empirical research agenda over the past fif-
32
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
teen years reveals that contemporary critical theorists have no reason to apologize to the allegedly more empirically minded for any failure to deliver concrete analysis. As noted earlier, postpositivist empirical research agendas do not purport to offer objective accounts of an external reality, but they have an explicitly normative and critical purpose. The question then arises of what kind of sociology should flow from the normative aspirations set out in the preceding section. It was noted there that the normative content of critical theory supports removal of the barriers to the equal enjoyment of rights, greater respect for radical differences of worldview, and efforts to reduce material inequalities. The point of these measures is to create new forms of community that increase access to dialogic arrangements and encourage what Fraser calls “parity of participation” for all members (see Cochran 1996). Whether modernity has the resources with which to make substantial progress in this direction is a question that can be deferred until the next section. What can be stated with some confidence at this stage is that visions of a universal speech community have not existed in all societies; they are the outcome of complex patterns of social development that have frequently been spurred on by political resistance and violent social conflict. What is equally clear is that the project of developing a sociology that traces these developments has barely begun and that it raises questions that go beyond conventional sociological analysis. As Anthony Giddens has argued in a different context, mainstream sociology was committed to an unfolding conception of social change in which little or no attention was paid to exogenous forces or to their complex interplay with endogenous factors (Giddens 1985). Frankfurt School social theory has not been immune to these traits, as Habermas’s schematic overview of the course of social evolution reveals. The “empirical philosophy of history with an emancipatory intent” that Habermas defends scarcely mentions international relations and their part in promoting or delaying progress toward a universal communication community (Linklater 1990a: postscript). A sociology that corresponds with the normative commitments set out earlier must therefore move from the idea of society to intersocietal systems (without committing the neorealist error of abstracting the latter from their constituent parts). These systems include, inter alia, relations among groups that have been forced together within imperial modes of domination, intercivilizational relations, and international societies of states. Recent sociology contains important resources with which to take this neglected project further. Michael Mann’s account of the early empires of domination explains how they dismantled scope restrictions by permitting the elite members of subjugated societies to enter the dominant political class. But far from affirming radical otherness, the early empires simply
The Changing Contours
33
tolerated cultural difference, not least because they generally lacked the social reach or “intensive power” to assimilate entire subordinate cultures within the prevailing order (Mann 1986). Any vision of equal dialogue with the alien other would have been anathema to the members of the ruling strata, as would the ethical commitment to reducing material inequalities in order to create social arrangements in closer harmony with the ideal of a universal speech community. Similar themes appear in Nelson’s sociology of civilizational structures and intercivilizational relations (Nelson 1973). Breaking down some of the invidious differences between insiders and outsiders within their boundaries was one of the great achievements of the major world civilizations, in Nelson’s view. But non-Western civilizations, he argued, hardly developed dialogic potentials internally or in their relations with the rest of the human race. With their deep-seated assumptions about the moral significance of the differences between insiders and outsiders, those civilizations were committed to hegemonial conceptions of international society (see also Bull and Watson 1984). Societies of states provide an interesting point of contrast not least because a dialogic element is intrinsic to their nature. Hellenic international society, for example, possessed the institution of diplomacy, though not the idea of dialogue between equals, until quite late in its history (Wight 1977: 2–3). Modern visions of a speech community with the potential to become universal would have seemed an absurd proposition to the vast majority of the inhabitants of ancient Greece. Whereas conceptions of moral and political universalism emerged, they invariably assumed the superiority of Hellenic culture and the ideal incorporation of the alien other within its supposedly more rational worldview (Kristeva 1991: 59). Relations with Persia revealed the tension between the egocentrism of Hellenic culture and the pragmatic requirement to enlarge the diplomatic dialogue so that Persia was recognized as a different but equal member of international society (Wight 1977: ch. 3). What is more, the Greek city-states system, along with the intersocietal systems that predated it, did not develop an ethic of transferring power and wealth to subordinate groups to ensure parity of participation in a widening dialogic community (Resnick 1992). It is tempting to draw the conclusion that support for lifting restrictions on the equal enjoyment of political rights, for respecting the radically different and redistributing wealth and power to the members of systematically excluded groups, is greater in the modern era than in any past intersocietal system. This is a proposition that can be advanced only with serious qualification. Support for these principles has not always been matched by radical changes in practice, and, needless to say, it varies enormously within and between societies. Greater support has not occurred because modern societies are more clever than their predecessors but because in many respects they are as, if not more, oppressive and have engendered powerful
34
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
opposition to their negative properties and tendencies as a result. The seemingly unique qualities of modernity are evident in the achievements of modern citizenship, around which struggles to universalize rights, respect differences, and reduce inequalities continue to revolve. Modernity’s qualities are also evident in the recent development of the international society of states. Scope restrictions that prevented non-Europeans from gaining admission to European society have been lifted, at least for those groups with the power to constitute themselves as separate states. Advances in respect for cultural differences and progress in reducing material inequalities within many nation states have failed to stir collective action to reduce international inequalities, but it would be foolish to conclude that there had been no progress at all on these fronts. Arguably, the commitment to pacify the society of states without converting it into empire is a more pronounced theme in the modern society of states than it was in ancient Greece or China. Still more radical changes in the structure of international society are made possible by these normative commitments. These are conjectural statements that further research will either confirm or disconfirm. Whatever their long-term fate, some observations about the condition of modernity can be safely made. As previously noted, the progressive side of modernity is not the outcome of the unassisted development of reason but the product of political struggle against terrible forces. The main influences on Frankfurt School critical theory knew as much. Immanuel Kant’s observation that war had taught human beings by experience what the use of reason could have foretold, namely that their primary political goal ought to be association within a cosmopolitical association dedicated to promoting permanent peace, conveyed the essential point (Kant 1970). Hegel’s account of the dialectical interplay between the development of reason and the struggle for freedom in the face of arbitrary state power and the destructive effects of industrial capitalism reworked the crucial theme (Avineri 1972). Marx’s claim that the fate of human freedom depended entirely on the outcome of the struggle against capitalist exploitation was the version that defined critical theory for much of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Many of the most insightful trends within social and political theory continue this tradition by providing critical theory with a more profound understanding of the strange ambiguities of modernity (see Smart 1985). Again, this is one point where the different paths of Frankfurt School critical theory, postmodernism, and feminism intersect. Current efforts to reconstruct the sociology of the ambiguities of modernity include the literature on the unprecedented territorial concentrations of power that have emerged over the past 200 years. The relationship between this phenomenon and the struggle to acquire legal rights against the state and rights of representation and participation has been one of its central concerns, as has the analysis of the impact of warfare on the evolu-
The Changing Contours
35
tion of state power and on subsequent demands for citizenship rights (Giddens 1985). Accounts of the dialectics of capitalism in which new structures of social control and patterns of inequality compete with demands for welfare rights have enriched the sociology of modernity and its ambiguities (Giddens 1985, 1993). Inquiries into the relationship between state building, war and capitalism and the formation of, and resistance to, modern patriarchal relations and the dominant conceptions of sexual identity have transformed the analysis. The same may be said of explorations of the homogenizing effects of state building and capitalism and the parallel ethnic revolt and struggle for recognition by indigenous peoples. No inventory of the ambiguous qualities of modernity would be complete unless it included the relationship between industrialization and the various social movements committed to reconstituting dominant approaches to the natural environment and to nonhuman species. Those formulations emphasize the deeply ambiguous character of Western modernity: They reveal that unprecedented territorial concentrations of power, unparalleled violence against subordinate groups and alien outsiders, and more insidious forms of social control compete with unusual levels of social mobilization to resist multiple forms of political domination and social exclusion. Critical social theory stands at the intersection of these contrasting forces, which form the conditions of modernity’s existence. Its opposition to the dark side of modernity draws on the moral and political resources that constitute the progressive side of modernity and reveal that improved forms of political community may yet evolve. The thesis that postmodernity does not represent a break with modernity but rather a vital intensification of its radical, democratic potentials reinforces the point (Keane 1990: 91–92). Different strands of critical social theory have highlighted the multiple strands of exclusion that run through the structure of modern societies and their international relations; they have analyzed the variety of counterhegemonic forces that resist forms of domination and exclusion within the modern world system; in so doing, they have turned the dialogic elements and further potentials of modernity against its dark and oppressive forces. Some critics of the “new scholasticism” lament the paucity of concrete social analysis in contemporary critical theory (Wallace 1996), but the charge misfires. In a relatively short period, there has been considerable progress in rewriting the sociology of modernity to show how the seeds of alternative social and political arrangements are evident within existing forms of life. Right at the heart of this enterprise is the analysis of the dialectic of dialogue, difference, and exclusion. Those analyses of the properties of modernity need to be placed in a wider historical context that allows informed assessments about the extent to which different intersocietal systems developed conceptions of universal
36
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
dialogue that are sensitive to cultural differences and economic inequalities. The historical evidence suggests that different forms of world political organization exhibit different properties in this regard (Linklater 1998: ch. 4). To summarize, the first empires promoted selective advances in universality but remained deeply exclusionary and inegalitarian. Lifting restrictions on access to elite positions enabled egocentric cultures to administer sprawling empires, but hierarchical worldviews prevented any major breakthrough in the shape of egalitarian commitments to universal dialogue. Similar worldviews are evident in the relations among the major empires or civilizations. Imagining their association within a universal communication community that overcame the deepest forms of social exclusion rarely emerged as an ethical ideal. Movement to new structures of consciousness is evident in societies of states with their commitment to dialogue among their constitutive parts. Hellenic international society broke through the limitations of early empires, but hegemonic conceptions of international relations hampered the evolution of modern conceptions of the equality of states and clashed with the Kantian notion of a universal kingdom of ends. Ethnocentrism prevented the radical extension of dialogic commitments in relations with non-Hellenic societies, although some movement toward more universalistic structures of consciousness was evident in the gradual expansion of international society to include Persia. A preliminary survey of the historical evidence suggests that the vision of forms of political community that are more universalistic than their predecessors and more sensitive to cultural differences and material inequalities is a uniquely modern idea and an expression of the progressive side of modernity.1 It is not entirely fortuitous that this vision has emerged in a civilization that may be unique in attaching deep moral significance to differences of race; that has been as, if not more, assimilationist than past intersocietal systems; and that has been the site for the development of seemingly unprecedented inequalities of wealth and power. But modernity is not reducible simply to this dark side; whether it can create political arrangements that represent its progressive side is the crucial question.
The Praxeological Domain The complaint that the critical turn has forsaken concrete social analysis for indecipherable reflections about the foundations of human inquiry was noted earlier; the related lament is that postpositivism is annoyingly detached from vital questions of public policy and governance (Wallace 1996). Invitations to deepen the connections between postpositivist inquiry and current policy and practice are welcome—all the more so if they take up complex questions surrounding the relationship between theory and
The Changing Contours
37
practice, which have always been central to those working within the Marxist tradition. One recent critique of postpositivism fails to mention, even in passing, Cox’s important and influential distinction between problem solving and critical approaches to international relations (Wallace 1996). This distinction is an important reminder that sophisticated policyrelevant research must confront the question of which interests are privileged and which are conveniently ignored by the urge to address issues of current practice (Cox 1981; Booth 1997). Critical theories of all descriptions are especially alert to these considerations, which are at the forefront of a range of inquiries into policy matters, political structures, and alternative forms of human governance. Critical theory in the revolutionary Marxist tradition was concerned with large questions about current political structures and alternative modes of social organization rather than with incrementalist policy recommendations associated with revisionist solutions to the problems of modern capitalist society. But in more recent times, few would deny the importance of shuttling between long-range questions about the prospects for alternative forms of political community and shorter-term policy debates that determine whether societies evolve in the normatively preferred direction. The commitment to the discourse theory of morality, for example, necessarily combines grand visions of more dialogic cultures and human subjects with support for concrete measures (such as freedom of information) that will contribute to the realization of that goal. Approaches to current policy have to be linked, then, with longer-term normative objectives that link critical theory with classical political philosophy and its reflections on the good society and the good life. This is the specific domain of critical praxeology. Raymond Aron introduced the term praxeology in the course of his reflections on the antinomies of statecraft (Aron 1966: 577–579). He maintained that the tension between Machiavellian calculations of opportunity and the Kantian problem of acting ethically and securing progress toward universal peace is at the heart of foreign policy. Aron’s writings highlighted the allegedly unending struggle between the realist conviction that the purpose of foreign policy is to enhance national power and prestige and the idealist commitment that the function of foreign policy is to promote cosmopolitan goals. In so doing, he stressed the recurrent tension between the ethics of conviction and responsibility that Weber analyzed in the final sections of “Politics as a Vocation” (Weber 1948). These realist approaches to praxeology are at odds with the Kantian alternative in “Perpetual Peace,” which informs the argument of the present section. In “Perpetual Peace,” Kant recognized that the struggle for power and security could not be eradicated overnight but might be eliminated gradually in a process of international political change lasting several centuries (Kant 1970). Kant believed that the bitter experience of war had taught human beings the need to bring
38
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
civility to international relations. Greater economic interdependence also encouraged the widening of humanity’s moral horizons so that the concern for human dignity and human rights had begun to unite the whole world. In Kant’s writings, praxeology was concerned with the prospects for releasing the progressive side of modernity from superfluous constraints. The static representation of the tension between power and ethics that typifies classical realism gave way to a more complex analysis of the dynamic qualities of world politics. Kant’s critical approach to praxeology focused on the pressures that had compelled human beings to humanize their international relations and on the specific measures they could take in the future to make world politics comply with their highest ethical ideals. Central to the approach is how the tension between the different sides of modernity can be resolved by the gradual accumulation of just international norms. The moral capital that accumulates in the struggle against unnecessary constraints checks the recovery of the politics of power and force, but it also creates the possibility of further advances in the politics of dialogue and consent. Compliance with these norms is essential for the reproduction of society, and serious violations of these norms create considerable public alarm and provoke significant political opposition. The integrity of these norms also requires the restructuring of social arrangements when they are found to clash with important ethical commitments. Important aspects of this process have already been discussed. Lifting scope restrictions so that the members of subordinate classes could enjoy the legal and political rights monopolized by dominant groups was part of a larger process in which systematically excluded groups contested the moral relevance of their differences from full-fledged citizens. Efforts to universalize legal and political rights triggered political discontent when dominant groups failed to deal with profound economic inequalities. Such measures have been regarded as deficient by groups that do not wish to have exactly the same rights as all other citizens but desire special rights and entitlements that recognize their cultural distinctiveness. The accumulation of norms therefore serves the dual purpose of preventing the recovery of pernicious systems of exclusion and enabling further development and movement. In modern societies, the concept of citizenship performs this dual role. The moral capital invested in citizenship is the product of resistance to territorial concentrations of power, to national-assimilationist policies designed to curb national minorities and secessionist tendencies, and to the social inequalities resulting from the transition to the industrial era. The struggle for citizenship has focused on lifting barriers to the enjoyment of equal legal and political rights, but it has also sought advances in welfare rights and the establishment of group-specific rights in response to the politics of cultural recognition. Citizenship rights provide a barrier against the
The Changing Contours
39
reemergence of past forms of unjust exclusion, and they are a vital element in the collective memory of earlier struggles to remove them. These rights are a key moral resource that progressive social forces continue to exploit in contemporary efforts to reconfigure political community. They ensure that a culture of sensitivity to unjust exclusion remains important to a significant proportion of the citizenry of modern societies. Whereas a realist account of praxeology stresses the tension between these normative commitments and the logic of power, a critical approach focuses on the higher possibilities that they build into the structure of modern societies. From the latter point of view, the moral capital invested in citizenship is not in a state of permanent tension with the logic of anarchy but confirms the Kantian theme that these societies possess the moral resources for narrowing the sphere of social interaction that has been ceded to the dominion of force and power. Universalizing suffrage by dismantling scope restrictions has been an intriguing feature of modern societies, all the more so because of the coexistence of deeply embedded particularistic norms that deny aliens representation and voice. Most societies have assumed that the distinction between insiders and outsiders has obvious moral relevance, at least as far as the right of democratic participation is concerned. Increased opportunities for and incidences of cross-boundary harm pose the question of whether the differences between insiders and outsiders are any more morally relevant than the distinctions of gender, class, ethnicity, and race. A profound moral contradiction arises for democracies that cause harm to outsiders by polluting their environment and endangering their health. The logic of their moral beliefs requires them to widen the boundaries of democratic government so that insiders and outsiders come together as associates in joint rule. Proponents of cosmopolitan democracy have offered a cogent defense of this argument, and the growth of regional organizations and the emergence of a global civil society encourage the belief that the history of democratic governance is entering a new phase of development (Archibugi and Held 1995; Held 1995; Archibugi, Held, and Kohler 1998). It is abundantly clear that national commitments to citizenship have already generated powerful arguments for creating a transnational democracy in Europe. Interestingly, these visions of expanded democracy often stress the need to devolve power to domestic regions and local communities. Most of them do not predict the end of the nation state, but they anticipate new forms of political community in which significant national powers are shared with substate and transnational institutions, and national loyalties exist alongside stronger subnational and transnational allegiances (Camilleri and Falk 1992; Meehan 1993; Beiner 1995; Turner 1993). Thus the moral capital that has been accumulated in the struggle against unjust exclusion is more than a way of preserving past achieve-
40
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
ments; it can also be used as a resource for creating new forms of political community and citizenship that institutionalize the dialogic ideal in a more complex ensemble of democratic public spheres. Praxeology in the Kantian tradition considers the implications of normative analyses of the highest ethical ideals and sociological explorations of the ambiguities of modernity for matters of current policy and practice. Significantly, praxeological inquiry considers large-scale questions about the possibility of new forms of human governance and reflects on the more important developments that can help realize this ideal. Visions of the modes of governance that ought to appeal to societies with deep moral commitments to citizenship are combined with critical reflections on the concrete measures that deserve support. The latter include the right of individual appeal against the state not only in national but in European courts; the international protection of minority rights; the devolution of power to domestic regions; and the development of richer conceptions of European citizenship that embrace legal, political, and welfare rights (Linklater 1996a). The recent critical or postpositivist turn has not attempted to shift the study of international relations away from issues of current policy and practice toward the higher reaches of detached philosophical analysis. One of its central ambitions has been to recapture something of the ethical spirit that existed when the field first came into existence, and to do so without repeating the mistakes of early idealism. Very complex issues attend this process, and it is unsurprising that much of the recent literature has addressed them in their own terms and for their own sake in relative isolation from questions of current practice. Those who have taken these philosophical issues seriously have often abandoned the familiar territory of conventional international relations for the less familiar world of social and political theory, a necessary step if the field was to advance quickly. No serious understanding of the complexity of the issues involved could conclude that the theoretical retreat had gone far enough and was in danger of imbalancing the subject. A more profound assessment of the meaning of the critical turn would note how far it runs parallel with the wider literature on the prospects for new modes of human governance and new forms of political community. It is not possible to undertake a detailed examination of these parallel lines of investigation here, but for present purposes, it may suffice to comment briefly on some recent writings that envisage forms of political community that break the nexus between sovereignty, territoriality, nationality, and citizenship. In The Other Heading, Derrida defends a European polity that avoids the monopolization of power and its dispersal to the representatives of exclusive particularisms (Derrida 1992: 41). In The Past as Future, Habermas supports moves to transnationalize democracy and to invest authority in substate and transnational authorities in a more democratic
The Changing Contours
41
Europe (Habermas 1994a). In the study of international relations, a related strand of thought defends the rights of national groups to preserve their differences but not necessarily to constitute themselves as exclusive, sovereign entities (Elshtain 1994). A parallel development notes the connections between Hedley Bull’s heavily qualified support for a neomedieval Europe and the critical-theoretical defense of forms of political community that are more universalistic and more sensitive to cultural differences than most states have been in the past (Linklater 1996a). Numerous parallels exist with a range of recent commentaries on the future of the nation-state in Europe (MacCormack 1996, Wallace 1994). Here the philosophical defense of societies that embody higher levels of universality without effacing human differences is reflected in praxeological reflections on new forms of community and citizenship that reveal the potentials of modernity. These reflections about governance, which deal with the possibility of postnational or postsovereign societies in Europe, inevitably raise complex questions about how Europe should conduct its relations with the rest of the world. Fears that a postsovereign Europe might turn in on itself and purchase its own welfare and autonomy by imposing hardship on others have been emphasized in these discussions (see Derrida 1992: 9). The important point is that efforts to release the progressive side of modernity within Europe may generate, and even require, injustice for the members of nonEuropean societies. For this reason, the ambiguities of modernity may be only partially overcome. But as already noted, the culture of sensitivity to unjust exclusion is a major dimension of modernity, and all efforts to consolidate the achievements of national citizenship by creating a transnational citizenship in Europe provoke the concern that they may clash with cosmopolitan ideas. Recurrent attempts to give meaning to world or cosmopolitan citizenship reveal that the dark side of modernity has never succeeded in eradicating a powerful moral sense that national communities are answerable to the rest of humankind (Linklater 1998: ch. 6). The Kantian ideal that commitments to dialogue, publicity, and consent can gradually contract the dominion of power and force in international relations is as important now as it was 200 years ago. Apel’s defense of “the progressive implementation of the standard of ideal communication and nonrepressive deliberation” (Apel 1979: 98–99) restates the Kantian ideal, as does the notion of the universal speech community defended by Habermas and Lyotard. The more important formulations of this normative project maintain that political subjects should endeavor to make their actions compatible with what might be agreed upon within an imagined universal communication community, and they should support all measures that will help bring such a community into existence (Bohler 1990: 133). Pressures on the current frameworks of communication in international relations offer more concrete guidance to those who support this ideal. The
42
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
diplomatic dialogue in modern international history was long confined to states and concerned with preserving political order among the most powerful. These dimensions of world politics are undiminished in importance, although there are important moves to open that dialogue to nonstate actors, including the range of nongovernmental organizations, and to extend it to embrace issues of global governance including the rights of individuals and minorities, international social justice, and greater concern for the natural environment and for nonhuman species. Reflections on the current state of the diplomatic dialogue are one way of monitoring the extent to which international society is making progress toward or falling short of the ideal of a universal speech community from which no voice is excluded and from which no dissenting perspective goes unheard because of political weakness or the absence of respect. Such reflections on the current state of the dialogue can hardly lead to confusion about the most desirable trajectories of development and patterns of change, although it would be foolish to expect that they will either settle the most profound disputes about the best means of promoting change or solve complex disputes about who has most responsibility for initiating political action. Critical praxeology should aim to highlight the moral deficits of international society and to stress immanent possibilities and desirable directions. From there, it can begin to explore the relatively uncharted waters of critical foreign policy analysis.2
Conclusion Few efforts to develop connections among social theory, moral and political philosophy, and the study of international relations existed even by the early 1980s. Resistance to exploring these connections was commonplace, not least because of realist arguments that the violent conflicts of the century had crushed the project of the Enlightenment. Dissenting voices were heard from various liberal or socialist standpoints that retained their faith in the idea of international progress. They prepared the way for the more systematic assault on realist and neorealist thought that has taken place since the mid-1980s. In the early stages, critical approaches reflected the influence of Marxist conceptions of society and politics. These approaches questioned many of the classical Marxian assumptions about the demise of nationalism, the epiphenomenal character of the state, and the nature and possibility of world socialism. But they were not exposed at that time to the radical challenges of postmodernism and feminism. They were equally critical of the conventional theory and practice of international relations, but they were deeply troubled by perceived similarities between realism and its
The Changing Contours
43
critical opponents. The totalitarian potentials residing within universal histories and global projects of emancipation were among the chief concerns. The intriguing question is where this leaves the tradition of critical theory with its Marxian commitment to creating an overarching perpective that unites normative, sociological, and praxeological modes of inquiry. Many have doubted the wisdom or possibility of recovering a project of modernity that holds on to these convictions. Perhaps they are right to do so, although this is not the conclusion drawn here. What has been proposed instead is an approach to critical IR theory that remains universalistic while recognizing that some forms of universalism have wished to submerge or extinguish the difference of the other. Here it is essential to stress that various accounts of the universal speech community are explicitly concerned not only with tolerating difference but with enlarging human diversity. They have a normative commitment to dialogic relations in which human beings can explore the possibility of forms of life simultaneously more universalistic and more diverse than preceding arrangements at the domestic and international levels. They invite further sociological studies that consider the condition of modernity with all its tensions and ambiguities in the broadest historical perspective, and they call for additional praxeological inquiries that reflect on how the progressive side of modernity can be embodied in new forms of political community that continue the struggle against all forms of unjust exclusion. Historical awareness is a central feature of critical theory, which recognizes that all categories and perspectives have to be amended, even abandoned entirely, as societies change. Contemporary critical IR theory in the Marxian tradition has not lost sight of this basic truth. Its changing contours are evident in its attempt to rebuild the project of modernity around the themes of dialogue, difference, and exclusion.
Notes 1. It is important to note some similarities here with the English School, which stressed the tensions between the dialogic element in systems of states and their exclusionary practices (see especially Bull 1977, 1983; Bull and Watson 1984; Wight 1977). For the purpose of exploring these issues in more detail, the English School is a convenient point of departure. 2. Critical foreign policy analysis can reflect on existing policy decisions and alternative possibilities in the light of the normative commitments and sociological observations discussed in this chapter. The latter would need considerable refinement in any detailed commentary on specific policy options.
3 THE WAY AHEAD: TOWARD A NEW ONTOLOGY OF WORLD ORDER Robert W. Cox
One recurrent criticism of critical theory in international studies is that it has yet to deliver a substantive research agenda. Working from the general to the particular, the criticism goes in its broadest sense to the question of ontology. How do we describe the sphere of reality within which our study seeks to focus on the important issues? My initial proposition is that international relations (IR) is an inadequate and misleading way of describing the object of our search for knowledge. The institutionalization of a discipline in university departments, academic posts, and funding is one thing. There is no harm in this endeavor so long as we keep an open mind about what the term international relations may cover. My point is that the term gives a distorted impression of what should be included. What’s in a name? A rose by any other name . . . But let us focus on the rose without, at least for the time being, trying to rename it—and thereby raising all the issues of material subsistence and institutional rigidity that will come in their time. There are two meanings of ontology. The primary meaning is an affirmation of the ultimate reality of the universe—what we can call Universality I. This meaning probably has its roots in monotheistic religion and was taken over in secular form by the European Enlightenment. Human beings invent the idea of God as the all-powerful creator; from that they reverse the process of invention to assume the human mind to be Godlike, that is, to have the potential for understanding the truth of the universe.1 Universality I can take the form of affirmation of the kind of truth embodied in religious revelation or in the certainties of Enlightenment philosophy. It can also, in a spurious form, apply to affirmations of universality that are manifestly products of a particular historical situation but not recognized to be such for lack of critical self-appraisal. Neorealism is a good example. 45
46
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
The other meaning of ontology—which we can call Universality II—is the attempt to identify the basic constitutive factors that help toward understanding and acting upon a particular historical conjuncture. We could say the task is one of perceiving the historical structures that characterize an epoch. These structures, which are mental constructions, summarize the cumulative result of collective human action over time. The purpose of defining them is to construct a base point for considering the problems of maintenance or transformation of a particular historical order. Universality II is universal in a transitory way, the snapshot of a world in perpetual motion, the synchronic picture of something that is diachronically changing. A synchronic picture cannot be a mere list of factors. To qualify as ontology, it has to show the interactive properties of a system—albeit an open system in which the homeostatic mechanisms that maintain closure can be disrupted by forces that open the way for change. Neorealism has an explicit ontology—a perverse form of Universality I—in which states, balance of power, Hobbesian power-seeking man, and the contractual basis of polity are presumed to be eternal interrelated components of world order. Critical theory has relativized neorealism so as to perceive it as an ideology of the Cold War. In a more positive sense, critical theory has envisaged a shift in ontology toward a more adequate depiction of the “real world” of the twenty-first century; so far this alternative ontology is only a work in progress. My aim here is to try to grasp the directions of ontological reconstruction that will give a proper weight to factors ignored by neorealism but that are relevant to understanding power relations affecting conflict, cooperation, and prospects of human survival. Because ontological shift both reflects and anticipates structural change, it is also important that the effort focus on the forces of agency that are capable of reshaping structures consolidated from the past. This inquiry into structure and agency is undertaken in a spirit of realism. Realism is concerned with power; but the questions, Where does power lie? and How is it exercised? should be asked without any prior assumptions about the answers. Neorealism starts with the assumptions previously mentioned. Its ontology forecloses a broader search. The realism of E. H. Carr, who initiated the modern study of international relations at the University of Wales, Aberystwyth, had a much broader and more open understanding of power in world affairs. He was sensitive to economic and social structures and to culture and ideology. He saw states not as a series of like entities (the state) but as historically differentiated forms. Returning to Carr’s realism is a first step toward escaping from the ahistorical confines of neorealism. Unfortunately, however, Carr’s reputation as a realist among students of international relations has come to rest mainly on his Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939 (1946). His essay Nationalism and After
The Way Ahead
47
(1945) better illustrates his broad understanding of economic, social, and ideological transformation shaping the nature of states and of world order. Much of the rest of his work, The Romantic Exiles (1949), for instance, and his studies of Marx, Bakunin, and Dostoyevsky as well as his essay What Is History? (1964) and his multivolumed history of the Soviet Union, demonstrate the breadth of his approach. There has already been a good deal of work toward expanding neorealism by adding markets to states in the conventional ontology. But even this is not a sufficient answer to the problem of where power lies in the early twenty-first century. A Marxist might justifiably argue that states and markets are just two forms of alienation. The first displaces human responsibility to an artificial construction, the state. The second displaces human relations to relations among things in the market. Underlying each of these constructs are social relations, the human substance that is active in these two spheres. Really existing social power relations are the fundamental object of inquiry. We may therefore begin by examining the way social relations are being reshaped on a global scale by tendencies in the global political economy, especially since the world economic crisis of the mid1970s. I see four interrelated configurations that define the “real world” of the early twenty-first century: (1) the social structure of the world as it is being reshaped by economic globalization; (2) the pattern of change in states and the state system; (3) humanity in the biosphere; and (4) the subjective (or better, intersubjective) aspect of world order, or the different understandings that different categories of people have about the nature of world order.
The Changing Social Structure of the World The term globalization is so widely and diversely used that some clarification of my use of it here is called for. In my usage, globalization has an economic connotation. Bernadette Madeuf and Charles-Albert Michalet (1978) drew a distinction between the international economy (understood in classical economic theory as flows of goods, payments, and investments across borders) and an emerging form of economy in which production was being organized on an integrated basis among entities located in a number of countries. The English translation of their article, which was written in French, referred to the latter as a “world economy,” just as the common French term for the process generating this emerging economy was mondialisation. The more common English-language term for this process has been globalization. Hence, I am using global economy to denote this emergent phenomenon. Of course, much of the world’s economic activity still
48
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
goes on outside this global economy, albeit increasingly constrained by and subordinated to it. I reserve the term world economy for the totality of economic activities of which the global economy is the dominant part. The policy impetus behind the formation of the global economy is neoliberal globalization; I have called its ideology hyperliberalism. The global economy was initially perceived in the sphere of production associated with transnational corporations (TNCs), but the deregulation of financial operations quickly followed and led to the globalization of finance, which, as in the Asian financial crisis of 1998, has manifested a destructive potential in relation to production and employment. The impact of the globalization process on power relations in societies, among states and social forces, and in the formation of institutions designed to entrench the global economy or to stimulate resistance to it is the realm of global political economy. The globalization of production is producing a three-part social hierarchy that is worldwide, cutting across state boundaries. The proportions of the three levels in society vary from one territorial unit to another, but the tendency is uniform throughout. The top level comprises those people who are integrated into the global economy. This stratum runs from the global economy managers in public and private sectors to relatively privileged workers who serve global production and finance in reasonably stable employment. The second level includes those who serve the global economy in a subordinate and more precarious way. They are the potentially disposable labor force, the realm of “flexibility,” “restructuring,” “downsizing,” and “outsourcing.” This level is a consequence of the phenomenon known as post-Fordism, the organization of production on the basis of a relatively permanent core of people concerned with planning, technology, marketing, and finance, and a peripheral group whose employment depends on the level of demand and production decisions made by the core group. Employment of this kind is expanding in the industrialized countries as the proportion of stable employment in industry declines, and it characterizes most industrial jobs in poor countries. The bottom level comprises those who are excluded from the global economy. Here are the permanently unemployed, superfluous labor, the underemployed, and many of the people living in what one former commissioner of the European Union, Claude Cheysson, called the “useless” countries (cited by Cheru 1997: 213, 221), that is, those countries that have little prospect of making a go of the global economy. The top level is doing quite well in material terms, although it is only a small proportion of humanity. The second level is the one that is expanding most rapidly with the geographical extension of globalization and with the growing penetration of the social structure of globalization into the economically leading countries. Its members are placed in an ambiguous posi-
The Way Ahead
49
tion toward the social order: They are supportive in their concern to find and keep a job but potentially hostile when insecurity strikes. The excluded pose a potential threat to the globalization order. But certain conditions may diffuse that threat: the fact that excluded people’s energies are directed to personal and family survival rather than protest and the proclivity of rejected people often to direct their violence against their excluded neighbors rather than against the established society. Nevertheless, the potential for challenge to the globalization order exists among both the excluded and the precarious segments. There are also contradictions among the integrated, many of these generated by ecological concerns that affect jobs in forestry, fisheries, and energy industries. The challenge to globalization, if it is to become activated, would require the formation of a common will, a vision of an alternative future, and the transcendence of the manifold divisions of ethnicity, religion, gender, and geography that cut across the three-level social hierarchy being created by globalization. This restructuring of world society brought about by globalization challenges the primacy of state-oriented identities as people become aware that transnational economic organizations determine their livelihood and populations become increasingly heterogeneous from migration. It also challenges the Marxist schema of the primacy of class-oriented identities. The nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century concepts of class have been muddied by the emerging social structure. The working class as it is conventionally thought of is now divided among the three levels of the social hierarchy, and these three components can be shown to have very divergent interests. Where the sense of class remains strong today, it may be more a cultural matter than defined by a property relationship. Yet the concept of class retains vigor and calls for reformulation in early-twenty-first-century conditions as a means to the formation of a common front of resistance toward an alternative to the future that is being prepared by globalization. Class would have to embrace comprehensively the various identities—ethnic, religious, gender, and so on—manifested by those groups that have initiated pockets of resistance.
States and the State System Since the fall of the Berlin Wall, interstate relations have tended to become more concerned with adapting state structures, policies, and practices to the requirements of a global economy conceived on neoliberal lines rather than toward the alliance building of the Cold War period. The dominant theme proclaimed by the United States and widely acquiesced to by the other major countries has been “democracy and market reform.” The slogan has
50
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
been applied specifically to countries of the former Soviet sphere and also to countries in what was formerly called the third world. The primary emphasis of dominant power has been on the market reform aspect, which in practice has been held to mean deregulation and privatization accompanied by measures to combat inflation and to achieve and maintain currency stability. The practical consequences have been the gutting of public services, increased unemployment, and rampant corruption. The democracy aspect has meant an emphasis on elections in the hope that they will legitimate market reform and on human rights in the sense of individual rather than collective rights. The cumulative consequence of these pressures has been to propagate the idea that the primary function of states is to adjust domestic economic practices to the functional requirements of the neoliberal global economy. I have called this process the internationalizing of the state (Cox 1987: 253– 265). It contrasts with the post–World War II concept of the state as mediator between the international economy (understood as flows across national boundaries) and domestic concerns about economic growth and employment. According to the newly dominant doctrine, domestic interests are best served by allowing free rein to the global economy, and new efforts at regulation, such as those embodied in the World Trade Organization (WTO) and the proposed Multilateral Agreement on Investment (MAI), are designed to limit the capacity of states to interfere with the working of the neoliberal global economic order. In terms of social relations, the global economy is led by and benefits mainly the top segment of the world social hierarchy just discussed. This segment, the integrated, is both inside and outside the state. It is outside the state insofar as it is embodied in agencies like the Group of Seven (G7, or now G8 with the inclusion of Russia) and the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and the WTO, or even in such unofficial conclaves as the Trilateral Commission and the World Economic Forum, which meets annually in Davos, Switzerland. It is inside the state insofar as the interests that are represented in these bodies are present within different countries and can put pressure on states at the national level. At the interstate level, two main functions are performed: First is the propagation and legitimization of neoliberal global economic practice by international institutions, mainly the IMF, the World Bank, and the WTO but now increasingly the UN itself. The UN used to be differentiated from these international economic agencies, which have operated clearly within a neoliberal logic, being seen as more open to the expression of heterodox views about world economy, particularly in the interest of less-developed countries. However, the success of the United States in securing the election of Kofi Annan as Secretary-General after excluding Boutros BoutrosGhali from reelection indicates a shift in the UN toward alignment with the
The Way Ahead
51
IMF and WTO policy orientation. The new Secretary-General seems to be moving toward centralizing budgetary control, which the United States has always sought, and giving fuller access to multinational corporate interests in the formation of UN policy. The second function at the interstate level is the neutralization of potential disruptions of the global economy that could arise from explosions among the bottom (excluded) segment of the world social hierarchy. Global poverty relief and riot control now tops UN priorities, displacing development assistance, which had the top spot during the 1950s and 1960s. Poverty relief takes the form of humanitarian assistance in the wake of famine and internal warfare, much of which can be seen as consequences of globalization. Riot control takes the form of military interventions where local governmental authority has broken down.
The Biosphere Alongside social restructuring, environmental degradation is an accompaniment to economic globalization. The conventional study of international relations has heretofore recognized only human actors, but in recent years some nonhuman forces have appeared, threatening to constrict the realm of human action: global warming, the hole in the ozone layer, deforestation and soil erosion, the loss of biodiversity, and the collapse of fish stocks, among others. These forces express the response of nature to the cumulative consequences of human activities. They are new phenomena that signal dangers to the physical environment in which human activities take place. They can lead to conflict, for example, over scarce vital resources such as water, and they challenge accepted modes of understanding humanity’s place in the world. Monotheistic religions with their notion of a transcendent deity encouraged a separation of human beings, the image of the divine, from nature, created by God for the use and enjoyment of humans. Scientific modernism inherited this idea in conceiving nature as something to be dominated, tamed, and shaped by human beings. The irruption of forces of nature into human affairs, not as the occasional flood or earthquake but as a deterioration of the planet’s life-support system, now suggests the need to revise this notion by seeing humanity as one component of the natural world, interacting with other forms of life and life-sustaining substances. The biosphere is this larger interactive realm, an envelope circling the earth and stretching from the seabeds to the higher atmosphere. In the modernist tradition, economics reduced nature to land and considered land a commodity (what Karl Polanyi [1944] called a false commodity, since land is not produced for sale on the market). Nature has been subordinated to economic logic, to the market mentality, which is based on
52
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
the proposition that everything is for sale. The basic problem for market logic is getting the prices right. Nature, however, has a logic of its own that is not comprehended by economics and that functions independently of economics. The basic problem for nature’s logic is equilibrium among the different forms of life and life-supporting substances. So long as there is enough slack in nature, market logic is tolerated by nature; but when the effect of economic logic is to strain nature to the limit, nature responds with its veto (Harries-Jones, Rotstein, and Timmerman 1992, 1998). The problem here is to rethink economics within a science of nature so that economic prescriptions are attentive to signals from nonhuman nature. This rethinking implies a departure from the modernist epistemology that separates human capacity for knowledge from the world of nature and conceives nature as a manipulable object. The dilemma for humans now is to think through the consequences of understanding ourselves as part of nature rather than as dominant over nature. One implication of this understanding is a fundamental contradiction in economic globalization and perhaps also in movements of democratization. The dynamic of globalization is consumer demand. The consumption model of North America and Western Europe—consumerism—is what the other peoples of the world have aspired to. To extend this model universally would likely have catastrophic consequences for the biosphere, but to suggest that relatively poor societies should drop this aspiration incurs the charge of imperialism. It seems obvious that those societies that have pioneered the quest of consumerism would have to show the way toward an alternative model that would be consistent with biosphere maintenance. This is where the challenge to democracy arises. Former U.S. president George Bush anticipated it when, in preparing for the Earth Summit at Rio in 1992, he was reported as saying: “Our lifestyle is not open to negotiation.” He was implicitly acknowledging that change of lifestyle is necessary to biospheric survival and at the same time recognizing that political survival in modern democracies makes change highly risky for politicians to advocate. If such a basic change in people’s aspirations and behavior cannot be changed by political leadership, let alone by exhortations at international conferences, the change must come from within civil society. The issue then becomes whether the reconstruction of people’s understanding of their place in nature and of what is necessary to maintain the biosphere can outpace and reverse the progress of ecological degradation.
Intersubjectivity: Civilizations and Forms of Political Economy The problem of the biosphere brings out the relationship between objective material conditions (ecological degradation) and subjective, or, more accu-
The Way Ahead
53
rately, intersubjective, understandings and values of people (consumerism versus ecologically responsible behavior). By intersubjectivity, I mean the prevailing sense of the nature of the world, or the common sense of reality shared among a population. Intersubjectivity can be understood as the knowledge produced in the cumulative collective response by people to their conditions of existence, to what Marx called the conditions not chosen by themselves within which people make history. Thus intersubjectivity is a creation of history, not something innate to the human soul, although in its unquestioned state it may appear among contemporaries to be an innate awareness of the natural order of the world. It is in the realm of intersubjectivity that civilizations become significant for world politics. The materialist connotation of the term civilization signifies an urban-centered aggregation of a large number of people such as came into existence circa 2500 B.C. in the Nile valley, the Fertile Crescent, and the environs of Mohenjo Daro (cf. Childe 1942). This material, technological, economically organized, and class-structured entity called civilization was unified in the realm of consciousness or subjectivity by religion. It is common nowadays to call civilizations by the names of religions— Judeo-Christian, Confucian, Islamic, and so forth. Religion enabled people within a civilization to develop a shared consciousness and symbols through which they could communicate meaningfully with one another. Myth, religion, and language were coterminous until language became secularized and rationalized. The material world provided a common ground of experience; religion provided a common realm of intersubjectivity. So a working definition of civilization could be a fit between material conditions of existence and intersubjective meanings (Cox 1996b). This definition does not imply a base-superstructure relationship in the sense that common material conditions generate similar ideological superstructures in a “vulgar Marxist” manner. One can attribute more autonomy to the realm of intersubjectivity while positing a necessary correspondence, or what Max Weber called “elective affinity,” between thought and material conditions of existence. The challenge of material conditions may be confronted in different ways in different forms of consciousness expressive of different values. The material limits of the possible are constraining, but there is always some scope for ethical choice. Feminist scholarship has been particularly fruitful in developing this notion of the social construction of reality. Feminists use it as a means of revealing the historical genesis of patriachy and specific categorizations or stereotypes of gender, but the insight has other applications as well. In the world of the early twenty-first century, civilizational differences are expressed through different forms of economic and social organization. This fact has been obscured both by dogmatic forms of Marxism and by dogmatic neoliberalism, both of which cling to an economic determinist philosophy, an oversimplified reductionist view of capitalism as a mono-
54
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
lithic global force. In one sense capitalism is, of course, a global force: Big corporate organizations based in different parts of the world compete for shares in a world market, and finance flows freely across territorial boundaries. But people in different places are organized in somewhat different ways, not only mainly to participate in this global capitalism but also sometimes to exist outside of it. These differences are important for the people who live within different coexisting forms of capitalism. Thus we can speak in one sense of global capitalism as the dynamic force of globalization; but at the same time, it must be recognized that capitalism, the competitive drive for profits and expansion, takes different social forms shaped by different civilizational imperatives, some of which place limits on unconstrained profit seeking. Concepts of society and organization can express different notions as to what is natural and proper in human relations. These differences cannot be reduced just to a matter of ideology. Ideologies are conscious constructions with specific programs. Intersubjectivities are less conscious and more deeply rooted, the common sense of a people as to what is right and proper in collective life. Karl Polanyi’s concept of substantive economies is a way of seizing these differences within the more abstract notion of global capitalism. Polanyi was concerned with the ways in which economies were embedded within societies (Polanyi 1944; Polanyi et al. 1957). He rejected the notion that the economy can be abstracted from society in such a way as to make society subservient to the economy. Where this is attempted—he spoke of the nineteenth-century attempt to impose the rule of a self-regulating market as a utopian project—it provokes a reaction from society that is usually expressed through political action. In Europe, the reaction began with labor legislation and ultimately led to the welfare state. Utopian projects are still current; the most obvious is the hyperliberal attempt to construct a deregulated global market. But other distinctive forms of economic-social organization also exist, and rival forms contest the terrain on which hyperliberalism has claimed predominance (see, for example, Albert 1991). Three salient existing forms of political economy are (1) the AngloAmerican individualistic-competitive form, (2) the European social market form, and (3) the East Asian mercantilist form (Fallows 1994; Tsuru 1993). Each of these has generated ideologized representations. Hyperliberalism is the ideology of the Anglo-American form, envisaging an untrammeled global movement of goods and money. The social market is the characteristic European form, ideologically derived from Christian democracy and social democracy. Asian capitalism has been constructed, often with attribution to Confucianism, as an ideology supportive of authoritarian politics or bureaucratized paternalism. Yet the forms are more deeply rooted than these ideologies; they can be seen as constructions that find a more or less
The Way Ahead
55
congenial base in different human attitudes and values—different intersubjectivities. There is scope for other potential forms of political economy to emerge. What will happen in Russia? The consequence of shock therapy has been erosion of public services, mass unemployment, frequent nonpayment of workers, and an economy controlled by the mafia. Russia’s tragedy has been its people’s subjection to a sequence of alien-inspired radical reforms, first by Peter the Great, then by the Bolsheviks, and now by Harvard economists. Is there a possibility that even so patient a people as the Russians may ultimately reject foreign models and attempt to build their economy based on their own practices of social relations? In China, a new form of political economy is emerging, rather confusedly described as both communist and capitalist yet gradually revealing its own characteristics (Ling 1996). Is it conceivable that Islam will evolve practices that reconcile its principles of human relations with economic activity in an evolving vision of the world? Another force lies in the Green movement, which has given rise to many small, locally based economies with cooperative forms of production and their own currencies (Helleiner 1996). These social experiments may perhaps be seen as an indicator of the search for economic practices that are consistent with biosphere maintenance. These different forms of political economy that express civilizational differences coexist within the world economy and in some cases become rivals. They challenge the notion of a single hegemonic, homogenizing global economy. Lionel Jospin, when the French Socialist Party emerged as victor from the French legislative elections in June 1997, characterized this electoral verdict as “un choix de civilisation” (Le Monde, June 7, 1997). He was stressing a break with the tendency toward dominance of the AngloAmerican form in Europe and the resurgence of the social market form of political economy. The use of the term civilization was appropriate in that context. The victory of Tony Blair’s New Labour Party in British elections several weeks earlier was celebrated not as a rupture with previous tendencies but rather as a change within continuity, heralding what might be called Thatcherism with a human face. The issue between rival concepts of civilization in Europe remains clouded.
Agency in Structural Transformation The distinction between agency and structure is an analytical distinction rather than a distinction of kind. Structures are ways of representing the world as it is. Agency focuses attention on the forces that change structures. Agency, in the sense in which I use the term here, represents cumulative
56
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
actions—not just a single event—that have as consequences either the maintenance or the transformation of structures. We can divide the forces at work into those that operate from the top down, which tend to maintain the trajectory of existing power relations, and those that operate from the bottom up, which may challenge existing power relations. There are also contending forces within the top, and rival and divergent forces at the bottom. Hegemony consists in the formation of a coalition of top-down forces activated by a common consciousness in which those at the bottom are able to participate. Counterhegemony arises when bottom-up forces achieve a common consciousness that is clearly distinct from that of hegemonic power. So a strategy of structural transformation may be seen as a project for the formation of counterhegemony. There is no need to attempt a full inventory of the top-down forces that maintain existing power positions and power relations. I shall mention three sets of forces that I think call for fuller study. The first is the mode of concertation of the dominant world-economy forces. This process takes place through some formal official organizations and conferences (e.g., the G7 meetings, the IMF, the Basel meetings of central bankers) and some less formal conclaves (e.g., the Trilateral Commission, the Davos World Economic Forum), although the important thing is not to identify an organization or an organizational complex but to understand the process through which collective policy guidelines are reached. Because this process is only vaguely delineated, I have called it a nébuleuse (Cox 1996c: 301–302; 1996d: 27).2 A second area that merits much fuller study is the private power that is effective in world financial markets. The bond-rating agencies are a good example of actors that effectively determine the conditions on which governments and corporations can borrow and thus what activities they can undertake and what they must forgo (Sinclair 1994, 1997). A third set of forces have the cumulative consequence of sustaining existing power and can be loosely described as involved in political corruption and clandestine activities. I would group these under the heading “the covert world” and examine particularly the interrelationships of the various kinds of agents in the group. It includes intelligence agencies, organized crime and the drug trade, money-laundering banks, the arms trade, and terrorist organizations. It may seem strange to include terrorist organizations committed to destroying the existing order among a set of forces that have the consequence of maintaining the status quo, but they work in the same field as these other agents and at times interact in cooperation as well as in conflict with them. Although there have been studies of some of these components of the covert world individually, for example, of organized crime and of particular intelligence agencies (the CIA or the KGB), the pattern of interactions among such agencies and their consequences for political sys-
The Way Ahead
57
tems have not received much attention. Yet this realm of political activity has great implications for popular control. A weak civil society leaves a wide political space for occult influences. Probably the best way to enhance democratic accountability is to narrow the space open to the covert world through the development of an active civil society. Struggles shaping different forms of capitalism illustrate the divergent and conflicting tendencies among top-down forces: differences between the United States and Japan over economic practices; the conflict over social policy in Europe, epitomized once as Margaret Thatcher versus Jacques Delors; conflicts over who has the right to harvest depleted fish stocks. These conflicts are indicators of the problematic nature of global capitalist hegemony and of the potential for the emergence of a world of not one capitalism but several. I am not here referring to economic blocs or the socalled triad of rivals: Europe, America, and Japan. I am referring rather to different basic concepts of social economy and the ethics of how production and distribution should be organized. Such different concepts have historical-geographical bases but are not necessarily unified or coherent entities engaged in a trade war. The bottom-up forces are many and various but have rarely achieved a degree of coherence that could plausibly be considered a basis for counterhegemony. The prospect for counterhegemony is, however, the focal issue for the study of structural transformation. The French strikes of December 1996 were notable not only in rallying workers despite the weakening over recent decades of the labor movement but also in gaining the sympathy and support of a public that was willing to put up with a shutdown of public transport in a big city in the cause of combating an economic policy perceived as sacrificing ordinary people in favor of dominant global-economy interests. A comparable effort at mobilizing opposition to the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA) was initiated by labor movements in the United States, Canada, and Mexico with the support of women’s and environmentalist organizations. This effort failed but did demonstrate a degree of political efficacy. Increasingly, new social movements have become the vehicles of protest and means of prospecting for alternative forms of social economy. They have only partially been directed toward the state and have rarely operated through formal electoral channels. They express more a will to reconstitute civil society, and in some cases to construct what Yoshikazu Sakamoto has characterized as a “civic state” on the basis of a strengthened civil society—a state that would be more fully responsive to the bottom-up forces of civil society. This would be the direction in which one could envisage a society that could reestablish harmony within the biosphere. It must be recognized that this aspiration remains utopian. One intriguing model is presented by the Zapatista rebellion in the Mexican state of
58
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
Chiapas, which is seeking to transform itself from a military-political rebel movement into a broader-based movement in civil society that is directed toward the democratization of the Mexican state while building transnational links of support (Najman 1997). Other movements of resistance, very widespread in Africa, have sought survival of excluded groups through organization outside the political system and the formal economy. This form of resistance has been called the “silent revolution” in Africa (Cheru 1989). The collapse of the kleptocratic state in the former Zaire was effected by organized military rebellion, but the way was made easier by the widespread development of local self-help and the informal economy, which deprived the corrupt Mobutu regime of any popular support (Braeckman 1997). The study of social movements has thus become basic to an understanding of the potential for structural transformation. Three levels or stages apply: (1) the level of conditions propitious for awareness of being in a common situation, a sense of opposition toward dominant powers; (2) the level of a social movement, that is, a condition of aroused and motivated collective consciousness; and (3) the level of organization that poses the questions of alliance and cohesion among groups, of doctrine and ideology, and of leadership. It should not be assumed that all social movements are supportive of democratic methods and open comprehensiveness. The contemporary world is rife with racism and right-wing populism; the possibility of a fascist revival is probably stronger now than at any time since the 1930s. Such undemocratic organizations are as much popular movements as those usually classified as new social movements. Civil society is a terrain of struggle between exclusionary and nonexclusionary forces. The context in which this struggle is taking place seems to leave the outcome indeterminate. If modernism in political terms can be defined à la Max Weber as consisting of states that define the national identities and loyalties of people, hierarchical rational bureaucratic administrations, and classes and status groups that give people their social identities, this modernist social structure has become weaker in all parts of the world (although more weak in some parts than others). State authority has been fragmented by ethnic, linguistic, and local identities and by macroregional institutions like the European Union and NAFTA. Bureaucracies have been experienced as alienating by those who have to deal with them. Class identities have been eroded by the growing salience of ethnic, cultural, and gender identities and by the fragmenting of classes in the new social structuring produced by globalization. People have become depoliticized by awareness that politicians are incapable of dealing or unwilling to deal with the consequences of economic globalization as it affects their lives through decaying public services
The Way Ahead
59
and unemployment, and by evidence of political corruption that flows from the high cost of election campaigns and the importance of political decisions for corporate interests. The postmodern political condition is one of weakened and fragmented authority at the top and fragmentation of protest and resistance at the bottom. Occasionally, the latter may be overcome by a (usually unsustained) explosion of “people power.” Eric Hobsbawm summed this up when he wrote in his Age of Extremes: A History of the World, 1914–1991: “The world at the end of the Short Twentieth Century is in a state of social breakdown rather than revolutionary crisis” (Hobsbawm 1994: 459). What is to be done? The only way effectively to confront the salient issues of the early twenty-first century—biospheric collapse, extreme social polarization, exclusionary politics—is to reconstitute political authorities at local, national, and global levels that are firmly based in public support. Only strong public authorities will be capable of dealing with these problems. Such a movement would have to come from the bottom, from a reconstitution of civil society as a support for political authorities attentive to people’s needs (whereas much of the movement in civil society recently has been toward withdrawal from alienating government and corporate powers). The movement presupposes the rediscovery of social solidarity and of confidence in a potential for sustained collective creativity, inspired by a commitment to social equity, to reciprocal recognition of cultural and civilizational differences, to biospheric survival, and to nonviolent methods of dealing with conflict. The supreme challenge is to build a counterhegemonic formation that would embody these principles; and this task implies as a first step the working out of an ontology that focuses attention on the key elements in this struggle.
Notes 1. Giambattista Vico, a philologist working in Naples in the early eighteenth century, may be regarded as the first countermodernist (neither a premodernist nor a postmodernist). It was very clear to him that the human mind was not adapted to understanding the truth of the universe. It was, however, he thought, well adapted to understanding the processes of historical change (Vico 1970). 2. I have sought to avoid imputing clandestine power to this partially visible, or transparent, complex: “The visible form is a photo opportunity accompanied by an anodyne press communiqué. Far from being a sinister occult power, the nébuleuse may turn out to be a Wizard of Oz. Perhaps no one, or no coherent structure, is really in control” (Cox 1996d: 27).
4 CRITICAL THEORY AND THE DEMOCRATIC IMPULSE: UNDERSTANDING A CENTURY-OLD TRADITION Craig N. Murphy
Contemporary critical theory in English-language international relations (IR) may best be understood as today’s manifestation of a long-standing democratic impulse in the academic study of international affairs. The impact of this impulse can account for scientifically progressive breakpoints within the discipline, the moments of transformation that are part of almost every conventional account of the field’s history—for example, the transition from idealism to realism in the period between World Wars I and II. Understanding critical theory in this way lets us compare today’s scholarship to that of earlier democratically inspired schools within the discipline; it allows us to ask whether today’s theorists have been as successful as their predecessors. Along most relevant dimensions of comparison, today’s critical theory is just as progressive as its three predecessors—the work of John A. Hobson and his colleagues in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, the interwar studies of realists on the left such as E. H. Carr and Reinhold Niebuhr, and the critical scientific peace research of the early 1960s. Nonetheless, along one significant dimension, contemporary critical theory may be less progressive than its predecessors. Unlike early scholars with similar political motivations and similar epistemological concerns, contemporary critical theorists have offered little programmatic input into the political practice of egalitarian social movements. In the final section of the chapter I speculate as to why. Before doing so I make the case that the history of the field can be understood through the lens of this hypothesized democratic impulse and then link earlier manifestations of this impulse to some defining intellectual practices of contemporary critical theory. 61
62
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
Egalitarian Concerns in International Relations When social science disciplines recount their own histories, it is almost invariably with the aim of explaining why some current disciplinary trend continues a line of scientific progress that has marked the field since its beginning. Within a field these accounts most often differ simply because there are different ways of defining the central concerns of science and therefore different criteria for assessing its progress. One of the most consistent stories that IR scholars can tell about their own field is that it has at its core a view of social science as a meliorative endeavor subject to a consensus theory of truth. In this story, scientific progress occurs along five relatively orthogonal dimensions. Thus, a progressive social science regularly produces explanations that 1. Account for more phenomena, 2. Are more consistent within themselves and with other scientific accounts of other phenomena, 3. Would be consented to more widely by all free men and women (men and women whose views are unconstrained by relations of domination or exploitation), 4. Empower the weak or otherwise ameliorate their condition, and 5. Are more concise, parsimonious, or elegant than other explanations. Although progress can take place along any one of these dimensions, they are listed in an order of relative importance that would be consistent with a meliorative, consensus-oriented epistemology (Tooze and Murphy 1996). Of course, there would be many who would argue with both the ordering of these dimensions of scientific progress and the inclusion of some, in particular the third and the fourth. Here I ask readers to accept only that these are five dimensions along which a consistent, academically credible account of social scientific progress might be made. In fact, they are the dimensions along which critical theorists following Jürgen Habermas are likely to judge scientific progress. They emphasize that the practical, meliorative dimension is as essential in social science as it is in medicine and that unconstrained consensus is an indicator of truth that is particularly significant to the social world (Habermas 1971: 75–90; McCarthy 1978: 303–307). Periodically there have been prominent schools of IR scholars who have judged the progress of their own scientific work along this set of dimensions. I contend that these successive schools reflect a democratic impulse operating within the field simply because the epistemological views of these schools can be distinguished most readily from those of their contemporaries by considering the two democratic dimensions, 3 and 4.
Critical Theory and the Democratic Impulse
63
Many other schools of scholars, let’s call them uncritical scholars or problem-solving scholars (to follow Robert W. Cox), separate any meliorative concerns they may have as citizens, religious devotees, and so on from judgments about the success of their work in what they conceive of as a value-neutral realm of social science. Many of the same scholars also see little reason to judge their work on the democratic basis of the breadth of the unconstrained consensus that it might enjoy. Quite the contrary, many understand the history of more mature sciences as evidence that true scientific progress may lead to a progressive narrowing of the intellectual caste that is capable of understanding the new truths as they are revealed. Despite the fact that an uncritical view of science often has been the one accepted by mainstream IR scholars, it is significant that the major progressive disciplinary changes that are recognized by almost all accounts of international relations were not wrought by these uncritical, problem-solving schools, no matter how much more conventional their view of scientific progress may be. The key changes were wrought by men and women who both wanted the discipline to speak to an ever wider audience and were certain that the field had a socially progressive, meliorative function. Between those moments of critical innovation, the academic discipline usually deteriorated along dimensions 3 and 4 even though more parsimonious, more consistent, and (to a lesser extent) more encompassing work was produced from year to year by the increasingly uncritical mainstream.
Origins of the Academic Field A century ago international relations first entered the English-speaking academy on both sides of the Atlantic as the child of an anti-imperialist social movement. The academy was one of a number of places in which citizens of increasingly democratic nations found the space to talk with other citizens about the politics of princes. The field’s key founders in both Great Britain and the United States were activist scholars such as John A. Hobson, an early leader of the Union of Democratic Control of Foreign Policy, and Emily Greene Balch, the Wellesley College economist who chaired the union’s sister organization in the United States. In Britain, Hobson’s books and lectures fueled public outrage over the human and financial costs of the Boer War. He treated British actions as ruthless aggression in defense of the narrow interests of the mining companies newly operating throughout southern Africa in the last decades of the nineteenth century. The political object of this Christian socialist economist’s critique included the various organizations and publications through which Cecil Rhodes had created a movement supporting his mining interests (on Hobson, see Long 1996; for Balch, see Randall 1964, Palmieri 1995).
64
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
Hobson’s attempts to explain the international politics of his day were preferable on all five dimensions to the alternative explanations offered at the time, both the realist arguments of the generals and diplomats who disapproved of the new level of public discussion of matters of state and the liberal imperialist arguments promulgated by the more democratic voices that were sponsored by Rhodes and other captains of industry. Hobson and his colleagues could explain underemployment as well as imperialism; free citizens as well as statecrafters were treated as competent enough to support their views—and those views certainly won in the court of public opinion; the scholars of the new field promulgated meliorative policies of full employment, nonintervention, and support for democratization when it occurred overseas. Moreover, their views did not suffer from the contradiction of the “scientific” racism that was central to the liberal imperialist account. In his classic study Imperialism, Hobson maintained that the simultaneous extensions of the British, French, German, Belgian, and U.S. empires in the last decades of the nineteenth century reflected the capture of diplomatic and military policy by self-interested political minorities (Hobson 1965). There was, Hobson agreed, a real economic problem to which the overseas investment associated with imperialism was a response: Industrial capitalist economies produce more than can easily be consumed or invested at home without diminishing the relative power of the capitalists. But imperialism was neither the only nor the best solution. A better alternative, one that would serve the interests of the vast majority, would be to allow the wages of the vast majority of poorly paid workers at home to rise. The fact that governments of industrialized societies did not choose this alternative reflected the capture of foreign policy by a tiny minority (Hobson 1965; Long 1996: 72–96). A political solution, to make foreign policy subject to democratic control, followed directly. The popularity of that conclusion increased between the end of the Boer War, in 1902, and the end of World War I, in 1919. Others added to Hobson’s arguments. Norman Angell, another leader of the Union of Democratic Control, affirmed that it was not capitalist interests per se that led to belligerence and violence. To the contrary, the larger profit that could come to capitalists through peacetime trade ensured that if all modern states could be made subject to the general interest of profit-making firms (as distinct from the particularistic interests of a specific sector) they would be peaceful (J.B.D. Miller 1995). Angell would later be derided by realists who deliberately misunderstood him as having proclaimed the logical impossibility of war among capitalist powers just months before the outbreak of World War I, but in his own day he was treated as a prophet. He was awarded the Nobel Peace Prize in the early years when it was still occasionally given for the same purpose as all the others endowed by the
Critical Theory and the Democratic Impulse
65
Swedish industrialist, to spur invention and science in the designated field, in this case, the new field of public discourse about international affairs. Nonetheless, the choice of Angell rather than other British IR innovators was hardly apolitical. Whereas Hobson’s sort of argument tended to appeal to a working-class and, as yet, not particularly powerful audience, Angell’s kind of argument spoke to more powerful commercial and industrial leaders, one of whom endowed the first professorial chair of international politics at what is now the University of Wales, Aberystwyth. The benefactor named the chair for Woodrow Wilson, the hero of the moment, whose well-intentioned but somewhat incoherent diplomacy throughout the war had been legitimated with the democratic foreign policy slogan, “open agreements, openly arrived at” (Porter 1995). Back in the United States the more intellectually consistent arguments in favor of democratic foreign policy came not from Wilson’s political supporters and apologists but from many of the men and women, like Emily Greene Balch, who founded the discipline of international relations. Although Balch supported many of Wilson’s ideas about a postwar League of Nations, she was an ardent critic of his 1915 intervention in Haiti and of U.S. imperialism in general. Balch, like Hobson, also worked to help define and articulate the demands of industrial labor, focusing especially on the interests of women and immigrants, who made up the majority of the U.S. working class at the turn of the twentieth century (Palmieri 1995: 130, 170–171; Balch 1910, 1918, 1927). Balch’s political leanings led to her 1918 dismissal from the conservative New England college where she taught. Although she later became reconciled with the academic world when the college joined in nominating her for her 1946 Nobel Peace Prize, other, often more conservative—more Wilsonian—scholars ended up filling the space she had helped create in the U.S. academy for the field of international relations. Many in the interwar generation of IR scholars on both sides of the Atlantic maintained faith in the pacific influence of public opinion over foreign policy as well as in Angell’s conclusions about the ultimately benign interests of capitalist enterprise. Many of the interwar scholars worked tirelessly to support and maintain the international institutional framework in which the pacific interests of business in free trade and intergovernmental cooperation might come to the fore. Scholars became some of the most visible and ardent critics of U.S. isolationism and some of the most impassioned advocates of the League of Nations. By the early 1930s, when most League agencies began to experience chronic financial crises, some scholars were willing to move to Geneva and work with little or no pay to staff the beleaguered institutions (anticipating a practice that has been typical within the UN since the mid-1980s, when the United States stopped paying its full assessments). Others stayed in the academy, work-
66
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
ing to design new, more effective systems of international government and to convince the next generation of elites to accept their legitimacy (Murphy 1994: 183–184).
Interwar Realism as Democratic Critique Few living IR scholars have a very clear conception of the preoccupations and motivations of the first generation of scholars within our field, but most of us remember E. H. Carr’s devastating portrayal of the naive idealism affecting both policymakers and scholars in the interwar decades when war was “abolished” by international agreement and true believers turned a blind eye to the League’s obvious failures in Ethiopia and Manchuria. We may be less likely to remember what some think of as unpleasant truths about Carr: that his realism initially led him to support appeasement, that he opposed the kind of liberal internationalism that is now so often portrayed as the only road to prosperity and peace, and that he and other early realists such as Reinhold Niebuhr stood far to the political left of most of the “idealists” they critiqued (Carr 1946: chs. 1–2; Brown 1992; Merkeley 1975; Kegley and Bretall 19561). Carr, Niebuhr, and the recently more accurately remembered Karl Polanyi—whose Great Transformation was a contemporary work that is similar to the major studies of the canonical realists 2 —all provided accounts of international affairs that were superior to those of their academic contemporaries, whom Carr caricatured as utopians. The utopians—the more Wilsonian successors of the more democratic founders of the field such as Hobson and Balch—had consistent ways to account for the failure of the League. The realists could not only explain that failure; their theories also explained the economic failure of the liberal fundamentalist economic policies (endorsed by the victors in World War I as the best policy for the vanquished and then adopted by Republicans in the 1920s), the rise of fascism (as a political response to long-term contradictions of liberal economics and shorter-term issues that ensured the failure of the Weimar Republic’s alternative), and the reasons for the failure of well-meaning liberals (Wilsonians) in their attempt to establish a social order that supported the common woman and man (Murphy 1994: 163–177). The early realists also wrote for a “democratic” audience that extended beyond the academy both to citizens—for example, the industrial labor movements to which the prewar Niebuhr remained closely linked—and to government officials. The meliorative aspects of the early realists’ work included not only relatively clear-eyed proposals about the fascist threat but also proposals for more democratic societies to copy aspects of the thensuccessful systems of state involvement in the economy by the fascists and
Critical Theory and the Democratic Impulse
67
the Soviets, proposals that were echoed in the interwar studies of some critical liberal internationalists, such as David Mitrany and Mary Parker Follett, who, significantly, were never labeled as idealists or utopians by the early canonical realists (Murphy 1998). Finally, the early realist views suffered from neither of the sets of contradictions that typified many of their academic or policy-making contemporaries. As Jawaharlal Nehru argued in his brilliant contemporary analysis of World War II, a key part of the political background both of the actual appeasement policy of Britain’s conservative government and of the failure to use the League to counter earlier fascist moves was the continuing sympathy that many reactionary policymakers had for the racist ideology underlying fascism (Nehru 1985: 418, 481–482). But no dewy-eyed, antiscientific Anglo-Saxonism clouded the early realists’ analysis. Nor, of course, did the realists suffer from what we now might call the psychological denial that affected the interwar liberals whose own Wilsonian vision had proven so flawed. Of course, today, realism is rarely remembered as the international theory of the left. In the Cold War United States the theory became attached to the name George Kennan, the formative intellectual of the postwar U.S. world empire, and to such aging progressives as Niebuhr and Walter Lippmann, who turned their backs on the socialist ideals that had guided them throughout their most politically active years. By the late 1950s one version of realism had become, in part, a justification for shielding foreign policy makers from public scrutiny; it was the so-called realism of the national-security experts—along with their special, publicly inaccessible knowledge—that made it best to let them make all those vital decisions about the nuclear arms race, the NATO buildup, and land wars in poorly understood parts of Asia.
Behaviorist Peace Research as Democratic Challenge Almost as soon as this uncritical form of realism gained ascendancy within the journalistic and policy communities in the English-speaking world, it was challenged from inside the academy. The challenge came in part from scholars who are, often somewhat strangely, not considered part of the canonical tradition of international relations. Most notable in this group are the revisionist historians of U.S. foreign policy (see, for example, Williams 1959, LeFeber 1963, McCormick 1967). The challenge also came from some, such as linguist Noam Chomsky and socialist activist Michael Harrington, whose exclusion from the canon is more easily understood. Chomsky and Harrington never based their critiques of uncritical realism
68
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
on their academic expertise but asked simply that they be treated as the observations of informed citizens within a democracy (Chomsky 1969; Harrington 1977). Nonetheless, there was one group within the academy that is still treated as part of the IR canon and that did link its critique to its academic expertise: the early generation of behaviorist peace researchers. Elise Boulding recalls the intellectual hothouse of the early years of “scientific” peace research, especially at the University of Michigan, where she and Kenneth Boulding crossed paths with J. David Singer, Anatol Rapoport, Johan Galtung, and many others who shared a commitment to scientific method and distrust of Cold War policymakers and their incoherent, superstition-laden, war-promoting observations about the world (Boulding 1997). She reports that in the still unquestionably sexist academic world of the day, it fell to her—the woman with “free” time—to comb through the scrap baskets and put together the newsletter that began to link the Ann Arbor group to like-minded groups—Robert North’s astonishingly productive group of students at Stanford; Karl Deutsch, Bruce Russett, and Hayward Alker at Yale; and others. This was the beginning of the International Peace Research Association, the Peace Science Society, and the research sections on foreign policy, peace studies, and the scientific study of international processes within the International Studies Association. That these groups began with an essentially meliorative aim is hardly questioned within the standard histories of the field. That their epistemological concerns were essentially democratic may surprise some in the current generation of critical theorists, but consider Ole Holsti’s paradigmatic study of John Foster Dulles’s beliefs (Holsti 1962). Holsti hoped with his research to help explain why Cold War foreign policy experts failed to live up to their promise. The study shows that Dulles, far from being realistic, was a rigid ideologue, someone incapable of having his core beliefs about the Soviet Union moved by any change in Soviet behavior. Holsti demonstrates his conclusion by referring to information and forms of analysis accessible to any citizen; to public documents, not secret insider knowledge; and to easily replicable systems of counting and readily calculated correlations. With Holsti and the other behaviorist peace researchers, as with Habermas, truth is largely that which is judged to be true by the largest possible consensus of free women and men. Science, rather than the much less accountable policy expertise, is the road to truth about international affairs, in large part simply because science is democratic. The story of another wonderful article, from the waning years of the Vietnam War, makes the point even more pointedly. J. David Singer and Melvin Small used the generalizations about international affairs contained in the presidential state-of-the-world messages to evaluate the theories
Critical Theory and the Democratic Impulse
69
espoused by the quintessential (uncritical) realists of the day, Richard Nixon and Henry Kissinger. Using the publicly available, readily replicable Correlates of War data, simple two-by-two tables, and clearly explained statistical measures, they demonstrated that Nixon frequently affirmed sweeping generalizations that were not supported by the historical record, as well as many, of course, that were. The article’s lessons are made even more dramatic by the authors’ account of the initial reception of their research. They initially wrote their report for Foreign Affairs, the elite journal in which foreign policy experts speak to each other and to corporate leaders and top journalists. Foreign Affairs rejected the article. The democratic epistemology that its authors affirmed did not mesh with the belief in the value of irreproducible expertise, which was widely shared by the journal’s elite readers (Singer and Small 1975). Thus much of early behaviorist IR shared the same democratic impulse that animated both the first wave of anti-imperialist scholars and the interwar realists on the left. In addition, the work begun in Ann Arbor, Stanford, and Oslo was superior to the contemporary uncritical realism along all dimensions. Singer and Small, or any of those who provided competing behaviorist accounts of war that were not simply codifications of realism, could indeed explain more cases than Kissinger or any other realist luminary (Vasquez and Henehan 1992). The behaviorists had a consistent view of knowledge, its sources, and its role in policymaking that was in sharp contrast to the inconsistent views of the traditional scholars and policymakers of their day. The behaviorists’ epistemology urged them to place their ideas before as wide an audience as possible, and their concerns about the way they built their science meshed with a meliorative agenda that linked them to forms of democratic social action, to movements for peace and justice that helped ensure that their societies survived the Cold War. Of course, many scholars trained on both sides of the Atlantic in years after the Vietnam War never experienced behaviorist peace research as a democratic, critical tradition. Many IR scholars today are apt to see demands for science as only one part of the gate-keeping activities performed by relatively conservative, most often U.S., and most often white and male scholars against the critical voices of scholars whose specific egalitarian concerns have only recently gained a tenuous foothold within the field. There is a great deal of truth to that observation, although it is one that may make us forget an important part of the history of the field. It is, perhaps, useful to remember that before Kenneth Waltz or Robert O. Keohane were self-consciously writing about the values of social science, when they were still writing in the mode of traditional scholars, Elise Boulding and Cynthia Enloe were self-conscious positivists, creating a social science whose truths were open to all as part of the critical challenge
70
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
to an undemocratic cult of international relations expertise (consider, for example, Boulding 1976; Enloe 1980).
The Rise of Contemporary Critical Theory The current wave of democratically inspired theory in IR grew up, in part, as a challenge to the uncritical positivism of the field’s mainstream, especially as it was consolidated in the United States in the 1980s and 1990s. Yet it is important to recognize that the response to positivism was not the whole story. Looked at through the lens of the longer history of citizens talking to citizens about the politics of princes, the self-consciously critical theory of the 1990s came as part of a wave of democratically inspired global theory that began in the waning years of the Vietnam War. The primary aim of that movement has been to make a wide range of previously excluded voices heard within the central academic and public dialogues about international affairs. Whereas Hobson and Balch’s generation spoke about the imperialized world, primarily with the aim of promoting the interests of working people within the colonizing powers, worldsystems theory, subaltern studies, and much of Gramscian IR sought to amplify the voices of the imperialized world, to rewrite international relations from the point of view of the interests and aspirations of the impoverished South. Whereas every earlier generation of critical theorists of international relations included women who often saw parallels between the emancipation struggles of women and movements for peace and decolonization, the feminist IR of the previous decade has placed gender inequality at the center of what needs to be understood in order to understand international affairs. Whereas earlier generations of critical scholars recognized the importance of protracted social conflicts rooted in histories of injustice to the vast majority of the world’s less powerful, members of the new generation of critical scholars whose research led them to form conflict-resolution workshops linking perpetrators and victims actually empowered the victims by taking the task of explaining those conflicts away from external experts and demanding, instead, that the discipline accept the mutually agreed upon explanations of the conflicts that arose from those workshops as the most plausible explanation (Rouhana and Kelman 1994). The article in which Robert Cox makes his often-cited distinction between critical and problem-solving theory includes a strong acknowledgment of the key link between democratic inclusiveness and the critical enterprise (Cox 1981). Theory is always for someone. Critical theory is the kind that allows us to understand how social structures come into being and how they may be changed. It is, in that sense, the kind of theory that is for those who are concerned with the transformation of society as it is, largely
Critical Theory and the Democratic Impulse
71
including those whose interests and aspirations are not served by global structures as they are—the excluded, the powerless, the hitherto unheard. When contemporary IR critical theory is understood in this larger way—as a movement concerned with vastly increasing the number of voices, the number of standpoints, reflected within the field—the movement, too, can be seen as producing scientific progress within the discipline. Almost invariably, today’s critical theory accounts for more than uncritical positivist studies of the same phenomena, if only because the critical theorist includes a wider range of people as objects to explain and as sources of explanation. Liberal feminist Mona Harrington, for example, often can explain much more than canonical liberal institutionalists, including her mentor, Stanley Hoffmann, simply because she demands that her theories account for the actions of women as well as they account for the actions of men (cf. Harrington 1981 with Hoffmann 1968). Similarly, the internal logic of much of today’s critical theory is quite a bit more coherent than that of much uncritical IR positivism simply because uncritical work often must rely on loosely connected ad hoc arguments to explain away its failure to include the entire universe of cases under its “universal” generalizations.3 And, of course, the inclusion of a wider range of people within critical theory’s understanding of global politics mirrors its epistemological commitment to wide, unconstrained consensus as a primary gauge of truth.
The Impossibility of a Detached Social Science So far, then, I have made the case that IR critical theory really does do little more than update Hobson, if that is taken to mean that it carries out the byno-means-simple task of reflecting the democratic impulse that has resulted in the major breakpoints of scientific progress within the field. Here I want to take the argument further and claim that some of what is often seen as the distinctive contributions of today’s critical theory was also anticipated within the schools that reflected the same democratic impulse at an earlier time. Much of what is distinctive about today’s critical theory comes from its critique of international relations positivism, so my claim here is simply that parts of that critique have been present in each of the earlier critical schools. Steve Smith writes of today’s critical theorists that one of their great strengths is treating the silences of mainstream research as meaningful, asking why those silences exist, positing plausible explanations for them, and using those explanations to uncover aspects of the way in which international action is constituted (Smith 1995: 1–2). For example, within the subfield of international organization and international law, Peter Vale has followed the silences of realist and liberal discussions about the new world
72
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
order to identify quite clearly whom the order is not for, who is bound to be peripheralized no matter which side wins the hegemonic debate over the near-term global future (Vale 1995). And within international political economy, Roger Tooze has written about the “unwritten prefaces” to neorealist and neoliberal classics, their authors’ silences about the quite restricted, often inherently undemocratic cultures in which they believe reliable knowledge must be constituted (Tooze 1988). Vale’s contribution is like many of those made by earlier IR critical theorists when they followed the silences in the uncritical mainstream of their day. The earliest academic IR scholars followed silences about imperialism that made it possible for policymakers to ignore the issue of undercompensated labor at home. The interwar realists saw Wilsonian denial about the failure of the League and the rosy-eyed view of Adolf Hitler as a sort of closet liberal internationalist as a useful mask for the unpleasant reality that there were real alternatives to free-market liberalism on both the left and the right. Cold War peace researchers uncovered the Western interests in maintaining the system of antagonistic blocs that lay behind the mainstream’s unwillingness to examine evidence of changing Soviet motivations. Anatol Rapoport, for example, wrote that it was foolish to look to empirical peace research to provide expertise to end the bipolar conflict simply because the problem was not that scholars knew too little about the conflict but that the bipolar powers did not want to end the conflict. The role of peace research was, instead, to undermine the legitimacy of the war system via “critical enlightenment” in “areas where obsolete thinking and habits and vested interests perpetuate superstitions that stand in the way of removing a very real threat to civilization” (Rapoport 1988). Each group of critical scholars also included those who, like Tooze, examined the knowledge-constituting culture that generated the silences of their day. The early anti-imperialists and the Cold War–era peace researchers emphasized the way in which traditions of expertise led to the denial of public scrutiny and, from there, to blindness to questions about the systemic sources of competitive imperialism and superpower rivalry. The interwar realists also explored the impact of a knowledge-constituting culture that afforded scholars and policymakers an intellectual basis on which to deny the evidence of the failure of the League and of the liberal fundamentalist economic policies that had been imposed on weaker nations. This culture is not dissimilar, as the distinguished Mexican economist Victor Urquidi argues, from the knowledge-constituting culture of today’s neoliberal economics and neoliberal international political economy (Urquidi 1992). Early generations of critical IR theorists also reflected on the epistemological problem of disinterested objectivity in the social sciences. Hobson and Carr both wrote that the key distinction between the natural and social
Critical Theory and the Democratic Impulse
73
sciences arose from the fact that doing social science was itself social action that was bound to influence the things the (positivist) scientist merely wished to observe. The insight did not lead them to discard traditional scholarly methods of question generation, evidence gathering, and verification, but it did lead them to caution themselves and their colleagues about the potential, often unpredictable, impact of their own words, which could become self-fulfilling prophecies or (perhaps more usefully) one of those strange kinds of social myth that become a reality if they are believed—for example, the myth of the collective power of the working class to transform capitalism by the withdrawal of its labor power (Augelli and Murphy 1998). Peace researchers Rapoport and Adam Curle took a similar set of issues even further by noting that there are significant sets of real-world conflicts that are unresolvable in the form of strategic games: asymmetric conflicts (conflicts involving distributional inequalities) and ideological conflicts, including conflicts of identity. Both are resolvable only in the nonstrategic mode that Rapoport called debate, but social scientists cannot explain (or predict) the successful outcome of debates. If we could, if we could point to a specific sequence of actions that would invariably result in one party convincing another party of the first’s way of seeing an issue of identity or justice, actors would be able to use that pattern in a deceitful way, as a strategy to win compliance, thus turning the debate back into a strategic game in which the conflict is unresolvable. As a result, Rapoport argued, we social scientists really cannot produce any positive theory relevant to the general problem of making peace in most of the conflicts that plague the world, but we can say something about the ethics of debate, about the type of discourse situation that must be maintained if we want to have any hope that a conflict involving questions of injustice or identity can be resolved (Rapoport 1962: 1–28; Curle 1971: 183–189). Mark Hoffman, one of the leading figures in the new generation of IR critical theory, has taken that conclusion to heart in his actions and research as a third-party facilitator within protracted social conflicts. Conflict workshops create the possibility of Rapoport-style debate that may allow conflicts of injustice or identity to be resolved by the parties involved (Hoffman 1992). This type of debate is, in fact, one significant way in which contemporary critical theory has had programmatic impact on the practice of some egalitarian social movements, specifically those that have become explicit parties in protracted conflicts in which violence has been one of a number of strategies used to promote the interests and aspirations of the least advantaged. I believe it is also significant that this important input into egalitarian practice simply continues and replicates one of the inputs of the previous generation of scholars whose work reflected the democratic impulse within the field.
74
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
Contemporary Critical Theory and Egalitarian Practice Earlier generations of critical scholars made contributions to egalitarian practice in two other ways: (1) by suggesting designs for social institutions that would regularly reproduce more egalitarian outcomes, and (2) by suggesting strategies that movements of the disadvantaged might follow in order to defeat their opponents. Perhaps our generation of critical scholars has been less likely to offer this second type of input simply because, consciously or unconsciously, we have learned the lesson understood by Rapoport and also promulgated quite explicitly (in different ways) by Gandhi and by some recent poststructuralist commentaries on egalitarian political practice: Ultimately conflicts between oppressors and oppressed must be resolved through the transformation of the perceptions and attitudes of the oppressors (and, likely, those of the oppressed) via open debate, a process in which strategic concerns are irrelevant (Rapoport 1972: 84; see also, in a different context, Brent 1996). My own hunch is that this idea is not true. Even if we had learned this lesson, we would probably have learned along with it Adam Curle’s related lesson that the dominant parties in asymmetric conflicts enter such debates only after they have become convinced of the material and moral power of the weaker party, and getting to that stage is, most certainly, a matter of strategy and gamesmanship, as Gandhi’s life work so clearly demonstrates (Curle 1971: 183–189). Similarly, even if we had learned Rapoport’s lesson, we would still have reason to work on the first issue: designing more egalitarian institutions that might be agreed upon at the end of the transformative debates that can resolve asymmetric conflicts. It may be easier to understand why these sort of forward-looking plans are as rare for our generation as they were for the interwar critical realists. Unlike Hobson’s generation or the generation of the early positivist peace researchers, we live at a time that is not very hopeful for those with egalitarian aspirations and with interests in substantive democracy. As the UN Development Programme (UNDP) and other intergovernmental agencies keep repeating year after year, global inequality—material inequality among regions of the world and among social classes everywhere—has grown more in the past twenty-five or thirty years than in the entire period of the rapid growth of inequality that began with the British Industrial Revolution (UNDP 1999). At the same time, in the past fifteen to twenty years, almost all of the grand egalitarian visionary projects of the twentieth century have been discredited: communism, decolonization, the welfare state. Perhaps our positive theory has failed to let us see any alternatives to these older grand visions. Perhaps we do not understand enough about the
Critical Theory and the Democratic Impulse
75
global political economy to create a relevant grand egalitarian vision for the early twenty-first century or even politically relevant visions of lessencompassing policy changes. If that is the case, it may very well be that today’s critical theorists would do well to follow Susan Strange’s unwelcome advice and “get on with it” by doing empirical research either to find the relevant levers of power for the disadvantaged or to persuasively conclude that no such levers exist (the phrase did not survive into the published version, but see Strange 1995). Perhaps we find Strange’s admonition troubling in part because within academic international relations it is actually quite comfortable for critical scholars to be politically detached from the social movements that are working to thwart the global forces they see as creating ever greater inequality. One of the leading historians of U.S. IR has argued that in terms at least of democratic input into foreign policy, the recent (post–World War II) legitimation and professionalization of the field has been a very mixed blessing. It has meant that now, during their college days, U.S. elites are likely to learn a bit about the world at large, some of it even from relatively critical scholars. That is probably a good thing for the lives of the many people around the world who are subject to U.S. supremacy. It has also meant, however, that as critical scholars have found more opportunities within the academy, the need to serve as intellectuals of popular social movements has faded (McCaughey 1984). On a grander stage Gramsci writes of the hegemonic strategy of “decapitating” the popular masses by enticing their intellectuals into the priesthood, the universities, and the state-run schools (Augelli and Murphy 1988: 125–126). Similarly, Emily Greene Balch’s recent biographer writes that her dismissal from Wellesley was, in the long run, a personal liberation that allowed her to focus her intellect entirely on the issues that the college’s governors found so disreputable (Palmieri 1995: 117–118, 242–244). No critical theorist would hope for a similar closing of the space for critical IR within today’s academy. Nonetheless, we may need to guard against the political tameness and complacency that would help to keep that space open.
Notes 1. In terms of the history of postwar IR, it is interesting that the Kegley and Bretall volume was edited by the father of positivist foreign policy, analyst Charles W. Kegley Jr., whose recent work has come out of a critical peace research tradition and emphasizes liberal-internationalist “democratic peace” arguments that are more typical of Hobson or Balch. See Kegley and Raymond 1994. 2. This link is recognized by a number of those who admire Robert W. Cox’s work and is, perhaps, reflected in his choice of a designation for the eclectic combination of insights from Gramsci, Polanyi, and others (Cox 1997).
76
The Contours of Critical IR Theory
3. Some of the most telling critiques of the tendency of IR positivism to ignore large numbers of relevant cases have come from scholars employing more traditional methods. Robert H. Jackson, for example, has demonstrated that scores of the “fundamental units” of rationalist neoliberal and neorealist models simply do not have the independence that those models assume. Hence, the resulting theories can, at best, apply to only a limited part of the world (see Jackson 1993).
PART TWO CRITIQUE IN CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY
5 THE NATURE OF CRITIQUE IN CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY Kimberly Hutchings
In this chapter the aim is to focus attention on the nature of critique in the kind of international relations theory that refers to itself as critical. I begin by drawing attention to the fact that there are different forms of critical international relations theory. What is sometimes identified as critical theory proper tends to rely heavily on Marxist or Frankfurt School sources. In contrast, postmodernist and feminist IR theory, which also sees itself as critical, draws on a range of post-Marxist inspirations. In spite of this diversity of theoretical grounding, however, I argue that it is possible to identify a common element that helps to identify all these theoretical approaches as critical. It is my contention that this common element reflects a logic that can be traced back to the origins of the idea of critique in the work of Kant. I then go on to suggest that, as with Kantian critique, there are both dangers and possibilities inherent in the kind of critical theoretical turn in international relations (IR) that is the subject of this book. The dangers can be summed up as those of lapsing back into the wars of reason between realist and idealist perspectives, which critical theory in international relations is actually supposed to have transcended. These dangers, I argue, are largely responsible for the tendency of critical IR theory to remain trapped within unsolvable theoretical debates rather than turning attention toward redirecting empirical research and specific explanation. The possibilities of critical IR theory relate to the ways in which it opens up our understanding of the scope and potential of developments in international politics. There are two dimensions to critical theory’s contribution here: On the one hand, by challenging the traditional limitations on explanation, critical theory extends the capacity of social scientists to account for particular phenomena; on the other hand, by never taking the limitations and conditions of possibility of 79
80
Critique in Critical IR Theory
contemporary world politics as given, critical theorists elucidate the possibilities and probabilities of change. There are at least four general positions that can claim to be examples of critical theory in the international relations context. First, there is neoGramscian work on global political economy and international politics, most notably exemplified by the work of Robert W. Cox (see, for example, 1996a). Second, there is explanatory and normative theory, such as that of Andrew Linklater (Linklater 1990a, 1990b, 1998), which draws on the work of the Frankfurt School and of Jürgen Habermas in particular. Third, there is postmodernist work—such as that of Richard Ashley (1988), R.B.J. Walker (1993, Ashley and Walker 1990), James Der Derian (1987, Der Derian and Shapiro 1989), and Jens Bartelson (1995)—that draws on a range of poststructuralist and postmodernist philosophers, of which Michel Foucault and Jacques Derrida are the most significant (on Foucault, see Hutchings 1997). Fourth, there is feminist work, such as that of Jean Elshtain (1987), Cynthia Enloe (1989), Christine Sylvester (1994), V. Spike Peterson (1992a), Rebecca Grant and Kathleen Newland (1991), and Ann Tickner (1992), which draws on a very wide range of traditions (including Marxism, the Frankfurt School, and postmodernism) but always insofar as those traditions have been mediated by the insights of the diversity of theoretical traditions peculiar to feminism (see also Hutchings 1994). In none of these four categories is there an exact consensus about what that particular version of critical theory should look like. This means that it is no easy matter to pin down what being critical means or to work out whether there is anything in common among the perspectives that all see themselves as critical. I suggest, however, that there is a certain common logic at work in these different critical positions. This is not an argument that all these different perspectives are saying the same thing but simply that insofar as they involve a critical aspect, they share certain formal characteristics that have particular theoretical and practical consequences. The best way of summing up what all the previously mentioned critical theories have in common, I would suggest, is to say that they are all engaged in tracing and challenging given limits, most obviously the limits given in the dominant neorealist perspectives on the explanation and judgment of international politics but also, particularly in the case of some postmodernist and feminist work, those inherent in more liberal, idealist approaches. There are two interrelated ways in which critical theories accomplish this. One is by focusing on the ways in which the object of investigation in international relations fails to fit within the limits prescribed for it by more orthodox approaches. This approach involves a challenge to the ontological assumptions that have governed prevalent thinking about what constitutes and accounts for international relations (in realism’s case a particular conception of the state and the interstate system operating
The Nature of Critique
81
in terms of realpolitik) as opposed to domestic or transnational politics and global economics. The second is by challenging the necessity of the conditions of possibility of judgment (explanatory and normative) that are relied on by more orthodox approaches. This involves an epistemological challenge to orthodox modes of analysis and investigation in international relations (which rest on specific conceptions of the notions of state, interest, and power as well as on positivist methodological assumptions) but also a challenge to the apparent exclusion of normative values from explanation in mainstream thinking. In addition, it brings into question the distinction between morality and politics; it is through this distinction that the nature of international politics has been defined by both realism and idealism. Critical theorists tend not to accept the characterization of politics in terms of realpolitik and the banishment of morality from the realms of politics. Similarly, they reject the characterization of morality as a matter of ahistorical, transcendental principles by which political reality will always be condemned. In the context of this chapter it is impossible to do full justice to the different versions of critical theory; what follows is a very brief consideration of how each of the critical approaches carries out the dual challenge I have identified. Cox’s work is well known for its eclectic use of a variety of theoretical traditions, although his most prominent theoretical debts are to the Marxist historicist tradition in social science (Cox 1996a: 124–173). Cox’s historicism is the key to the way he traces and challenges the limits of realism in both senses mentioned previously. In terms of the ontological aspect of his critical work, Cox criticizes realism’s characterization of its object of analysis for its ahistorical perspective, in which the limits of a particular present are treated not as historical constructions, which come about through a complex interaction between states and substate and transstate forces, but as unquestionable eternal verities. In making this critique of classical IR thinking, Cox is drawing attention to a range of conditions of possibility for international politics, including economic, cultural, and ideological factors. His claim is that if the theorist does not see the object of study as including these conditions of possibility but deals with interstate relations in isolation, then the work only reproduces and reinforces the common sense of the age. In terms of the epistemological aspect of his critical work, Cox also identifies modes of social scientific investigation as part of the historical development that delivers a particular articulation of the pattern of state power, productive forces, and world order. In other words, positivism is not a neutral and guaranteed route to the truth but a methodological approach that itself reflects a series of assumptions about politics, power, human nature, and knowledge; it is itself historically conditioned. Cox’s arguments about history and knowledge establish a strong link between the explanatory and the normative in social science. Certain
82
Critique in Critical IR Theory
kinds of explanation are seen to derive from the norms embedded in either hegemonic or counterhegemonic discourses. This observation directly challenges the line drawn by traditional international relations theory between facts and values. In addition, the identification of norms as within history rather than located in the conscience of the historian undermines the assumption common to both realism and idealism that the spheres of politics and morality are inherently distinct. For Cox, moral ends are a potential of his object of investigation and are open to being recognized and encouraged by the critical theorist but are not invented by him or her. Linklater’s work has much in common with Cox’s. In Beyond Realism and Marxism, Linklater also argues that analysis in international relations that is restricted to interstate relations fails to recognize the role of sub- and transstate political and economic forces in conditioning the possibilities of international politics (Linklater 1990b: 1–7). As with Cox’s work, Linklater’s argument is not designed to dismiss the insights of realism but to identify their partiality and examine the role of what has been excluded in order to enhance explanation and understanding in the field. Like Cox again, Linklater seeks to bring history into the ahistorical assumptions of traditional international relations theory and to challenge the claim to neutrality in its theoretical and methodological framework. In Linklater’s case, however, there is a specific variant of the challenge to the fact/value and politics/morality distinctions that are constitutive of classical realism and idealism. Whereas Cox works with the notion of hegemonic and counterhegemonic discourses, Linklater draws on Habermas’s discourse ethics and theory of historical development to identify the potential of modern states to transcend the logic of the state system reflected by realism (Linklater 1990b: 163–164; see also 1992b: 35–36). Among the conditions of possibility that realism takes as eternally given (i.e., the state) is a notion of right that points beyond particular interest. Over time, a pattern of collective learning oriented by the logic of communication itself may enable the transcendence of the “anarchy problematique.” Thus the presumptions of realist analysis have to be rethought not only in terms of the ways they have been historically produced or constructed but also in terms of their capacity for self-transcendence, conceptually and in practice. Postmodernist approaches to international relations depart from the work of Cox and Linklater insofar as postmodernists are suspicious of any reference to or reliance on notions of progress in history, whether of a Marxist or Habermasian kind. In addition, postmodernist work focuses less on the specification of what international politics is than on the ways it has been discursively constructed by the discipline of international relations itself—largely because postmodernists insist on the impossibility of disentangling questions of what is from discourses about what Is. This conviction is evident in the work of Der Derian on diplomacy and Bartelson on
The Nature of Critique
83
sovereignty; both theorists draw attention to the discursive construction of what has come to be identified in more mainstream analysis as independently existing objects of investigation (Der Derian 1987; Bartelson 1995). Ashley and Walker (1990) likewise have drawn attention to the intimate connection between academic IR’s vision of world politics and the politics of academic international relations itself. Nevertheless, the ways in which postmodernists trace and challenge the limits of more orthodox approaches to understanding world politics clearly echo aspects of Cox’s and Linklater’s arguments. Like Cox and Linklater, postmodernists question the boundary between the domestic and the international and argue that the conditions of possibility of interstate relations include sub- and transstate forces. Similarly, postmodernists challenge the epistemological presumptions of positivism, the distinction between fact and value, and the conceptual armory of realism, in particular realism’s reliance on a particular understanding of the concepts of state, sovereignty, and power. When it comes to challenging the morality/politics distinction, however, postmodernists see themselves as being more radically critical than Cox and Linklater. As was already discussed, Cox and Linklater challenge the distinction realism draws between morality and politics both by pointing to the normative agendas implicit in the study of international relations nurtured by hegemonic interests and by arguing for an alternative mode of theorizing oriented by alternative normative values. Both Cox and Linklater identify critical theory with a project of emancipation and with the capacity to discriminate between the workings of power and the workings of freedom. In contrast, postmodernists are reluctant to suggest that there are any stable criteria by which one version of the international can be judged better than another. They argue that using the notion of emancipation as a ground for criticizing the theoretical and practical status quo is itself authoritative and exclusionary, an argument that problematizes the idea of a clear distinction between power and freedom. For this reason postmodernists accuse critical theorists such as Cox and Linklater of relying on uncritical assumptions about criteria of judgment that collapse critical theory back into Marxist or liberal idealism. Nevertheless, in spite of this rejection of the idea of a substantive vision of emancipation, postmodernists still claim that their theorizing is in a “register of freedom” (Ashley and Walker 1990). This register of freedom is identified with the Foucauldian notion of an imperative to constantly transgress the boundaries of given limitation (in theory and practice) rather than with any substantive ideal of a world without oppression (Hutchings 1997). Feminist international relations theory is an even more recent development within the discipline than the perspectives already mentioned and is in some ways more difficult to characterize because there are feminist positions that would classify themselves as critical in the Cox and Linklater
84
Critique in Critical IR Theory
sense or as postmodernist and that therefore reflect many of the characteristics of the positions previously noted (Hutchings 1995: 169–185). Feminists, like other critical theorists, question the existing ontological and epistemological assumptions of international relations theory. In particular they draw attention to the consequences for those assumptions of considering gender as one of the crucial conditions of possibility both for contemporary interstate relations and for the realist worldview. The work of critics such as Elshtain and Enloe has drawn attention to the fact that gendered divisions of labor and constructions of femininity and masculinity underlie many practices in contexts—from diplomacy to the military—that are central to the realist perception of international politics. The work of Tickner and Peterson has challenged the positivist claim to neutrality by pointing out the gendered assumptions that help to construct the building blocks of positivist analysis and methodology (Tickner 1991; Peterson 1992b). Once more it is argued that the assertion of a fact/value split and of a morality/politics distinction collapses in the face of investigation of how that distinction is produced and sustained within theory. With regard to the morality/politics split, one of the most significant strands in feminist thinking about war has been a set of claims about the normative standard inherent in the caring work most commonly carried out by women and its potential both to maintain and to subvert the possibility of war as an acceptable last resort in international politics (Ruddick 1990). The previous brief overview has served to illustrate my initial claim that at least one significant feature is shared by the different theoretical approaches to international politics that see themselves as critical: They all trace and challenge the ontological and epistemological limits given in traditional realist analysis. However, a certain tension has become evident between the critical perspectives that might be seen as in the mainstream of critical theory and the postmodernist approach. This tension has its ground in the different answers the alternative critical theories would give to the question of how their own critique is possible—the question, in other words, of the conditions of possibility of the critical theorists’ challenge to the conditions of possibility of realism. It is fairly clear from the previous account that Cox and Linklater suggest a dual answer in accounting for their own critique: First, they both operate with a concept of emancipation that functions as a principle for judgment of the contemporary world order; second, they both argue that this normative principle of critique is immanent, even if by no means necessarily realizable, within history. This dual ground, which each would account for differently by reference to the theoretical sources on which they draw, enables a more definite account of better-worse judgments and outcomes than is offered by postmodernist theorists. The way postmodernist theorists answer the question of how their critique is possible involves no such reference to values immanent within
The Nature of Critique
85
history. Instead, postmodernists locate the possibility of critique within the necessary unsustainability of any secure ground for judgment. Thus, for postmodernists, better-worse claims are always inherently problematic. Once the question of how critical theory is grounded or validated becomes a focus of attention, it is all too easy for the tension described to take on the form of a fixed opposition in which different schools of critical theory condemn (and caricature) each other. For critical theorists of the Cox-Linklater orientation, the postmodernist position is condemned as ultimately unintelligible as a critical theory because in the end, it has no reference point in relation to which its own account of international politics is better in the sense of being more progressive or emancipatory than realism or idealism. For postmodernists, neo-Gramscian and Habermasian critical theory is condemned as ultimately unintelligible as a critical theory because, they claim, it relies on assertions about normative values and progress in history. A similar standoff is reproduced in feminist critique. In this context, the analogous position to that of Cox and Linklater is provided by feminist theorists who ground their critique in a particular account of what the oppression or emancipation of woman means and use this as a measure for better-worse. Postmodernist feminists respond by pointing to the ways in which specific characterizations of woman, oppression, and emancipation are themselves open to challenge and argue that critique is better understood as the refusal of all given conditions for judgment. Their opponents reply that this view renders critique as nothing other than a commitment to the pluralization of voices and thereby deprives it of moral authority and political effectiveness (Hutchings 1994, 1995: 169–185). To sum up, it appears as if one kind of critique is seen as disabling itself through uncritical reliance on given, ungrounded, and ungroundable assumptions; the other kind of critique is seen as disabling itself through its collapse into a skepticism about the possibility of any meaningful judgment at all. Ironically, this debate has clear echoes of the argument between realism and idealism or its contemporary liberal heirs, an argument that all kinds of critical theory saw themselves as superseding. Here also it was always the case that one side condemned the other for cynicism and skepticism on the one hand or for dogmatic reliance on ideal and unsubstantiable standards on the other. This focus on what differentiates alternative critical perspectives from one another diverts attention from what they share. This diversion in turn means that as an influence on the theory and practice of the discipline of international relations, both kinds of critical theory risk marginalizing themselves by becoming preoccupied with this inward-looking battle between what is characterized as skepticism on the one hand and dogmatism on the other. It is at this point, I would argue, that a consideration of the ways critical IR theory in its various guises is developing may be illuminated by an
86
Critique in Critical IR Theory
examination of Kantian critical philosophy. Not only does the logic of Kantian critique provide an excellent clarification of the patterns of thinking in critical IR theory, but it also highlights the danger of self-marginalization and suggests how that danger might be addressed and the positive potential of critical theory be realized. At the beginning of my discussion, I characterized critical IR theory in terms of its preoccupation with the tracing and challenging of the conditioning ontological and epistemological limits of more orthodox approaches. In this sense, critical IR theory is a classically Kantian enterprise. Kantian critique sets out to trace the conditions of possibility of claims to knowledge, taking its starting point from the untenability of skepticism, exemplified by Humean empiricism, and dogmatism, exemplified by Wolffian rationalism. Kant is concerned with what conditions the appearance of the object of knowledge (the analogous question might be, How does international politics come to appear as it appears?) and with what conditions the ways in which the object of knowledge is known (analogously, the conceptual framework and methodological techniques of realism). The paradox of Kantian critique, however, is that even as it refuses the classical empiricist and rationalist alternatives, it constantly comes back to them when it attempts to account for its own ground or authority. Whereas the purpose of critique is to trace the limitations of reason in order to engage in critique, reason (in the form of the work of the critic) takes on powers that appear to transcend that limitation, which the critic needs to account for. In the struggle to make this accounting, the Kantian critic is always in danger of either asserting a dogmatic authority over judgment or problematizing the authority of critical judgment to such an extent that its very possibility becomes open to question. I have discussed the nature of what I term the politics of Kantian critique at some length elsewhere (Hutchings 1995: 11–57); what is important here is the apparent difficulty Kant’s critique has in sustaining itself as critical. If the critic succeeds in grounding the authority of critique, critique lapses into the dogmatic assertion of set standards of judgment. If the critic fails to provide a ground for critique, critique lapses into skepticism. It appears, then, as if critique depends on refusing to either succeed or fail in the task of establishing the ground of its authority. In Critique of Pure Reason, Kant describes the clash between skepticism and dogmatism in terms of the wars of reason (Kant 1929: 601–608; Hutchings 1995: 150–166). In contrast, he presents critique as initiating a peacemaking process that mediates between and transcends the two precritical alternatives. As I have suggested, this mediation and transcendence is not a stable resolution of antinomic moments but a problematic interplay of dogmatic and skeptical elements that are always held in tension. When called to account for the authority of critique, the critic’s response is and must be equivocal and unsatisfactory (Hutchings 1995: 186–191). I have
The Nature of Critique
87
suggested that critical theory of international relations, like Kantian critique, is an attempt to transcend the wars of reason in which realist analysis is countered by idealism and vice versa. In accounting for its own authority, however, critique in international relations also follows Kant in threatening to fight the battles of reason all over again. Characterizing the critical other as a modernist dogmatist or a postmodernist skeptic merely returns theory to a tedious and unwinnable war. At the same time it encourages critics to identify their own critical practice as having overcome the difficulties of critique rather than as preserving and acknowledging its tensions, thus rendering critique uncritical once again. The problems critique encounters when it attempts to ground its own authority represent the dangerous road that is all too easy for critical IR theory to take, whether it goes in a skeptical or dogmatic direction. For the critical theorist, it is impossible either to ground critique securely or to abandon the notion of critical authority. The mark of critique is precisely a fundamental insecurity about its conditions of possibility. This insecurity is best summed up as a capacity for constant theoretical self-reflection in which the vulnerability of the conditions of possibility of critique is acknowledged even as its claim to authoritative judgment is made. The preoccupation with the ground of critique is dangerous because it forces critical work into a philosophical argument that, as Kant shows, is both violent and unresolvable. Thus the energies of critique get caught up in a backward-looking theoretical debate rather than being pushed outward into the exploration of how critical insights may be used to strengthen understanding and explanation in the realm of international politics. This regressive debate occurs in critical IR theory when the tension between different ways of grounding critique becomes the focus of attention. If no ultimate accounting for the authority of the judgments of critical theory is possible, the only way critical theory can prove itself is through more modest and pragmatic means. These means amount, I suggest, to a critique of orthodox theoretical frameworks and methodologies on the one hand and on the other to a clear indication of the explanatory benefits and costs of moving beyond those frameworks and methodologies in specific contexts. In the previous brief discussions of the different forms of critical IR theory, I focused principally on the critique of orthodoxy, which is characteristic of critical theory. Essentially, this critique demonstrates that realism’s account of its own assumptions is open to question and that those assumptions may be better accounted for by a rethinking of the conditions of possibility of realist work. How can this rethinking be carried out? One way would be to seek to demonstrate that the validity of the judgment of the critical theorist can be proved by its being traced back to ground superior to that on which the realist rests his or her case, a move that involves the critical theorist demonstrating his or her epistemological and ethical
88
Critique in Critical IR Theory
authority. As I have already suggested, I think this is a dangerous road to take and presents the critic with an impossible task. The other road is a phenomenological or immanent critique in which specific examples of realist analysis are shown to rely implicitly on what they exclude explicitly and are unable to account for. This kind of work does not need to rely on largescale claims to truth or goodness but simply on a commitment to examining the conceptual and practical conditions of possibility of that which is taken for granted in the dominant form of explanation. This work has in fact been crucial to all forms of critical theory and is perhaps most evident in the ways critical theorists draw attention to the historical, social, economic, and normative conditions of modern state sovereignty. The argument works in two directions: First, in relying on the notion of state sovereignty, it is argued, realism is bracketing off its reliance on a nexus of structures and forces by which states and sovereignty are constituted and sustained; second, the exclusion of these structures and forces from explanation, it is argued, limits realism’s ability to grasp the interplay between interstate behavior and historical, social, economic, and normative conditions and therefore limits its explanatory and predictive power. I suggested that there are two directions in which critical theory can develop. First, it can move in a more negative direction in which attention is focused on the partial and distorting nature of realist analysis. So far most critical theoretical work not caught up in the backward-looking wars of reason has been of this nature. The second direction, which is only in its infancy within critical IR theory, is one in which the positive implications of the rethinking implied by the immanent critique of realism are thought through. Here, it seems to me, critical theory has great potential as long as it maintains a scrupulous attention to its own limitations and the theoretical and methodological assumptions it is making. This kind of work is likely to be of three kinds. The first would be work that involves developing new conceptual frameworks and methodological techniques through which international politics can be explained and understood. The shift from the term international relations to the term international politics to describe the object of investigation provides one very simple example. The term international relations, according to the realist tradition, encapsulates the fundamentally apolitical and ahistorical logic of the state system. The use of international politics immediately prevents from being taken for granted the idea that different kinds of possibilities pertain to the international as opposed to the domestic political sphere. The second kind of work would offer alternative explanations for phenomena—from war to interstate cooperation—that realism is concerned to account for. Here critical theory is obliged to demonstrate empirically how the historical, social, economic, and normative conditions of the modern state system account for specific international developments.
The Nature of Critique
89
The third kind of work would focus on phenomena that realism tended to exclude or see as marginal to mainstream explanation of interstate behavior, such as transnational organizations, new social movements, nationalism, and democracy. Here critical theory is likely to find much in common with contemporary work in development studies, global political economy, sociology, and political science, which all testify to the difficulty of operating on the presumption of the state as the crucial constitutive limit on the analysis of economic and social order or normative political agendas. For many critical theorists of international relations it would seem as if the previous discussion misses one very important dimension of critical theory: I have focused on what critical explanatory work in international relations might look like but have not mentioned the normative element that is common to this sort of critique. Critical theory’s quarrel with realism has never been a purely social scientific one; it has also always been about values and their importance not just as phenomena that are part of international politics but as something that acts as a focus or orientation for social scientific work and the kinds of policy priorities that may follow from it. Above all, critical theorists of all persuasions, including postmodernists, have stressed that critique is necessarily bound up with freedom (Hutchings 1995: 158–165). In what sense does the kind of work I have mentioned incorporate this dimension? Here, once again, it is tempting to see historicist and Habermasian critics as lined up against postmodernists, with the former claiming a grasp of at least some of the determinate conditions of freedom (emancipation) and the latter arguing that freedom can be understood only negatively, in terms of resistance to determination (transgression). According to these responses, the link between critique and freedom would be realized in terms of condemnation or prescription depending on whether a particular analysis did or did not fulfill either emancipatory or transgressive criteria. This answer to the question of the normative dimension of critical theory returns us to the wars of reason, since it reopens the unresolvable debate about the grounds of critique, this time in terms of rival accounts of freedom. However, there is a more minimal normative sense in which historicist, Habermasian, postmodernist, and feminist critical theorists can all claim that their theoretical work is grounded in and oriented toward freedom. This sense derives from the commitment of all critical theorists to always consider the question of the conditions of possibility of both the theory and practice of international politics. This question has infinite implications, it can never be definitively answered, and it rests on the assumption that no conditions are simply given but all are produced and constructed. By stressing this claim as a universal presumption of critique, critical theorists are also committed to the revisability in principle of any given theoretical posi-
90
Critique in Critical IR Theory
tion or state of affairs. When critical theorists move beyond this claim to the specific prescription of one path rather than another or the condemnation of what is in terms of what might or ought to be, they are building on a deeper insight that is fundamental to all critique. What cannot be revised is the assumption of the revisability of conditions itself. I would argue, therefore, that it is possible for IR theory to be critical without being specifically prescriptive as long as it involves the exposure of conditions of possibility in the sense already discussed. Specifically, prescriptive critical theory is certainly not ruled out, but as long as it remains critical it must continue to make explicit the fundamental assumption on which it rests. Thus prescriptive critical theorists need to be cautious and to articulate as clearly as possible their own (revisable) basis for the claims they are making. Moreover, prescriptive critical theorists must always acknowledge that no normative position is nonexclusive or unchallengeable. Perhaps most important, all critical theorists should be clear that the possibility of revision of things as they are is purely theoretical unless and until revision either is or becomes the burden of actual economic, social, or political movements and forces. The actual effects of critical theorizing are not guaranteed and cannot be known in advance. The irony of the previous discussion, of course, is that it is theoretical and may therefore be seen as falling foul of the common complaint about critical theory, that is, that it has failed significantly to further the explanation and understanding of an increasingly complex and obscure world of international politics. What I have tried to argue in this chapter is that this charge can be made reasonably against critical theory only insofar as it allows itself to be distracted by philosophical debates about the ground of critique, debates that actually rest on a fundamental misconception of what critique means. Critique is premised on the impossibility of a definitive answer to the conditions of its own possibility and can only content itself with the acknowledgment of the revisability of any grounds on which its specific claims are based. The positive potential of critical theory lies in its widening the range of phenomena relevant to the explanation of international politics and a range of questions that a realist agenda rules out in advance. The significance of critical theory will be demonstrated in two ways in the future: first, in the empirical work that is being and will be carried out in the wake of its theoretical challenge; second, in the extent to which critical theory’s constant reminder that the world need not be as it is chimes in with world historical, social, economic, and political forces— forces that are way beyond the control of the critical theorist.
6 NEGATIVE DIALECTIC? THE TWO MODES OF CRITICAL THEORY IN WORLD POLITICS N. J. Rengger
Almost coterminous with the birth of the modern states system has been the development of the many attempts to transcend it. At its conceptual inception in the late sixteenth and seventeenth centuries there were many who bitterly opposed it, seeing it as little better than a law of the jungle and a denial of everything they felt Christian Europe stood for. Perhaps the most eloquent, and still among the most interesting, of these figures is Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (Riley 1992, 1996; see also Nardin, Brown, and Rengger 1998). However, Leibniz’s affection for the medieval conception of the Respublica Christiana was not the route that disaffection with the states system was increasingly to take in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, even though, significantly, it is perhaps increasingly relevant today. For those who felt that the order created by the states system most strongly resembled the order of the grave, the procession of attempts, begun by the Abbe de St. Pierre, to find a way of converting the system into one of perpetual peace is perhaps the best-known attempt to transcend the states system. Commented on at the end of his long life by Leibniz and throughout the eighteenth century by writers such as Rousseau, perhaps the most famous version of this attempt today is Kant’s justly celebrated essay “Perpetual Peace,” first published in 1795 (in Reiss 1970). Kant sketched a program for the gradual transcendence of the states system in all but name and its replacement by a system of cosmopolitan law. Kant, of course, is usually—and often rightly—seen as a liberal. However, there is in Kant’s thinking a radicality that many liberals shy away from. It is perhaps most clearly displayed in his writings on international relations; it was, after all, Kant who famously referred to his predecessors in the field—Grotians and realists alike—as “sorry comforters” 91
92
Critique in Critical IR Theory
(those specifically mentioned included Hugo Grotius, Samuel Pufendorf, and Emmerich von Vattel). In his “Perpetual Peace” essay, Kant spoke firmly in the accents of the European Enlightenment, of which he was perhaps the greatest philosophical representative. It is worth remembering, in this context, his famous description of Enlightenment in one of his other essays: “An Answer to the Question ‘What Is Enlightenment?’” Enlightenment, he writes, is the emergence of man from his “self incurred immaturity” (1991: 59). In other words, for Kant and for the Enlightenment as a whole, the key to our emancipation is to recognize that it is we who hold ourselves back. In international relations (IR) theory, Kant was famously referred to by Martin Wight as a revolutionist, and it is his hostility to the states system that makes him genuinely revolutionary in that sense if not in others. He has, however, been joined in that hostility by a good many thinkers and traditions, especially in the twentieth century, even where they have shared almost nothing else with him. In the nineteenth century, it was the liberal Enlightenment that dominated, and such hopes were largely forgotten save for a few little-known—at the time—radicals like Karl Marx. In the twentieth century, however, such hopes of systemic transcendence, what Richard Falk refers to as “system transforming” hopes, became much greater, especially over the last few years, when all sorts of possible agents were fingered as the agent who would put the final nail in the coffin of the states system: technology, globalization, the world economy—the list goes on and on. This revolutionism that would seek to transcend the states system had two great advocates in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, Kant and Marx. Andrew Linklater has described them as “the two great exponents of moral and political universalism within the tradition of philosophical history” (Linklater 1990a: 205). They were also the two greatest exponents of emancipation—though they did not entirely agree either on what was to do the emancipating or on what humans were being emancipated from. In the context of international relations, however, the tradition in which they stand is unambiguous. The order of the current international system is no true order at all, for it has no place for justice and little for humans as humans rather than humans as members of discrete communities. The problem of order can therefore be solved only when it is effectively transcended. This tradition is rightly seen as a cosmopolitan tradition—though it is not, of course, the only available cosmopolitanism; it is also seen, again often rightly, as a universalist one (on the relationship between cosmopolitanism and universalism, see Rengger 1999: epilogue). Most important, it is seen as an emancipatory project.
Negative Dialectic?
93
Emancipation and Critical Theory in International Relations There are a number of approaches that seek to develop this line of reasoning, and not all of them are directly related to (academic) international relations theory. For example, it would be central to a good deal of liberation theology (and some continental political theology, such as that of Jürgen Moltmann and Johann Baptist Metz); to more general dependencia analysis (André Gunder Frank, Samir Amin) and world-systems analysis (Immanuel Wallerstein, Christopher Chase-Dunn); and to some still more heterodox work such as the critical pedagogy of Paulo Friere, the critical legal theory of, among others, Roberto Managebeira Unger, and the literary and political writings of Edward Said and a number of other postcolonial literary theorists. (Leonard 1994 provides an interesting overview. See also Moltmann 1967; Metz 1969; Frank 1967; Wallerstein 1974, 1979, 1980, 1989; Chase-Dunn 1989; Arrighi 1994; Friere 1983; Said 1994; Unger 1987.) However, the body of work that makes this the centerpiece of their argument in contemporary IR theory is usually called critical theory. Critical theory is, however, often used in international relations in an unhelpfully general way—to name but five examples, international relations theory influenced by poststructuralism; feminist IR theory; Gramscian concerns, especially in international political economy; some interpretive constructivisms such as that of Kratochwil (1989); and Marxisant analysts such as Fred Halliday and Justin Rosenberg (Halliday 1994; Rosenberg 1994a; see also Rengger 1996) are all often referred to as critical theory, as is the work of those thinkers, most obviously Andrew Linklater, who draw sustenance from the tradition of critical theory properly so called, that is to say, the critical theory of the Frankfurt School.1 I want to emphasize that in this chapter I am concerned to discuss only those critical theories of international relations that make emancipation central to their analysis and operation. This focus effectively rules out poststructural international theory and a good deal of constructivist theory. Although it is possible to argue, as for example, Andrew Linklater has, that all forms of critical theory have something to bring to the emancipatory project, many poststructuralists and constructivists would, I suspect, be very skeptical about this. In any event, the central set of arguments I am concerned with here are derived from or related to Frankfurt School critical theory. In my view, it is the Frankfurt School–influenced critical IR theorists who have provided the most general orientation for critical theory in international studies as far as emancipation is concerned, and it is this orientation that essentially drives the critical project in international relations.
94
Critique in Critical IR Theory
Thus in this chapter I want to offer a general argument connecting certain key Frankfurt School themes with the use to which they have been put in critical international relations theory. I will return in my concluding remarks to what this general argument might imply for other critical literatures in contemporary international theory.
The Frankfurt School and Critical Theory The general story of the Frankfurt School is well enough known and has been sufficiently well told by others (see Jay 1973; Wiggershaus 1994; Held 1980). However, I do want to make a couple of prefatory points, since I will come back to them later on. As is well known, the powerful mix of different intellectual currents that became known in the 1930s as critical theory was originally developed by thinkers as different as Karl Korsch, Georg Lukács, Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, Walter Benjamin, Eric Fromm, Leo Lowenthal, and Herbert Marcuse and covered fields as diverse as history, political science, social theory, aesthetics, political economy, psychology, and economic history. This critical theory was powerfully influenced by Marx and by Sigmund Freud (see, for example, Jay 1973) and, rather less obviously but perhaps more powerfully still, by Hegel. However, it is also significant that it developed in the context of the stresses and tensions of the Weimar Republic. Virtually all the original members of the Frankfurt School were both Jewish and Marxist—at least in general orientation—and all were, in the Weimar context, Vernunftrepublikaner (Gay 1974), that is to say grudging, rationally led supporters of Weimar, which they saw as a liberal bourgeois republic. It was Horkheimer, of course, who first referred to the theory he and his colleagues were developing as critical theory, and as is well known, he did so to distinguish it from what he termed traditional theory (Horkheimer 1972). This was theory seen as separate from that which is theorized about, as in traditional pictures of the natural sciences and, though Horkheimer hardly had this in mind when he was writing, as the dominant post–World War II traditions of social science have predominantly seen themselves. Critical theory, by contrast, saw itself as irretrievably situated and thus related to social and political life. Thus critical theory, but not traditional theory, can investigate the function of theory itself—who and what it serves and why and how. This capacity is put in service of the task of theory as conceived by the Frankfurt School—as Horkheimer and his colleagues became known on their return to Frankfurt after the war—which is to investigate the historical and social evolution of society, tracing contradictions that might open up in it and offer the possibility of transcending it.
Negative Dialectic?
95
However, the thinking of the Frankfurt School on this point oscillated wildly. The early, largely prewar, writing was broadly optimistic, seeing the possibility for successful political action to help bring about change. Much critical theory indeed remained optimistic even after the war. The work of Marcuse, for example, remained wedded to the idea of effective political action into the 1960s—hence his adoption by the students in the United States during that period as a leading exemplar of radical politics (Marcuse 1972b; Bronner 1994: chs. 10–11; Bokina and Lukes 1995). Similar points could be made of a number of other former Frankfurt School adherents, for example, Erich Fromm (Bronner 1994: ch. 10). However, the central duo of the Frankfurt School, Adorno and Horkheimer, displayed a very different trajectory. Their writing during World War II, and Adorno’s at least thereafter, was much more pessimistic. Indeed, it is difficult to resist the sense that, at least from their joint authorship of Dialectic of Enlightenment during the 1940s, the intellectual relationship between the two altered to the extent that whereas prior to the war Horkheimer was the senior partner, as it were, after the war Adorno was elevated to that position. The key text was, indeed, Dialectic of Enlightenment, and in it they presented a deeply pessimistic view of the Enlightenment as a whole and of the possibilities for transformation in the contemporary context (Adorno and Horkheimer 1944/1979). Unquestionably, the experience of the rise of Nazism in Germany and the revelations about the Holocaust played their part in this pessimism, but other reasons lay deeper still. Adorno, in particular, came to believe that the exploitative and oppressive aspects of modern society were now so embedded, and so protean, that they were continuing to gobble up even those aspects of life that had previously remained potentially independent, such as Adorno’s beloved “culture”—hence, of course, his mordant and bitter delineation of the emerging “culture industry,” or the commodification of creativity. His writings were, he came to believe, a message in a bottle for some future generation that might, if it was lucky, live in a totally transfigured time. He remained the great Hegelian, still alive to the possibilities of dialectical contradictions to the end, but his overview was always pessimistic. I shall come back to this point in a moment. In this chapter I examine the parameters of critical thinking in international relations, which seeks to solve the problem of order by, so to speak, abolishing it; it seeks to transform the states system—and perforce much else as well. The point is that critical theory hardly speaks with one mind on this: It has, so to speak, two modes or faces, optimistic and pessimistic, each of which is locked in dialogue with the other. The optimistic view is now most persuasively put by the most significant contemporary representative of the Frankfurt School—significantly also, its most Kantian—to wit, Jürgen Habermas (see, for example,
96
Critique in Critical IR Theory
Outhwaite 1994; Held 1980). Habermas’s influence on contemporary critical theory in all of its variants is almost impossible to overstate. Both in his native Germany and elsewhere, especially in the United States, Habermas has become a major influence.2 Most especially in the current context, he has been far and away the most influential critical theorist as far as critical theory in international relations is concerned. With rather more qualifications and hesitations, such optimism is shared by the éminence grise of critical IR theory—and by the most influential Gramscian, Robert Cox, as well as by some of his friends and followers, such as Stephen Gill. It is also the view of some of the most robust feminist scholars of international relations, for example, Ann Tickner (Tickner 1992); and it is shared with various emendations of content or temper by many working in what is now called critical security studies, for example, and especially, Ken Booth (Booth 1991a, 1991b, 1995). And though this is less relevant here, it is a common assumption of virtually all the related critical theories I have referred to. Mark Hoffman, in his essay on the trajectory of critical theory in international studies—“Critical Theory and the Inter-Paradigm Debate”—has called this optimistic impulse utopian and, notwithstanding the extremely bad press this term has had in twentieth-century international relations, I suggest that he is right to do so (Hoffman 1987).3 It is utopian in the sense that all the best emancipatory theory is utopian, and as the early Frankfurt School was, following the sense of utopia made famous in the work of Adorno’s friend Ernst Bloch’s magnificent The Principle of Hope (Bloch 1986; also useful is Geoghan 1995). I want to suggest, in fact, that the emancipatory project of critical theory in IR—as opposed to, for example, its value as a salutary discourse— depends on this optimism. Indeed, I want to suggest that notwithstanding all their differences, all those committed to an emancipatory project in contemporary world politics share this optimistic impulse. Thus, however much they might differ from Frankfurt School critical theory in emphasis and orientation, they will perforce share the belief that the progressive transformation of society is possible. They must.4 However, I suggest that there are problems inherent in this view, that the project of emancipation in critical theory at one and the same time develops what we might call a dark side. It is this dark side that was the source of Adorno’s pessimism and it is this side, I suggest, that critical theory in international relations must confront if it is to make good on its emancipatory project.
The Achievements of Critical Theory First, I need to offer an overview interpretation of how the optimistic strand of critical theory manifests itself in Frankfurt School–influenced critical IR
Negative Dialectic?
97
theory. I shall do so first through the work of the foremost critical theorist of international relations, Andrew Linklater. Linklater is, without doubt, the most penetrating critical IR theorist writing in the tradition of the Frankfurt School. Inasmuch as the future of critical theory lies with critical international relations theory, a view subscribed to by a number of “noninternational” critical theorists as well as—as you might expect—by a number of international critical theorists, it seems certain that Linklater’s influence will grow.5 Linklater has recently provided a useful and powerful interpretation of what he considers to have been the achievements of critical theory, and he has amplified this interpretation in his most recent book (Linklater 1996b, 1998). He thinks, in brief, that critical theory has four main achievements. First, it has taken issue with positivism by arguing that knowledge always reflects preexisting social purposes and interests. In the context of IR theory this argument has led to powerful criticisms of rationalist theory and what Linklater calls a “gradual recovery of a project of enlightenment and emancipation reworked to escape the familiar pitfalls of idealism.” Second, critical theory stands opposed to claims that the existing structures of the social world are immutable and “examines the prospects for greater freedom immanent within existing social relations.” Third, critical theory learns from and overcomes the weaknesses inherent in Marxism, emphasizing forms of social learning, drawing very heavily on Habermas’s reconstruction of historical materialism, and opening up new possibilities for constructing a “historical sociology with an emancipatory purpose.” Fourth, critical theory judges social arrangements by their capacity to embrace open dialogue with all others and envisages new forms of political community which break with unjustified exclusion. . . . Critical theory . . . envisages the use of unconstrained discourse to determine the moral significance of national boundaries and to examine the possibility of postsovereign forms of political life. (Linklater 1996b: 279–280)
Linklater also suggests that various forms of postpositivist theory in international relations can all agree that “reaching an understanding [which may not culminate in a moral consensus] captures the most important respect in which critical theory, post-modernism, feminism and also philosophical hermeneutics are involved in a common project” (Linklater 1996b: 293). He implies that it is through this process, very much tied in his view to a Habermasian discourse ethics, that the states system can be transcended and human beings emancipated, since it is through this possibility that we can begin to articulate what it might mean to live in “post-sovereign” communities, and thus transcend the “sovereign” communities of the states system. There are two points I want to draw attention to here. The first is the
98
Critique in Critical IR Theory
extent to which, as Linklater presents it, critical theory has a project—the emancipatory project—that comprises a fourfold set of developments, each of which build on each other and reinforce each other, thus opening the way to still further “achievements” in which critical theory will “maintain its faith in the Enlightenment project and defend universalism in its ideal of open dialogue not only between fellow citizens but, more radically, between all members of the human species” (Linklater 1996b: 296). The second is the extent to which this view of critical theory subsumes a good deal of the substantive agenda of international society theory and constructivism and liberalism without necessarily accepting the methodologies of any. As the article makes clear, and as recent work in critical IR theory demonstrates, the plausibility of this position turns on whether discourse ethics provides for genuinely emancipatory theory. For critical IR theory, as Richard Devetak has recently noted, “emancipation can be understood as the establishment of a community which allows and protects the development of universal autonomy. . . . The question [thus] arises as to how . . . to reconstruct world politics so as to extend to the entire species a rational, just and democratic organization of politics” (Devetak 1996b: 169). The answer that the leading critical IR theorists give is drawn, very largely, from Habermas’s attempt to develop a discourse ethics that recognizes the necessity of universalist principles while not doing violence to the fact of diversity. Discourse ethics, of course, depends on Habermas’s general theory of communicative action (Habermas 1984, 1989a; see also Outhwaite 1994: 68–120; Bernstein 1995: 35–57, 88–135), which emphasizes the centrality of consent to intelligible communication. As Devetak puts it, Communicating subjects [need] to rationalize or account for their beliefs and actions in terms which are intelligible to others and which they can then accept or contest. Similarly, social norms and institutions must also be submitted to scrutiny and argumentation if they are to maintain legitimacy. At such moments when a principle, social norm or institution loses legitimacy or when consensus breaks down, discourse ethics enters the fray as a means of consensually deciding upon new principles or institutional arrangements. . . . Newly arrived at political principles, norms or institutional arrangements can only be said to be valid if they can meet with the approval of all those who would be affected by them. (Devetak 1996b: 171)
He goes on to point out three things about discourse ethics: It is universalistic, it is democratic, and it is a form of moral, practical reasoning that is “not simply guided by utilitarian calculations or expediency, nor is it guided by an imposed concept of the good life. Rather, it is guided by justice” (169).
Negative Dialectic?
99
The implications of this view for world politics have been developed in differing ways by different critical theorists. However, in general terms, as Devetak says, three broad implications stand out. The first is concerned with the evolution of more generally democratic forms of global governance and is predicated on an explicit critique of the state as simply inadequate, both practically and ethically, for contemporary decisionmaking. As David Held, the critical theorist who has perhaps done most to develop this line of argument, notes, “Whose consent is necessary and whose participation is justified in decisions concerning, for instance, AIDS, or acid rain, or the use of non-renewable resources? What is the relevant constituency, national, regional or international?” (cited by Devetak 1996b: 171; see also Held 1992, 1995). Second, and perhaps potentially most immediately fruitful, discourse ethics offers a way of thinking about and regulating conflict. The critical theorist who has developed this line of argument most thoroughly and interestingly is Mark Hoffman (Hoffman 1992). Again, discourse ethics offers a way of being inclusive without denying difference. Third, Devetak suggests that discourse ethics “offers a means of criticising and justifying the principles by which the species organizes itself politically, that is it reflects on the principles of inclusion and exclusion” (Devetak 1996b: 172). Since in principle no one should be excluded from any process that affects them, actually or potentially, this becomes a very clear cosmopolitan universalism that suggests that the “problem of order” can openly be overcome through the progressive evolution of what Linklater calls the “social bond of all with all” (Linklater 1993: 119). Critical IR theory is thus committed, I think, to a version of institutional as well as moral cosmopolitanism, to use Charles Beitz’s well-known terms (Beitz 1993). 6 Indeed, Linklater, toward the end of both Beyond Realism and Marxism and The Transformation of Political Community, has made explicit that in his view the future of critical theory depends on its ability to develop analyses and institutions that actually help to restructure world politics along the lines suggested by this analysis.
Negative Dialectic? The question arises, however, How can critical theory, even on its own terms, be emancipatory in the required sense? I suggest that in fact critical theory has a profound ambiguity about the question of emancipation, that critical theory is engaged, in a sense, in a negative dialectic with itself on this question. This ambiguity can be most clearly seen in the work of Adorno, and so I shall turn to him before assessing the implications of this reading for critical IR theory. It would obviously be impossible to offer even a sketch of a thinker as
100
Critique in Critical IR Theory
complex and nuanced (and as committed to the claim, as he often insisted, that “true philosophy resists paraphrase” [Jay 1984a: 11]) as Adorno in the space I have available. All I want to do is illustrate why I think Adorno’s thought is problematic for the emancipatory project—on which, I have suggested, the versions of critical theory (both general and international) that I previously discussed depend (on Adorno, see Bernstein 1995; Rose 1978, 1992; Honneth 1985, 1992a). To do this, I first want to develop Jay Bernstein’s recent reformulation of critical theory along Adornoesque, rather than Habermasian lines. He argues first that critical theory is not a theory of society or a wholly homogenous school of thinkers or a method. Critical theory, rather, is a tradition of social thought that, at least in part, takes its cue from its opposition to the wrongs and ills of modern societies on the one hand, and the forms of theorizing that simply go along with or seek to legitimate those societies on the other hand. (Bernstein 1995: 11)
The three basic criteria of this tradition are a noninstrumental conception of reason and cognition, a nonfunctionalist conception of culture, and the harmonization of both (Bernstein 1995: 28). However, the central root of critical theory for Bernstein is the recognition—originally laid out by Adorno—that the dilemmas of modernity have a common root, directly or indirectly, in the abstractive achievements (and they are achievements) of instrumental reason, which produces two things. First, it produces “domination” in the sense of what he calls the domination of “exchange value over use value,” seen as the result of the “universal development of the exchange system,” part of a continuous rationalization process within modern societies that leads to the domination of institutions over people. Second, it produces “nihilism” in that this “rationalization process” possesses “three logically discriminable features; proceduralism (formalism or methodologism as applied to social sanctions), substitutablity and end-indifference,” which lead to a continuous devaluation of the highest values. These questions become the problem of justice and the problem of reason for Adorno, and, taken together, Bernstein suggests they represent, respectively, the Weberian and the Nietzschean departure points for contemporary theory. These issues have, however, tended to be analyzed apart from each other. As Bernstein puts it, Traditional Marxism [and one might add most contemporary analytic moral and political theory] tends to focus on the question of injustice . . . making its trajectory at one with the most advanced moments of liberal political theory. Conversely, the tradition of existentialism and phenome-
Negative Dialectic?
101
nology [and one must add here most contemporary poststructural thinking as well] . . . directs itself to the problem of nihilism. . . . Adorno’s original insight . . . was the identification of the common root . . . and hence the demand for a theory that would address each dilemma without losing sight of the other. (Bernstein 1995: 28; emphasis added)
In terms of the basic criteria that Bernstein lays out for a critical theory, it is clear that the first requirement, a noninstrumental conception of reason, addresses the first problem and that the second, a nonfunctionalist conception of culture, addresses the second. However, as Bernstein puts it, “The harmonization requirement constrains the satisfaction of the first criterion such that it becomes answerable to the demands of the second” (Bernstein 1995: 28). This discussion provides Bernstein with a way of reviewing the obvious differences between Habermas and Adorno. “Fundamentally,” he says, they differ with respect to the weight and focus they offer to the justice and meaning questions: Habermas believes that Adorno slights the question of justice in his engagement with the nihilism question, hence giving undue significance to the role of art in his theory and, by implication, espousing a position which could only be satisfied through a Utopian reenchantment of the social and natural worlds. From an Adornoesque perspective, Habermas’ focus on the justice problem entails surrender over the question of nihilism, falsely assuming that total disenchantment would not be existentially equivalent to total reification. (Bernstein 1995: 29)
Bernstein’s argument is centered on the claim that in his complex and profoundly important reworking of the central assumptions of critical theory, Habermas holds to the basic project (what he calls the “very idea”) of a critical theory, but the theory that results is skewed because in evolving its centerpiece, the theory of communicative action, he develops it primarily in the context of the problem of justice and it is this that then leads to an account of the problem of nihilism. In other words, the problem of nihilism is constrained by the problem of justice rather than, as Bernstein and Adorno would suggest, the problem of justice being constrained by the problem of nihilism. The result is that the dialectic on which critical theory depends becomes inverted, negative in a profoundly un-Adornoesque way. If Bernstein’s reading is a plausible one, there is an equally profound implication for the emancipatory project that is held to be at the center of critical international relations theory. As we saw, one of the features of contemporary critical theory—and especially of critical IR theory—is the sense that not only should critical theory be able to critique modern societies, it also should answer the Where’s the beef? question. It should also be able to offer action-guiding principles and have institutional and political recommendations of an institutionally cosmopolitan kind.
102
Critique in Critical IR Theory
However, on the Adornoesque reading offered by Bernstein, such a view is untenable. “In locating a form of reasoning that is not instrumental and which, remember, includes a cognition of ends, and a materialist conception of culture which is compatible with such a practical reason, we exhaust the demand that theory be practical,” he says (Bernstein 1995: 19). Moreover, first, “whether or not, at any given time, the contradictions, suppressions and forms of domination in a society entail macro-potentialities for collective action is itself a historically contingent matter,” and second, the demand that theory must have a “praxial dimension” itself runs the risk of collapsing critical theory back into traditional theory by making it dependent on instrumental conceptions of rationality (Bernstein 1995: 19). In other words, for Bernstein and Adorno, the problem of nihilism constrains the problem of justice precisely by making an impossibility the sort of institutional-political recommendations that Linklater has made central to critical IR theory. Any such considerations cannot be thought through in advance but rather would have to depend on the contingencies of the given context. The only way around this is to attenuate the common root of the problems of modernity: to concentrate, like Habermas (and Linklater), on the problem of justice and to ignore or downplay the problem of nihilism. This, however, is at best a partial critical theory and cannot live up to Adorno’s hopes for it.
Emancipation, Critique, and Ambiguity It is this danger, then, that critical IR theory might be said to be currently courting and, at least to some extent, must court if it is to perform the task it has set itself. In the first place, it is critical theory as an emancipatory project that requires, as Linklater suggests, “light cast on present possibilities” and thus runs the risk alluded to previously. It is therefore the notion of emancipation in this context that creates the problem—rather than the project of critical theory per se. It is noteworthy, however, that emancipation was not one of Adorno’s major concerns. It is precisely this, of course, that has irritated so many emancipatory critical theorists (Bronner 1994: 199–200). However, if critical theory cannot be emancipatory in the required sense, it can add nothing to reflection on world politics as critical theory. Everything would remain, as it were, contingent on history and context. Whatever critical theory might be able to say about the problems of justice and nihilism held together, it would be silent on the question of praxis. This predicament applies especially to critical IR theory. Think, for example of Linklater’s four achievements of critical theory in international relations. The first two—that is, the critique of positivism and the insistence on the mutability of social structures—are facets that I think both
Negative Dialectic?
103
Habermas and Adorno would accept as a legitimate part of critical theory discussed by Bernstein. However, as Linklater emphasizes, the last two, namely the attempt to develop an emancipation-oriented sociology and the stress on the human capacity for unconstrained dialogue, are fashioned around the reconstruction of historical materialism developed by Habermas. As such, these would be vulnerable, I think, to the charges leveled at that project by Bernstein and others. The point here is to suggest that the emancipatory project in this context runs the risk of tipping critical theory back into traditional theory and, as a result, could not offer a treatment of emancipation free of the corruptions of instrumental rationality. Only if Habermas’s reconstruction—and that developed by some of his more recent followers—can escape the Adornoesque critique will emancipation in this sense be a plausible trajectory for critical theory.
Strategic Emancipation or Tactical Ethics? I want to emphasize that in many respects, critical IR theory represents one of the most humane and generally hopeful accounts of contemporary world politics available. Its insights are profound and its sensibilities far more interesting than much of what passes for reflection (even theory) in international relations more generally. However, I think that Adorno’s problem, if I may call it that, is real and has not yet been adequately dealt with. In this penultimate section of the chapter, I offer one reading as to why that might be so and suggest some implications of this reading for the emancipatory project in international relations theory. I want to start with an unlikely source (the following draws from and develops on Rengger 1996). In the Republic, in perhaps the most famous of his many images, Plato portrays society (any and all societies) as a cave. Some insist that the cave is all there is, but others claim that there is light outside the cave and that, perhaps, it is only because of this light that we see in the cave at all. In our current context, let us suggest that most international relations scholarship, realist, liberal, constructivist, and societal, either assumes that the cave—international society, the international system, or what you will—is all there is (that is relevant) or is agnostic (and uninterested) concerning the possibility that there might be anything outside the cave, however outside is understood. Therein, in many respects, lies the attraction of IR scholarship (a clear focus, an agreed set of problems) but also the site of its greatest weaknesses. In Platonic terminology, it is left trying to see in the cave by virtue only of the pale light that exists there, and what it sees, of course, is shadows. That does not mean that some very interesting accounts of the shadows cannot be given; nor does it mean that the shadows are unimportant, for we all remain in the cave and the shadows are, of course, real for us.
104
Critique in Critical IR Theory
Emancipatory theory in international relations stands outside this mainstream of contemporary IR scholarship, however. Emancipatory theorists seek their anchorage in that proud and much broader tradition that encompasses Kant and Hegel, Marx and Max Weber, Émile Durkheim and Freud. They know there is light outside the cave—the light of real historical processes—and they seek to let it in so that the cave can be seen whole, in full light. Doing that, they believe, would transform the cave, for it would be observable by all who care to see it for what it truly is: the completion of the Enlightenment project. Indeed, their challenge is precisely that it is the corruption of the Enlightenment project by the growing dominance of instrumental rationality that has made IR theory—and indeed other aspects of contemporary social science, especially the “queen of the social sciences,” economics— the tool of the powerful rather than the weapon of critique that it should and could be. However, Adorno’s problem casts a dark shadow on this claim. For Adorno, the danger is that Marxism in its traditional mode and, as Bernstein suggests, critical theory in its Habermasian mode run the risk of becoming traditional theory, of becoming domesticated or co-opted by instrumental rationality. At this point, however, many sympathetic to critical IR theory will surely insist that critical theory is not so at risk. For critical theorists are of course deeply aware of the problems of instrumental rationality; indeed, in large part they build their critique on their distrust of it. This claim is, I think, true, but it misses the full force of Adorno’s suspicion. To bring that out, I want to draw on a distinction taken from the French thinker Michel de Certeau. De Certeau distinguishes between strategy and tactics in a very particular way. For de Certeau, strategy is the calculus of force relationships which becomes possible when a subject of will and power (a proprietor, an enterprise, a city, a scientific investigation) can be isolated from an environment. A strategy assumes a place that can be circumscribed as proper and thus serve as the basis for generating relations with an exterior distinct from it (competitors, adversaries, . . . targets or objects of research). Political, economic and scientific rationality has been constructed on this model. (de Certeau 1988: xix)
In other words, he understands the term strategy to be analogous to Adorno’s instrumental rationality (although there are differences, to which I shall come back in a moment). Tactics, in contrast, is a “‘calculus’ which cannot count on a ‘proper’ (a spatial or an institutional localization). . . . The place of the tactic belongs to the other. . . . The ‘proper’ is a victory of space over time. On the contrary, because it does not have a place, a tactic depends on time. . . . It must
Negative Dialectic?
105
constantly manipulate events in order to turn them into opportunities” (de Certeau 1988: xix). It is obvious, of course, that rationalist IR theory is, in de Certeau’s sense, a strategy. What about critical theory? The danger, I think, is that virtually all versions of the emancipatory project are becoming at the very least strategic if not fully a strategy in de Certeau’s sense. To put the matter slightly differently, critical theory contains a strategy that, I suggest, threatens to overwhelm its tactical sense. To explain, let me go back to Plato. In Plato’s story—contrary to the emancipatory project as I have presented it here—Socrates taught that the cave cannot be fundamentally transformed. This is not to say that there is no change possible; rather it is a claim about the kind of understanding the light outside the cave can provide. Socrates is a guide; he does not seek to bring light to the cave but to help those who wish to leave the cave (and are able to do so) to experience the light themselves and, as a result, understand themselves and the cave better. In so doing, they can balance understanding of the realities of the cave—the shadows—with their knowledge of what the sun illuminates in them. Socrates suggests that when the philosopher returns to the cave, it is the philosopher who by definition is transformed, not the cave—the transformation of which is, at best, contingent. I suggest that the sort of knowledge we have upon returning to the cave, if we take Socrates’ route seriously, is tactical knowledge as outlined by de Certeau. As Adorno suggests, the cave remains what it has always been; it is we—as analysts, as actors, as humans—who are changed, but of course we cannot be properly changed in the absence of change in the cave. The dilemma that I think Adorno could not escape (and that for all their power modern Adorno advocates such as Gillian Rose and Bernstein cannot escape either) is that in trying to change the cave one inevitably and inescapably becomes embroiled in the clutches of instrumental reason. This is why Adorno was reduced, finally, to suggesting that his work was messages in a bottle for an age that had—somehow—escaped the clutches of instrumental reason. He effectively abandoned any search for a way of getting to such a world because he realized that with his own analysis, he could get there only by using the methods that would forever block his passage. In other words, the problem is simply that in acting in the world as it is, as we must do to bring about change (even for the better), we have to partake of the forms of instrumental rationality, in which case we tip back into traditional theory, and any emancipation that results would have to be seen in that way. To develop a research agenda for change, we must therefore have a strategic conception of what is required to develop or open up the system rather than simply a tactical response to what the system imposes on us. Tactics, as de Certeau says, are always reactive; the emancipatory
106
Critique in Critical IR Theory
project in its dominant modes in contemporary international relations theory is not—it is, and must be, proactive.
Conclusion If all of the preceding argument is plausible, then the emancipatory project in IR theory faces a fateful—and possibly a fatal—dilemma. To make good on its emancipatory agenda, critical IR theory will have to show both that the Adorno problem can be resolved and that it can add something to other ways of dealing with the task of social change that distinguishes it from the more radical forms of liberalism, without tipping it back into the clutches of instrumental rationality. I do not suppose for a moment that critical theory is without the resources to perform this task. As Linklater himself suggests, one of its great strengths is the alliances it can build with other forms of critique. There is therefore much that critical theory might do to seek to overcome this negative dialectic. The various strands of so-called postpositivist theory in international relations do indeed reinforce each other on certain key issues, and it might be that this is one issue where the insights of some poststructural thought—so close often to Adorno’s own—might usefully be brought to bear. Critical theorists, even Habermas in practice if not always in theory, could also point to their emphasis on totality. It is the emphasis on the whole, on interaction and interrelations, that can, they might suggest, help them avoid various forms of reification. Surely in this context they might avoid collapsing tactics into strategy (in de Certeau’s sense) but hold them together dialectically. My response would be to admit that it is perhaps a fruitful avenue for critical theory (and indeed for some aspects of post-Nietzschean, poststructural thought) to explore. However, it crucially depends on the initial assumptions developed by critical theory being true—depends, in other words, on the common root being a necessary rather than a contingent problem of modernity. This claim is rooted in the philosophical parentage of critical theory and poststructuralism, of course; they are profoundly the children of Nietzsche and Weber, however much they might have rebelled at parental authority. Along with much twentieth-century thought, they are deeply suspicious of and ambivalent about the rise of the methods and institutions of a science that seems unstoppable and unanswerable and yet that constantly threatens, they think, to depersonalize and dehumanize. It is this threat that gives rise chiefly, I think, to Adorno’s despair at the modern world. If instrumental rationality is the villain and the two greatest and most protean forces of the modern world, capitalism and science, are precisely the areas
Negative Dialectic?
107
where instrumental rationality is most at home, it would be difficult not to despair. Yet critical theory never really considers denying the initial assumption that Nietzsche and Weber made (and that Heidegger, Adorno, and today’s theorists have all made), to wit, that the developments they trace—and about which they are, I think, often extremely acute—must mean what they take them to mean. That these developments often have meant what they have been taken to mean is certainly true, but that they must mean what they are thought to mean seems to me simply an article of faith. In other words, one is free to put together science, history, and society in different ways without assuming that the way they are together now is the only way they might be put together. There are many different naturalisms, and only some seem to me to deserve the strictures critical theory visits upon them all. If one can take this approach, it might be that the “iron cage”—or, to use Adorno’s version, the “totally administered world”—is rather less allencompassing than might be supposed, and there might be a route out of it different from the one developed by critical theory. This different route may be one not so hostile to instrumental rationality per se and therefore one more able to put together strategy and tactics in both intellectually and politically fertile ways. Of course, it is not part of my task here to outline such a view. In any case, nothing that I have said should be taken to suggest that critical theory—in international relations and more generally—should be regarded as anything other than one of the most important and, both actually and potentially, fruitful theoretical departures of the twentieth century. All I would say is that given the negative dialectic that, I believe, lies at the heart of critical theory, its future is much more uncertain than many of its advocates might wish. And given this uncertainty, it might be advisable to take a long hard look at its grounding assumptions. It might after all be the case that there is a better way.
Notes This is an extensive revision of a paper originally given at the Critical Theory and World Politics Conference at Aberystwyth. All participants to the conference should be thanked (and none blamed) for the use to which I have put their very helpful comments. I must also thank Hayward Alker, Jay Bernstein, Chris Brown, Ian Forbes, Mark Hoffman, Andrew Linklater, Craig Murphy, Onora O’Neill, Maurizio Passerein D’Entreves, Ann Tickner, and Richard Wyn Jones for many helpful discussions over several years on all aspects of critical theory, both in general and in the IR context. It almost (but not quite) makes me think there might be something in Habermas’s notion of an ideal speech situation of unconstrained communication! If there was, these worthies would certainly be ideal citizens for it.
108
Critique in Critical IR Theory
1. And sometimes an even wider use is intended. Many contemporary international relations theorists, for example, refer to other constructivists as critical theorists as well. This is clearly the view that lies behind the recent critiques of critical theory by John Mearsheimer (1994–1995) and Stephen Walt (1996). 2. It is probably true, and not irrelevant in the present context, that we are now witnessing the effective emergence of a third generation of critical theorists in both Europe and North America whose concerns are still wider than those of Habermas and certainly include, increasingly, questions that are traditionally central for international relations (such as development, globalization, democratization). This third generation of theorists would include, by my reckoning, Axel Honneth, who has inherited Habermas’s chair at Frankfurt, Seyla Benhabib, Nancy Fraser, Ken Baynes, James Bohman, David Held, and possibly such scholars as Maurizio Passerein D’Entreves. Many of these have written on IR—for example, the essays in Bohman and Lutz-Bachmann (1997)—and Held has been a powerful advocate of “cosmopolitan democracy,” one of the real growth areas in contemporary IR. Taken together with the work of scholars such as Linklater, who is more or less of an age with these figures, these developments presage a real growth in critical IR theory over the next few years. 3. See the subsequent exchange in Rengger 1988 and Hoffman 1988. Since there has been some comment on this exchange (see, for example, George 1994 and Smith 1995) and since, despite the fact that Hoffman and I later published a joint essay amending our respective positions (Rengger and Hoffman 1992), some of this comment has been rather inaccurate, it seems appropriate to correct any misperceptions there might have been. Hoffman is usually seen (correctly) as an advocate of critical theory, I often (and incorrectly) as an opponent of it from a broadly poststructural position. At the risk of sounding like a witness to the House Un-American Activities Committee, I am not now, nor have I ever been a poststructuralist. Of course, there is a good deal in poststructural IR theory with which I agree—as I do indeed with critical theory—but there is also much that I dissent from. My intention in my original response to Hoffman was merely to point out that critical theory in IR studies was already a mixture of the emancipatory and the poststructural and that, as a result, Hoffman’s version of critical theory (i.e., Frankfurt School– and Gramscian-inspired emancipatory critical theory) was unlikely to be the next stage of international relations theory. I would now put this view rather differently, and indeed, that is what I am doing in this chapter. 4. It is worth pointing out that a number of the early critical theorists became increasingly mystical, even theological, in their old age (this is true even of Adorno, though he also remained a resolute atheist, a mixture very reminiscent of Bloch). I suggest that the reason is simply that one of the strongest ways of being utopian in the required sense is a theological way, even if there is the minor inconvenience of (probably) having to believe in God. Contemporary critical theorists, for example, Habermas and Linklater, do not do this, of course—at least not yet. 5. It is interesting in this context that Linklater is virtually ignored in mainstream attacks on critical theory. There might be any number of reasons for this. I suggest that one powerful one is simply how difficult it is for mainstream scholars to attack Linklater without engaging in genuine debate with his Habermasianderived project. It is much safer and far easier—given their own assumptions—to restrict their criticisms to constructivists they can co-opt (or try to) or poststructuralists they can patronize (or try to). As Linklater’s own brilliant demolition job on neorealism shows, critical theory is extremely difficult to do, partly because it seeks to radicalize the very project mainstream scholars such as Keohane see themselves committed to.
Negative Dialectic?
109
6. Effectively, for Beitz, cosmopolitanism should be understood as being both inclusive (it encompasses all local points of view) and nonperspectival (there is no foreground or background). However, there are two ways of seeing this. Moral cosmopolitanism concerns itself with the way that any institutional arrangement in world politics should be justified and evaluated. “Its crux is the idea that each person is equally the subject of moral concern, or, alternatively, that in the justification of choices one must take the prospects of everyone affected equally into account” (Beitz 1993: 124). Institutional cosmopolitanism, however, is concerned with “the political constitution of the world. . . . Although the details may vary, the distinctive common feature is some ideal of world political organization in which states and state-like units have significantly diminished authority in comparison with the status quo” (124). Beitz’s cosmopolitan liberalism is a moral cosmopolitanism but not really an institutional cosmopolitanism.
7 GLOBAL REALISM: UNMASKING POWER IN THE INTERNATIONAL POLITICAL ECONOMY Jeffrey Harrod
After the defeat of the aristocratic government, the middle classes developed a system of indirect domination. They replaced the traditional division into the governing and governed classes, and the military method of open violence characteristic of aristocratic rule, with the invisible chains of economic dependence. This economic system operated through a network of seemingly equalitarian legal rules which concealed the very existence of power relations. —Hans J. Morgenthau (1967) Nevertheless, economic considerations derive such weight as they have from the fact that economics are one—and an essential—aspect both of political and military power. The activities of monopolist enterprises on the national and international levels deserve attention by the student of international relations for an additional reason. He can analyse here the workings of power politics in a field in which all means of power, short of military power, are applied. —Georg Schwarzenberger (1951)
In this chapter it is first argued that realism as an approach to the comprehension of society and politics—a “real,” or societal, realism—must be distinguished from a realism that emerged as central to the study of interstate relations, or international relations (IR) realism. Realism as an approach and a philosophy was essentially developed for and directed at relations within societies, and its application to relations between societies—nation states—not only has introduced confusion in the discussion of international politics but also has hindered its more useful application to global society. The second claim is that the contemporary rise of the power of the corpora111
112
Critique in Critical IR Theory
tion at the expense of the state has produced in the current period powerdisguising rationalities that, more than ever, require the application of the original realism project of unmasking social and political power. In conclusion, it is noted that a global realism, as part of critical theory, is needed as an approach to comprehend contemporary developments and thereby lay the foundations to change them.
Societal, or Real, Realism Realism as an approach, or as a worldview, has a variety of meanings in philosophy and art. Most of these surround the notion that there is something real to be observed, discovered, or proven and that other approaches disguise or distort such a reality. When such an approach was used in a political or social analysis, the reality identified focused on the sources, uses, and objectives of power. Societal or political realism thus evolved as the approach that placed emphasis on power and, in doing so, absorbed, rejected, or subsumed more theological, naturalistic, or systemic explanations. However, the original intention and objective of such realism was the study of relations among individuals and social groups and between the governors and the governed. The extension of such an approach to relations between formally delimited, geographically and culturally distant social aggregations—nation states—was unfortunate, simplistic, and dysfunctional, as is often the case in the application of approaches and theories designed for one use and one environment to dissimilar ones. This original, or what I will call here “real,” or societal, realism needs to therefore be distinguished from its extension to an approach or theory in international relations, or IR realism. For the purpose of making the distinction between real and IR realism, I have taken the work of two of the earlier so-called IR realists—Georg Schwarzenberger and Hans Morgenthau. This is done in full awareness that in international relations these scholars may not necessarily be representative of the realists and neorealist writers conventionally considered to be IR realists. Their selection is partly symbolic and partly substantive. They are symbolic because I will argue that in their work is embodied the origins of the intellectual trajectory in which societal realism was applied to the study of international relations. The choice is substantive in that they represent a tradition in approaches to social theory and analysis that is found at the core of many of the intellectual products from continental Europe. In this “continental philosophy” there has been an emphasis on humans as members of communities and societies rather than as individuals and on the contradiction among ideas based on reason and created within societies by different forces and for different purposes (West 1993).
Global Realism
113
These two authors influenced a whole generation of writing within academic international relations and, in the case of Morgenthau through the impact of his books, the practice of U.S. foreign policy in the training of diplomatic and political personnel. Georg Schwarzenberger’s Power Politics (1951, first published in 1949) saw three editions and many translations and was particularly important in Japan and Latin America. Hans Morgenthau’s Politics Among Nations (1967, first published in 1948) was, it hardly bears to repeat, the basic university text in the United States (whether used positively or negatively) for international relations courses for more than two decades. In understanding their approach, we must consider the similarity of their backgrounds. Both were German, both left Germany in the 1930s essentially as escapees, and both had studied law. Thus they both wrote in English for a primarily Anglo-American readership. Naturally, both were influenced by the writers of early-twentieth-century Germany and continental Europe. For Morgenthau, Max Weber was important, whereas Schwarzenberger used Arthur Schopenhauer and Ferdinand Töennies to elaborate the concepts of society and community, which for him yielded the crucial distinction between a power-oriented society based on “interest and fear” and an idealistic community based on “self-sacrifice and love” (Schwarzenberger 1951: 12). In basing their writings on the elements of realism found within the works of these writers and such others as Joseph Schumpeter, Karl Mannheim, and Bertrand Russell, they were societal realists, that is, as with most of their own intellectual mentors, their original focus was on the discrete societal level. This observation applies more to Morgenthau than to Schwarzenberger, although in lectures the latter was most insistent on a power approach at all levels. Furthermore, Schwarzenberger’s definition of international relations hints at the origin of the tools of analysis and the problems it would bequeath. For him the study of international relations was “the branch of sociology which is concerned with international society” (Schwarzenberger 1951: 8), of which nation states were members. It is perhaps significant, then, that neither of them were greatly concerned with the intellectual input to classical IR realism. Niccoló Machiavelli, for example, is one such source (although, in fact, his writing was more about the internal governance of principalities than the relationships among them [Hale 1996]), and there is sufficient material within The Prince to make it a founding text for IR realism. Yet Morgenthau was overtly critical of Machiavelli’s discounting of the importance of the opposing force of morality and principle within power relations (Morgenthau 1967: 220), and Schwarzenberger was inclined to see the Machiavellian view as too simplistic (Schwarzenberger 1951: 219) and
114
Critique in Critical IR Theory
therefore respected him more for revelation of the disguises of power rather than as a guide to action. In seeking to reveal the nature and source of power and its mechanism of operation, they were to some extent like other realists reacting to the excessive romanticism, legalism, and ideology that sought to disguise them. E. H. Carr, considered to be another realist, noted in his Twenty Years’ Crisis, written in 1939, that it was “written with the deliberate aim of counteracting the glaring and dangerous defect of nearly all thinking, both academic and popular, about international politics in English-speaking countries from 1919–1939—the almost total neglect of the factor of power” (Carr 1946: vii). But Schwarzenberger and Morgenthau were as much concerned about the disguise and operation of power as the fact that power was being ignored. Morgenthau, for example, was particularly scathing about those who believed in the essence of the Kellogg-Briand Pact of 1928, under which all the fifty-four signatory states agreed “to renounce war as an instrument of national policy in their relations with one another” (Morgenthau 1967: 265); Schwarzenberger noted that the origin of this pact was the French desire to prevent U.S. use of force against France, whereas in response, “the US State Department served warning that more than one power could play the game of drafting seemingly innocuous pacts with arrière-pensées of its own” (Schwarzenberger 1951: 505). Schwarzenberger’s central question in revealing power was to ask the heuristic question, Qui bono?—Who benefits? Asking the question, Who benefits? was the first step to unraveling what he called “power politics in disguise.” Morgenthau went further in moving toward developing an axiom about social power itself: Actually, however, the very threat of a world where power reigns not only supreme, but without rival, engenders the revolt against power which is as universal as the aspiration for power itself. To stave off this revolt, to pacify the resentment of opposition that arises when the drive for power is recognised for what it is, those that seek power employ, as we have seen, ideologies for the concealment of their aims. What is actually an aspiration for power, then appears to be something different, something that is in harmony with the demands of reason, morality and justice. (Morgenthau 1967: 219)
Realism of this type is therefore also that of skepticism or cynicism about conventional wisdom and explanations. A realist is indeed the child in the story who is the only one in the crowd to declare that the parading emperor, who has been persuaded by tailors that he is wearing clothes, in fact has no clothes. In the story the child convinces the crowd and receives appreciation for doing so, but equally he might have been torn to pieces for destroying a myth.
Global Realism
115
The fable is apposite because the courage needed to fault conventional wisdom was in the story sourced in childlike innocence. But if the realist is an adult, such a protestation would be an act of great courage, of which Schwarzenberger was certainly aware, especially in international relations. In that area, he argued, the “threat to the freedom of research arises from unwillingness of the many to accept disagreeable truth in good humour” (Schwarzenberger 1951: 3). Thus the adoption of a realist approach may bring with it personal risks not associated with other intellectual endeavors except in ideologically inflexible, authoritarian, or totalitarian societies. The implication is that realism in any circumstance other than when power has a frank expression—where it needs no ideology or rationality to disguise it, as in tyranny or despotism—is subversive because power, as a power-maximizing device, invariably denies itself. As an illustration of the distinction between societal and IR realism, this conclusion can be contrasted with that of Barry Buzan speaking of IR realism: “Realism . . . is the natural home of those disposed towards conservative ideology” (Buzan 1996: 55).
Societal Realism and International Relations International relations as a subject area in social science was created at the end of the development of the social sciences. Whether the initial goal in forming the social sciences was to create a “neutral,” or conflict-free, study of society in the face of the engaged and class-conflict theories of Marx, the application of societal realism to them would have been problematic. It would have retarded the development of positivism (even though positivism was derived from the real realism ideas of an objective reality ready to be investigated) because power cannot easily be measured or its trajectory mathematically plotted. Positivism can research only what its method makes researchable. It can measure only the measurable. Societal realism as an approach to understanding the governance of modern societies also has holistic implications that ran counter to the demand in the social sciences for specialization and the consequent segmentation of human activity. Thus, in rejecting societal realism, the social sciences moved toward a fragmented and power-empty social science. Economics, for example, rejected power entirely when political was struck from its title (Harrod 1980). The original economists had been frankly political—that is, power identifying and considering. Even within the power-empty analysis of positivist and mechanistic economics, there were some particularly extreme developments. As IR realists applied power analysis to the national state, so international economists denied its existence in precisely the areas where it could be most easily seen. Thus, for
116
Critique in Critical IR Theory
example, international economics uncritically accepted the distortions and power-empty assumptions concerning the mid-nineteenth-century Portuguese-British trade case, which David Ricardo used to demonstrate his mathematical formulas of the advantages of free trade. By assuming that the existing pattern of trade was the result of “natural” advantage for wine in Portugal and textiles in Britain, he nullified the precipitating domestic and international power relations of industrialization and trade. These included, in this case, the trade and labor systems from which the cotton for the British textile industry was produced; the complex power relations in Europe that resulted in the Treaty of Methuen in 1705, under which Portugal had to abandon protection and development of its textile industry in favor of privileges for British merchants; and the fact that wine in Portugal was an official monopoly of the crown and courtiers. In sociology the impetus to avoid the location and objects of power meant first a scuttle into fragmented specialization, then positivism, and when the consideration of power seemed essential, as in organization theory, a resort was made to an amorphous systems approach in which power was mediated and mitigated by a system with qualities of automaticity and autonomy not so much different from those currently ascribed to a market. Even political science, despite brave attempts in the 1930s and 1940s (Lasswell 1934), found refuge in pluralism in which no power could be ascendant and in which state power within legal confines had to be accepted as actual power. The process of power elimination within the social sciences also included structural and intellectual elements. Part of that process was incessant subdivision and specious specialization that impeded the development of connectivity based on a society-wide exercise of power. In this way, for example, the suggestion of Kant for a single basic discipline—which he called anthropology—for the holistic study of humanity would never be realized. Likewise, the proposal of Wilhelm Dilthey, a historian at the turn of the twentieth century, that comprehension of humanity and society could be constructed only from historical reconstructions of the variety of life expressions (Harrod 1997) was destroyed by fragmentation long before Karl Popper felt the need to attack what he saw as the remnants of holistic analysis in The Poverty of Historicism (1961, first published in 1957). Although Popper was ambivalent about power, opposed to its absolute political variety but prepared to postulate laws relating to its partial use, the reviewer from the Times Literary Supplement quoted on the back of the 1964 edition of the book had no doubts of Popper’s intent: “[He is] one of the very few who raise the still small voice of reason and practical sagacity against the mysticism of the mass-mesmerists and power-boys.” When it came to international relations, however, it was more difficult to ignore and deny power. The central issues of the subject area, at least since the end of the 1914–1918 war, had been peace and war, and the latter
Global Realism
117
was the most overt expression of physical power. Thus international relations as a new area of social and political studies was relatively receptive to the application of realism and, in particular, to the notion that such an approach was necessary to reveal Schwarzenberger’s “power politics in disguise” and end Morgenthau’s “depreciation of political power.” In societal realism the objective of power analysis was to reveal the sources and mechanisms of power. Analysis would be needed to determine if the dominant power might be a single elite or group; a coalition of elites; a cadre located within a party, an institution, or organization; or a wide constellation of different entities. Mechanisms of power at the society level could be psychological, physical, or material or subtle and not-so-subtle combinations of all three. The analysis of power by societal realism was therefore a complex process. However, when applied to international relations, already defined as interstate relations, there was no need to search for the true source of power, for almost by definition the nation state could be the only source of power. Further, there were really few complexities of power mechanisms to investigate because the traditional means of the exercise of state power—diplomacy and war—remained exclusively central to international relations. For a better fit of societal realism to interstate relations, the state had to be made analogous to, or declared the same as, common constructs used to comprehend societies. If, as Schwarzenberger argued, international relations was a branch of sociology and the nation could not be disaggregated into individuals, classes, and groups, the nation state had to play the role of all three. Thus the personification of the state emerged as very much the language of the IR realists—the state does, the state says, the state thinks, and the state will do. Schwarzenberger went further in constructing a hierarchy out of the power endowments of the states. In this hierarchy the “great powers” were essentially the aristocratic class, or elite, as opposed to the middle and minor powers of the lower classes. But an even more important logical problem of applying societal, or real, realism to international relations concerned the objectives of such internationally wielded power. Morgenthau as a societal realist had no problem with the objectives of power within societies—power was class based and, through using the concept of the economic system, Morgenthau implied that power was used for economic gain. Thus he states: After the defeat of the aristocratic government, the middle classes developed a system of indirect domination. They replaced the traditional division into the governing and governed classes, and the military method of open violence characteristic of aristocratic rule, with the invisible chains of economic dependence. This economic system operated through a network of seemingly equalitarian legal rules which concealed the very existence of power relations. (Morgenthau 1967: 33)
118
Critique in Critical IR Theory
Yet he balked at applying such an economic motivation to relations between societies—as in interstate or imperial relations. Not only was imperialism not determined by economics but economics did not even supply a motive: “The captain of industry is no more driven towards his ‘imperialist goal’ [of achieving a monopoly] by economic necessity or personal greed than was Napoleon I” (Morgenthau 1967: 48). To support this conclusion he relied heavily on Schumpeter and quoted the latter several times: “Thus the historic evidence points to the primacy of politics over economics,” and “the rule of the financier . . . over international politics is indeed, in the words of Professor Schumpeter, ‘a newspaper fairytale, almost ludicrously at variance with the facts’” (Morgenthau 1967: 48). The final resting point in the discussion of motives for Morgenthau is then, at least in relation to imperialism, found in the “objectiveless expansion” thesis of Schumpeter. Essentially, the societal realist approach had adopted two positions in relation to the objectives of power. Either power was for material gain, as Morgenthau suggested in the previous quote, or it was for control, and thus the objectives of power could be revealed only by the results of the control so achieved. Applying these positions to interstate relations was difficult on two counts. In the first place, to define national interest as material gain necessitated disaggregating the nation state into those who most benefited and those that did not or may have even lost—in short, a class or elite analysis in which nations’ elites, rather than nations, sought specific material-based objectives, as in the case of economic imperialism. Such a position, which might have been worth discussing, meant confronting powerful myths. Schwarzenberger was cautious or ambivalent to the extreme on the economic motivation issue. “Thus, there is little material which would justify any conclusion in favour of the primacy of economics over politics in international society.” Yet, he continues, Nevertheless, economic considerations derive such weight as they have from the fact that economics are one—an essential—aspect both of political and military power. The activities of monopolist enterprises on the national and international levels deserve attention by the student of international relations for an additional reason. He can analyse here the workings of power politics in a field in which all means of power, short of military power, are applied. (Schwarzenberger 1951: 137–138)
If the objectives of power were not direct or indirect material gain, the aim of discovering the objectives of power by the results obtained could not be easily applied to the modern nation state at the international level. At the individual level the final acquisition of a promotion, a swimming pool, or a privileged position may help reveal the power relations and dynamics that preceded it. But such a procedure could not be applied to even a per-
Global Realism
119
sonified nation state. First, to seek results of power acquisition at the interstate level was too much of a short-term project, as the issues at that level of peace, war, and imperialism were of historic dimensions. Second, if the state was not disaggregated into groups or classes and status and prestige were only elements of the search for power, the only statelike objective could be territorial aggrandizement, and this was not sufficient to explain all the so-called actions of states. The way out of these dilemmas was, first, to argue that power was an objective in itself. This meant that the real objective need not be discussed or revealed. The second was that if there was to be an objective, it would be the national interest for Morgenthau and self-interest for Schwarzenberger, both of which were equally undefinable. It may be possible that these vagaries and distortions could be excused as necessary deviations justified by developing the more important project, namely of awakening the world to the dangers of legally, ethically, and ideologically disguised power relations. Morgenthau and Schwarzenberger were reacting to the excessive legalism of the interwar period in Europe and the mass ideologies of the 1930s and in particular the acceptance by intelligent people that solemn declarations and signatures had substantive political impacts. Thus Schwarzenberger was concerned by the “community” language of the UN under conditions of “society” in which such language would be misleading. Morgenthau and Schwarzenberger’s warning was born of their own life experience, in which they had seen the cynical manipulation of the symbols of liberal democracy and rule of law in the pursuit of absolute power. The imprecisions and illogicalities engendered by applying a societally generated, power-oriented approach to the international level produced the contemporary “international relations realism,” as (endlessly) discussed within the IR profession. The derivatives of IR realism were the personification of the nation state, ill-defined national interest, and the elimination of the prosaic motivations of elites in command of states rooted in discrete socioeconomic circumstances. This was not the real realism that sought to understand and reveal the sources of power—its instruments, lackeys, and sycophants—and to investigate its distinct objectives, all as an antidote to the rationalizations of philosophy, theology, ideology, and romanticism, which could be used to divert the perception of reality. This negative conclusion is not to fault either of the authors discussed. Reading their works in terms of social analysis rather than international relations is valuable and insightful. They were correct in the need for an antidote to “unreal” solutions being proposed at the time. An incisive power analysis at the international level was essential in that period. As already noted, any power analysis, even ones so distorted as that in international relations, inevitably becomes unpopular, if not subversive. Its practi-
120
Critique in Critical IR Theory
tioners break myths that others are constructing or are making a living from upholding; they reveal to those who feel they are free that they are governed, to those whose rationalizations of their own actions have been internalized that they are tyrants or victims, dominated or subservient, manipulators or manipulated. Morgenthau was accused by his colleagues in Chicago of having “a Germanic way of looking at things” (Thompson 1979: 547) and came out against the Vietnam War on moral grounds. Schwarzenberger was called a professor of immorality and denied security clearance, possibly because of his refusal to accept the conventional reasons for the commencement of the Korean War. As societal realists, their original project was laudable and their insights formidable, but the area to which they applied their realism and their reluctance to identify the motives of the states’ elites bequeathed the intellectual monster of IR realism—the absolute, power-seeking, personified, nation state.
Rationalities and Real Realism One of the key aspects of realism is that the source and mechanisms of power must be discovered or exposed because there is rarely an overt and transparent exercise of power. If this is the case, it follows that in any society there are power-disguising constructs. It is these that become the target for a realist analysis. The earlier IR realists, pushed by the distinction between the domestic and international levels, focused on the power-disguising, interstate-created legal constructs such as the League of Nations and the UN. They did not specifically apply a generic term to the powerdisguising constructs, preferring, in IR, to refer to utopianism or idealism as the antithesis of reality. In general, however, utopians were depicted as autonomous intellectuals with an erroneous vision of social reality and not as the knowing constructors of power-disguising myths in the service of power. In applying realism to contemporary international political economy, I use rationality as a generic term for constructed power-disguising myths. Thus a recurring friction in history is between rationalities and reality. For Cox, a rationality is a “collective mentality,” a “typical way of perceiving and interpreting the world” that is followed by different social groups within different forms of power relations and that sustains the continued existence of the form (Cox 1987: 25). But rationalities are also mental constructs that attempt to induce acceptance of an exercise of power that otherwise might be unacceptable. This is the emphasis that I placed on a similar use of the concept (Harrod 1987: 33). Rationalities explain the unexplainable, excuse the inexcusable, and offer a refuge for those who do not wish to deal with or confront power—often by denying its existence.
Global Realism
121
In using this concept I am aware that in a variety of forms, such a perception of the structure or process of social and political reality has been used by almost all those who have set out to consider the nature of society and governance. Thus what I have called rationality could be seen also in Weberian unauthentic legitimization, in Foucauldian “governmental rationality” (Gordon 1991), or in the concept of a dominant discourse. Likewise, it may be the internalization of the norms of ruling-class governance, as in Gramscian hegemony or the Marxist superstructure. Morgenthau gave no name to his power-disguising construct, preferring to refer to it as “something”: “What is actually aspiration for power, then appears as something different, something that is in harmony with the demands of reason, morality and justice” (Morgenthau 1967: 119). Rationalities are, then, constructed by groups and individuals in power. As they are intended for internalization, they must be rational at least to an extent greater than the (arbitrary) exercise of power. This rationality usually takes the form Morgenthau suggests, in which reason, morality, and justice are made central. The process of the creation of a rationality varies in the time taken to form it and in its complexity. In those of the church and state, mentioned further on, the rationality developed over centuries and was all-pervasive. But others are more temporal and geographically limited or may be limited in operation, such as those of political parties, enclave organizations, or distinct sets of power relations surrounding different forms of production. From such rationalities are derived legal constructs, social institutions and norms, and as such, they are the source of the control of human behavior. The need for a rationality may lie deep in bioneurological processes that, although not necessarily producing rational thought, nevertheless react negatively to illogicalities. Ongoing research in neurology and its relation to consciousness and studies of power and stress in bureaucracies points in this direction (for example, Edelman 1994). Overtly applied, power inevitably produces through its seeming or real arbitrariness stress that biochemical systems normally seek to reduce. Rationalities may temporarily disguise or block versions of the truth that the human brain would find stress producing. Rationalities are the Freudian dreams that disguise the disturbing real in symbols in order that the sleeper not be awakened. Realism challenges rationalities and awakens people from dreams. In the 1970s, feminist analysts adopting a realist perspective challenged the rationality of women’s work and biological determinism to reveal the ubiquitous power of patriarchy. It is evident that there is a constant antagonism between societal realism and power-constructed rationalities. Rationalities are necessary and may have effects that, by the standards of justice and equity, may be positive or less negative. The purpose of realism is not to destroy a rationality,
122
Critique in Critical IR Theory
but in analyzing and revealing it, realism may often do so. The durability of rationalities, the success with which they absorb, reject, or marginalize the realist challenge, may be the factor that determines historical epochs in which rationalities are constructed and destroyed and different constellations of power are developed. Once a realist critique is extant, the rationality and the power it hides are never the same. Rationalities and their dissemination are a major part of functional (problem-solving) theory, and the analysis of them is a major part of critical theory.
The Current Need for Realism Changes in the structure of power and its exercise bring forward new rationalities. When new rationalities are promoted, the need for realism is greater. In the current period of global history, the need for real realism may be greater for three reasons. First, there has been a shift in the groups or elites that are the holders of power and produce the rationalities; second, this shift of power has been away from political elites toward corporate elites; and third, there has been a change in the dissemination of rationalities, which has affected the political effectiveness of realists. Currently there appears to be considerable confusion relating to the changing power structure at the global level. A realist would expect such confusion because new power holders wish to disguise their role and the mechanism of power used. The most important of these changes is the relative decline in the position of political elites and their potential power. For fifty years, within the framework of corporatism, neocorporatism, and state corporatism, elites associated with the state, whether those associations were precipitated by elections or putsches, used their power in a centralized, directing, mediating, or arbitrating manner. This situation has substantially changed, and the shift in power from elites using the state to others not directly in control of the state apparatus is at the base of the notion of restructuring that is inherent in the concept of globalization. The relative increase in power of the corporate elites represents a shift in globally dominant politico-economic regimes, social formations, or patterns of power relations and their associated rationalities. The emergence of a dominant elite represents not merely a change in elites but a fundamental change in the patterns and structures of power. In terms of the concept of social formations as presented by Cox (and this author), the current changes can be seen as the transformation of social formations dominated by tripartite patterns of power relations in which the state used its power to mediate between corporate economic power and organized labor social power to a social formation dominated by the enterprise corporatism pattern of power relations in which the corporation makes nonnegotiable
Global Realism
123
demands on the state, promotes the social power of ancillary professionals, and fragments the social power of the labor force (Cox 1987; Harrod 1987). Thus the dominant institution in the contemporary world is the corporation. Dominant organizations or institutions that are the principal sources of power produce rationalities from which governing norms are derived. If there has been a succession of dominant institutions ranging through the church, the state, and now the corporation, then the rationality of the church was an all-powerful deity and that of the state the all-powerful will of the people. In both cases the logic of the rationality was that the state and church were instruments of a higher power that itself was based on reason and justice. In contrast, the corporation cannot easily construct a rationality at the macrolevel. There is no elaborated theology or raison d’état for corporations. The extant corporate rationality of neoliberalism is incomplete, for although it seeks to hide the source and exercise of power, it can produce little in the way of convincing or socially persuasive constructs to rationalize arbitrary inequalities. Thus neoliberalism postulates the market as the all-powerful source in analogy to the church and state with their deity and popular will, respectively, but the essential element of rationalizing the stress-producing illogicalities concerning distributional justice is lacking. If the corporate-constructed rationality is so weak, it can be asked why the realist critics have not been more successful in unmasking it. Attempting an answer reveals the difficulty of the current task of real realism in the international political economy. The first difficulty is that corporate power is social, spatially fragmented, and disparate, which means that power can be exerted at the macrolevel only by an aggregation of power via collusion. Corporate macrolevel power is indirect. Although it can directly close plants, create oligopolies, and shift capital, it cannot directly change interest rates or unemployment benefits. Thus whereas a government, church hierarchy, or individual leader may be blamed for the ills that befall the citizenry, it is more difficult to blame chief executive officers of corporations operating in different industries even though collectively their decisions may indeed be at the root of the perceived problem. Second, the corporation has brought to power a diverse stratum of professionals previously subscribing to professional rationalities; this emerging “power elite” has been identified in the work of Harold James Perkin, Robert Reich, and Eric Olin Wright, although for different purposes and with different conclusions (Perkin 1996; Reich 1991; Wright 1997). In exercising power, such professionals operate in distinct areas and in diverse social frameworks. Their current role of mediating corporate power is different from that of enforcing norms or regulating governments. The contradictions on which many social events and cultural products are now con-
124
Critique in Critical IR Theory
centrated are the exercise of corporate power with no other rationalities than efficiency and legitimate profit making and the rationalities of norms of justice and equity in law, propriety in accounting, ethics in medicine, method in science, and professionalism in consultancy. As the groups that practice these rationalities move further along the line, which starts with service and ends in extraction, the techniques to secure returns change. The emerging technique is the restriction of available information and its concomitant of inflated complexities in professional discourse. Only the insiders know and understand. The third difficulty stems from a change in the medium of dissemination. A rationality normally has to first satisfy an attentive public, that is, those with the time, ability, interest, and training to analyze the message. Subsequently the refined rationality is disseminated to a receptive public. This filtering process provides legitimacy at the various stages. But the rationality has to be sophisticated and appealing enough to be able to be defended in discourse within the attentive public. In the contemporary period the rationality promoted has been able to bypass the attentive public and be presented directly to the target public. This dissemination has occurred through the development of corporatecontrolled media and a form of communication that requires no personal investment, not even literacy, to absorb it. The target public then forces the attentive public to respond to the elements of a rationality that would, in the past, have been rejected or refined. The attentive public, usually the basic resource for real realism, is now forced to react to concepts and ideas of a rationality that would have normally been properly ignored: the mass media–precipitated rationality creating a media-driven discourse. The realist analytical tradition is being forced into a second-order position. The focus becomes the power relations of the delivery of the rationality rather than the source of the rationality. Thus the emperor is now in a tinted, bullet-proof car and the tailors hold a megaphone, declaring that the emperor has clothes. The child can no longer announce that the emperor has no clothes but must declare to the crowd that the megaphone is to be suspected as the source of the myth benefiting the tailors and satisfying the emperor. By the time the case is made, the emperor has passed and the tailors are making another mythical suit. The rationality of corporate power is the reification of the market. It is a weak rationality inasmuch as it denies not only the source of power but power itself, something that theology and raison d’état never did for church and state. Further, lacking a macrolevel appeal, corporate rationality must still use the nation state and the institutions of the nation state as a vehicle and shield, thus creating the current confusion as to the function and power of the state. On the one hand the state produces the macrolevel norms of justice, equity, and equality; on the other hand it is used to disguise the
Global Realism
125
power that is incapable, even under the best possible governing scenario, of producing any of these norms. The complexity of the rationality, the emergence of layered instruments of power, makes the task of a societal, or real, realism in world politics both more needed and more complex than it was for the early real realists applying their approach to interstate relations and adjusting them to fit the different level of the approach. The answer to the Qui bono? question, or What is the source of power? was always another state or alliance of states. Today the answer to that same question may be a consortium of corporations, state agencies, individuals in command of financial power, organized crime and interest groups, and professional groups increasingly operating globally. The global outcomes of the use of power are measurable and concrete as, for example, the universal tendency of redistribution of income toward the higher-income groups, the universal degradation of the environment, and increased incidences of new maladies. The complexity of power sources and mechanisms at the global level is such that an application of a real or societal realism would now have to be based on false analogies, as in the case of IR realism. What is needed, then, is a global realism that recognizes and analyzes the multiplicity of power sources and mechanisms at the global level and that approaches constructed rationalities critically. Such a global realism may well confirm Morgenthau’s aphorism of half a century ago that “the revolt against power . . . is as universal as the aspiration for power itself.”
8 WHAT’S CRITICAL ABOUT CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY? Mark Neufeld
Living in an era of globalization places new demands on both thought and action. One such demand is the need to theorize and act out of a global perspective. This demand is no less acute for those social and political theorists whose prime allegiance is to critical traditions. In this regard it is striking that one of the more prominent among those traditions—the critical theory of the Frankfurt School—has been largely silent on global-level issues or processes. As a leading American Frankfurt School theorist has noted, with the exception of occasional comments by Herbert Marcuse in the 1960s, a macrological critique of imperialism or of systems of world domination was “inexplicably absent from most of Critical Theory” (Kellner 1999a). Accordingly, although critical theory has had an influence on some branches of social science, for example, sociology and philosophy, it has, at least until fairly recently, had “virtually no impact on International Relations” (Halliday 1987: 165–166). Indeed, this obvious lacuna has prompted calls from contemporary proponents of critical theory for its reformulation in more globally sensitive terms. Note, for example, the following comment by Thomas McCarthy: “I have wanted to underscore the need for critical theory to adopt a consistently global perspective, so as to locate the received problematics of the nation state in a broader web of interconnected histories” (McCarthy 1994: 92–93). What holds for the critical theory of the Frankfurt School holds for other critical theory traditions as well, both in terms of their neglect of the global and in terms of their need for a corresponding reformulation. And here it is important to point out that scholars interested in carrying out such a reformulation could benefit greatly from a familiarity with the existing literature in international relations (IR) that makes claims to provide a criti127
128
Critique in Critical IR Theory
cal means of theorizing world politics. At the same time, it can also be argued that a greater sensitivity to the insights of critical social and political theory can be of significant benefit to the effort to develop critical IR theory. To that end I propose to undertake a review of some recent efforts in critical IR theory (see also Neufeld 1995–1996). It is my hope that this effort will contribute to greater awareness of the achievements in the realm of critical IR over the past few years. At the same time, I would also hope that a critical review of critical IR theory that draws on some of the insights of critical social and political theory more generally will contribute to the development of more adequate theorizing about world politics. Specifically, I hope this exercise will contribute to deepened reflection on what it means to approach the subject of world politics in a critical way—in short, What’s critical about critical IR theory, and how might its critical content be strengthened?
Assessing Critical IR Theory: Of Tradition and Standards If it is true that there is nothing so practical as a good theory, it is equally true that in the pursuit of good theory there is nothing so constructive as good criticism. Unfortunately, the latter often seems to be in as short supply as the former. This is particularly true in the case of efforts over the past couple of decades to develop a critical—in contrast to a mainstream—body of international relations theory. Certainly the commentaries of mainstream scholars have offered little in the way of criticism that one could characterize as constructive—that is, that serves not only to identify critical IR theory’s shortcomings but also suggests ways to remedy its faults. Indeed, if we are to be perfectly honest, mainstream commentators have rarely moved beyond gross caricature (Spegele 1996 is a noteworthy exception; on which see Neufeld 1997), charging critical IR theory with promoting an ethos of “anything goes” due to a lack of “standards” (Brecher 1995, Jones 1994) even while they denounce critical IR theory for being “inimically dogmatic” due to its overly harsh application of those very same (nonexistent) standards (Schmidt 1997). More lamentable still, however, is the fact that theorists from the margins have often seemed equally incapable of moving beyond a kind of more-critical-than-thou competitiveness (Frank 1997 and Walker 1994 are two disappointing examples). Engagements between modernist and postmodernist critical theorists, in particular, have often been characterized by a mode of reception conforming more to an Adornian “absolute negation” than to Walter Benjamin’s “redemptive hermeneutic,” in which one
What’s Critical?
129
attempts to redeem what is valuable and useful in the views of the other (Kellner 1999b). Of course, the self-cultivation of powerful egos by the advocates of marginal(ized) approaches is an understandable (masculinist) defense mechanism in the face of literally years of relentless attacks from the mainstream; for all of that, it is no less destructive in its effects on interlocutors—not to mention potential allies.1 Happily, we are not limited to disciplinary exemplars to guide our efforts. There exists outside of IR a number of critical theorists who have learned to tread the fine line of rigorous criticism without stepping over it into destructive dismissal of the efforts of others (see, in particular, Fraser 1989b; Bernstein 1983, 1991). It is the standards of solidarity and fairness set by these efforts that I will try to emulate in the pages that follow. This kind of exercise can provoke a number of objections. One possible objection is that the works chosen to review do not provide a true picture of critical theorizing about world politics. In response, I can only say I have tried to be catholic in my notion of critical theory and have not restricted my examples in terms of narrow, predetermined limits. One might also object that the judgments arrived at are problematic because the standards of what constitutes a critical theory have not been applied fairly. Here again, I can only respond by saying I have attempted to be as evenhanded as possible in my application of standards, though every conclusion remains, of course, open to contestation. Finally and most important, one might raise questions about the nature of the standards themselves and the very definition of critique from which they are derived. This potential objection requires a substantive response. Clearly, it is incumbent on authors of this kind of essay to be explicit about their notion of critique, thereby to invite reasoned debate about its adequacy. The notion of critique that informs this chapter is not neutral; it is the product of a particular intellectual tradition and reflective of the assumptions and normative commitments constitutive of that tradition. Appending a label to this tradition is not easy, though several alternatives suggest themselves. On the one hand, Frankfurt School critical theory, although certainly a major influence, is too narrow, as it excludes the theorizing of other influential figures such as Antonio Gramsci. On the other hand, to term this tradition modernist critical theory in order to distinguish it from its postmodernist counterpart, although not incorrect, is too broad. For want of a better term, the Western Marxist tradition will have to suffice. This term raises the question of which characteristics a body of theorizing would have to have to qualify as critical (in Western Marxist terms). Here it will be suggested that these can best be formulated by thinking of critical theory as the determinate negation of the dominant form of technical reason in mainstream IR and, arguably, mainstream social science gen-
130
Critique in Critical IR Theory
erally—that is, as the negation of positivism (see Neufeld 1995). To begin, critical theory stands in opposition to positivism’s objectivist conception of truth as correspondence to the real world. It does so for several reasons. First, as part of its effort to theorize the process of theorizing, critical theory incorporates the Kuhnian-inspired view that knowledge can be understood in terms of paradigms that are, in turn, incommensurable (i.e., having no common measure). In other words, because theory tells us not only how the facts are to be interpreted but also what counts as a fact in the first place, the objectivist notion of truth as correspondence to the facts is untenable. Accordingly, claims for empirical adequacy—although not unimportant—are always understood as relative in the sense that they are, fundamentally, intraparadigmatic (and not interparadigmatic) in nature. The second reason critical theory opposes positivism’s notion of truth as correspondence is that such a view has the consequence of limiting the role reason can play in human affairs. Specifically, in positivist terms reason is limited to episteme, a form of rationality that allows for assessment of knowledge claims in terms of empirical adequacy alone. Critical theory, in contrast, is committed to promoting a broader, practical form of rationality (phronesis) that will also allow for a reasoned assessment of the nonempirical dimensions to human life. In sum, a critical form of theorizing involves theoretical reflexivity, which makes politico-normative content as much a criterion of theory assessment as empirical adequacy. The second element of a positivist approach to the study of human society is a methodological unity of science involving the search for transhistorical regularities in human action. Once again, critical theory opposes this orientation, not least because of its effect of reifying the existing social order as natural. It does so by breaking with positivism’s naturalist assumptions about the essential similarity of the social and natural worlds and recognizes the vital role of intersubjective meanings in constituting human action as social practices that are, in principle, open to change. Accordingly, critical theory promotes an interpretive approach to the study of human society that seeks to understand the potential for change within human practice and social orders. Third, critical theory stands in opposition to the positivist understanding of reliable knowledge as value free in nature. Recognizing that knowledge can never be value free—that “theory is always for someone and for some purpose” (Cox 1981: 128)—critical theory embraces an overt normative commitment to progressive social change. It does so by incorporating a pedagogical understanding of the theory-practice relationship and by accepting that—under current conditions, that is, those of advanced capitalism where the interests of the few regularly take precedence in policy circles over the needs of the many—the audience for critical theory’s criti-
What’s Critical?
131
cisms of the existing order are the policytakers and not the policymakers. In this way critical theory places itself in the service of emancipatory practice. Finally, in combination these three elements of critical theorizing allow for more than the determination of the degree to which a given body of theory approximates critical theory understood as an ideal type. They also point to the overall criterion of adequacy by which critical theory must ultimately be judged. In Horkheimer’s words, “The value of a theory is not decided alone by formal criteria of truth. . . . The value of a theory is decided by its connection with the tasks, which in the particular historical moment are taken up by progressive social forces” (in Held 1980: 192). It might be objected, of course, that this criterion begs the question of what characterizes a progressive social force. The answer, of course, is that the understanding of progressive is connected to the assumptions of critical theory, which are tested, in turn, in the process of analysis and practice. This admittedly circular form of reasoning is that of a hermeneutic circle, which cannot be escaped either by critical or noncritical theorists, as much as objectivists of various stripes might strive to find a way out. I will move now to an assessment of the work of three figures in IR theory whose work can be read as providing a critical orientation to world politics: Alexander Wendt, Justin Rosenberg, and Cynthia Weber. Alexander Wendt Alexander Wendt’s work has proven to be immensely influential in contemporary IR theorizing, particularly in constructivist circles. Indeed, he stands as the youngest of what has been hailed as a new generation of masters of international thought (Neumann and Wæver 1997). Equally important in terms of this discussion is that from the beginning Wendt has made the notion of critical theory central to his intellectual project. From the “agentstructure debate” (Wendt 1987: 370) through his engagement with the social construction of international anarchy (Wendt 1992) and beyond (Wendt 1996), critique and critical theory have figured prominently in Wendt’s theoretical formulations. In his words, “‘critical theory’ (in a broad sense) is essential to the development of social science, and by extension international relations” (Wendt 1987: 370). Here too he has made his mark: In a recent debate held in the pages of International Security it was Wendt who was invited to provide a defense of critical theory in international relations (see Mearsheimer 1994–1995; Wendt 1995). This does raise the question, however, of what is critical about Wendt’s constructivist approach. There are a number of attractive features about Wendt’s theorizing. His work reflects very much the insight, lamentably still too rare in our discipline, that the claim that “International Relations is a discrete area of action
132
Critique in Critical IR Theory
and discourse, separate from social and political theory” can no longer be sustained (Hoffman 1987: 231). Drawing in particular on the work of Anthony Giddens and Roy Bhaskar, his exposition and application of structuration theory and the epistemology of scientific realism demonstrates an impressive facility with contemporary social and political theory. Also praiseworthy are Wendt’s considerable efforts to spell out his starting assumptions and clearly define his terms. In short, Wendt’s work evidences a concern with theoretical reflection on the process of theorizing itself, which, in important respects, qualifies it as a reflexive approach. The account balance is not straightforward, however. From the beginning Wendt has been clear that by critical he means looking “beyond given appearances to the underlying social relationships that generate (in a probabilistic sense) phenomenal forms” (Wendt 1987: 363). Thus consistent with his scientific-realist epistemology, Wendt defines truth in objectivist terms—truth is not correspondence to the facts, as in the case of positivism, but it is correspondence nonetheless. Truth is correspondence to the underlying structures that generate observable facts. Thus hypotheses are understood to be interparadigmatically falsifiable. Nor is there any question about Wendt’s commitment to “a wholly conventional epistemology.” As he argued in his defense of critical IR theory, “Constructivists . . . are modernists who fully endorse the scientific project of falsifying theories against evidence” (Wendt 1995: 75). It is the commitment to interparadigmatic falsification that shows Wendt’s notion of critique has less in common with critical theory’s distinction between critical and traditional, problem-solving forms of theorizing than with the Popperian critical rationalist tradition (see Horkheimer 1972; Cox 1981). In Popperian terms, critical thinking stands in opposition to dogmatic thinking, with the former adapting to refutation by experience and the latter ignoring all counterevidence (Hollis 1994: 72). In short, notwithstanding his replacement of positivism with scientific realism, Wendt replicates mainstream IR’s objectivism and, therewith, its unreflexive limiting of reason to episteme. The same mixed balance sheet can be seen in terms of the other elements of critical theory. On the one hand Wendt stresses the role of intersubjective meanings in constituting social relations. As he notes, what unites the various members of the critical IR family, that is, postmodernists, neo-Marxists, feminists, and constructivists, is their common concern with the socially constructed nature of world politics—a concern that results in a shared interest in how identities and interests are shaped by structures and, in turn, influence international behavior (Wendt 1995: 71–72). Structures, argues Wendt, are dependent on shared ideas: “What makes these ideas (and thus structure) ‘social’ . . . is their intersubjective quality” (Wendt 1995: 73). Thus Wendt’s constructivism seems to qualify as a nonnaturalist,
What’s Critical?
133
interpretive approach consistent with critical theory. In addition, he affirms a clear interest in emancipatory practice: “Constructivists have a normative interest in promoting social change” (Wendt 1995: 74). In his discussion of international identity formation, for example, he affirms the relevance of radical democratic theory for guiding our response to the “international[izing] state”: “The attempt to solve international collective action problems by creating collective identities among states creates an entirely new problem of making those identities democratically accountable, a problem ultimately of transforming the boundaries of political community” (Wendt 1996: 62). On the other hand, there are decidedly uncritical dimensions to his formulations. Specifically, Wendt’s objectivist epistemological commitments place severe limitations on what his approach can offer in terms of emancipatory practice. Notwithstanding an interest in social change, in Wendt’s formulation constructivists (must) restrict themselves to “trying to explain how seemingly natural social structures, like self-help or the Cold War, are effects of practice (this is the ‘critical’ side of critical theory)” in ways that allow for falsification (Wendt 1995: 74). These restrictions bring with them at least two serious consequences. First, in terms of the relationship between personal values and one’s research activities, it is not entirely clear how Wendt’s critical theorist differs from his or her mainstream counterpart. Not only are critical theorists similar to mainstream theorists in terms of having value orientations— “Critical theorists have normative commitments, just as neorealists do”— ultimately they are understood to be in pursuit of the same goal: an unbiased, objective account of reality. Notes Wendt, “We are also simply trying to explain the world” (Wendt 1995: 74). Second, in accepting the problematic objectivist distinction between facts and values, between the is and the ought, Wendt leaves no room to consider the ways in which his constructivism may serve politico-normative agendas independent of his personal value commitments. Because he limits reason to episteme—the direct consequence of his objectivist notion of truth—there is no way to ask critical theory’s central question: What and whom is Wendt’s constructivism for? Although Wendt does not address this question directly, his discussion of the theme of responsibility provides some important hints (Wendt 1995: 79–81). Wendt rejects vigorously the suggestion that constructivists are “subversive utopians who do not believe in a real world” (Wendt 1995: 81). Rather, constructivists are people who are concerned with providing knowledge about the possibilities for change to “those charged with national security” and with “getting policymakers to accept responsibility for solving conflicts” (Wendt 1995: 80, 81). As a consequence, and notwithstanding an ostensible interest in simply
134
Critique in Critical IR Theory
trying to explain the world, Wendt’s constructivism can be understood in explicitly political terms. Consistent with its objectivist epistemology and its statist commitments (Wendt 1995: 72), its purpose is to generate knowledge not for policytakers but for policymakers, not for the purposes of radical emancipatory change but for more effective management of the global system. In short, despite some important openings in the direction of critique, Wendt’s constructivism remains constrained by its efforts to satisfy mainstream theorists on their terms. Accordingly, it is difficult to escape the conclusion that despite significant gestures in the direction of critique, in the end Wendt’s constructivism conforms in many important respects to the classical notion of traditional problem-solving theory. As such, it does not take us as far as it might toward a fully critical theory of world politics. Justin Rosenberg Like Alexander Wendt, Justin Rosenberg is credited with making a significant contribution to the study of world politics generally and to the development of critical IR in particular (see also Neufeld 1994). From his earliest efforts to theorize the peace movement (Rosenberg and Bromley 1988: 66–94) through his more recent engagements to provide a counter to the realist theory and history of world politics (Rosenberg 1994a; see also Rosenberg 1996), Rosenberg has been credited with a major contribution to the critical understanding of world politics. Specifically, his work has been described as doing “a great service to the discipline of IR by . . . systematically developing the idea that one merit of the Marxist theory and method of historical materialism is that it can offer a better explanation of international politics than other theories” (H. Smith 1996: 203). Most recently, Rosenberg has issued an impassioned plea for the development of “International Imagination” through the adoption of the theoretical agenda of “Classic Social Analysis,” in which the concern to serve the cause of human emancipation is front and center. Specifically, Rosenberg calls for the reorienting of international relations theory in line with the approach of C. Wright Mills (an approach Mills described as “plain,” as opposed to dogmatic, Marxism) to incorporate a concern with (1) the grounding of social thought in substantive problems; (2) the use of a historical and comparative depth of field; (3) the perception of the social world as a totality; and, critically, (4) the commitment to the ideals of reason and freedom (Rosenberg 1994b). Of particular relevance for this discussion is the fact that Rosenberg’s “historical materialism”—his self-designation in terms of intellectual tradition—is offered as a form of critical theorizing about world politics. First, in his willingness to address the question of what kind of theorizing is required by the current context, Rosenberg evidences the openness to theo-
What’s Critical?
135
rizing about the process of theorizing that is characteristic of theoretical reflexivity. Second, in his rejection of the reification of the social structures—in his affirmation that what appears as “anonymous social forces and processes” is, in fact, the product of “collective human agency” (Rosenberg 1994a: 173)—Rosenberg weighs in against the assumption of naturalism, which underlies positivism’s methodological unity of science. And finally, in his assertion that theorizing must serve the “ideals of reason and freedom” (Rosenberg 1994b: 87), Rosenberg would seem to take a clear stand against positivism’s quest for value-free knowledge. At the same time, it must be recognized that Rosenberg’s formulations, like Wendt’s, suffer from some serious difficulties. To begin, some have objected that much of what Rosenberg recommends has already been said by others (Walker 1994). Calls for being more attentive to history in a comparative frame, for addressing substantive problems, for taking a holistic view, and for serving the ideals of reason and freedom, they argue, are hardly original even in the discipline of international relations. Even the idea that the approach championed by C. Wright Mills should be extended to the study of world politics has been proposed before—though, arguably, not with the same elegance and passion as one finds in Rosenberg (see Fox 1964). This criticism, however, misses the mark. Put bluntly, there is nothing inherently wrong with reiterating points made by others in a discipline so adept at creative forgetting as ours. More serious is the fact that Rosenberg follows Mills in accepting positivism’s objectivist notion of “truth as correspondence” to the facts. In making the case for historical materialism’s superiority over realism, for example, Rosenberg argues as follows: Adoption of a broad historical materialist framework is not axiomatic. It is contingent upon the claim . . . that this framework allows us to explain in greater detail and more consistently the historical objects and processes, causes and outcomes which constitute our field of study. . . . In the end, the ultimate judgement we can make of a substantive social theory is whether it enables us to write better history. (Rosenberg 1994a: 53)
Clearly, for Rosenberg, writing better history means developing a theory that fits the facts better than its rivals (see also H. Smith 1996: 205). As we have already seen in regard to Wendt, however, the notion of truth as correspondence—whether to facts or to underlying nonvisible structures— brings with it some serious liabilities. Kuhnian objections aside, an objectivist understanding of truth has as its consequence that central assumptions remain unexamined; important questions not only are not answered, they are not even asked. For example, the statement that international relations theory should concern itself with substantive problems raises a number of difficult issues.
136
Critique in Critical IR Theory
First, how is one to meet the objections of the champions of basic research, who respond by saying that many if not most of the significant discoveries of science that have proven useful for addressing substantive problems were made by people whose first order of business was anything but the solving of those problems (see, for example, Rapoport 1964)? Alternatively, even if one agrees that substantive problems should be our focus, there remains the question of which problems are by nature substantive and which are not. We could, of course, simply adopt Mills’s view that the “one huge substantive problem” that needs to be addressed is the “interpretation of the rise, the components, the shape, of the urban industrial societies of The Modern West” (cited by Rosenberg 1994b: 88). But in that case the question is merely transposed down to the level of the subproblems whose solution is necessary for solving the “one huge substantive problem.” To take a concrete example, is the gendered nature of global society a substantive subproblem or not? How are we to know? In sum, in critical theory’s terms the identification of substantive problems is not incorrect in and of itself. It must be understood, however, as derivative of the assumptions of the theoretical orientation being pursued. Any undertaking that moves directly to stipulating substantive problems without reflecting on the necessarily relativized nature of the starting assumptions is inherently problematic. Similarly, questions must be raised about Rosenberg’s conceptualization of the related elements of history and totality. Put simply, how is history to be treated? How is the holistic viewpoint to be conceived? The tradition of Western Marxism, for example, offers many different formulations of totality (Jay 1984b). Rosenberg tells us history should not be used to try to model and predict (Rosenberg 1994b: 105). But if totality is something we establish through observation—something we “find out empirically by looking at the world” (Rosenberg 1994b: 105)—why should we not be looking for the invariant transhistorical regularities sought by positivist social science? Why should we not define explanation as subsuming observable regularities under a general covering law? These questions become particularly apposite in terms of critical theory’s second defining characteristic of an interpretive approach, which rejects the assumption of naturalism to underscore the intersubjective constitution of the social world by self-interpreting human beings. Such an approach is not adopted, first and foremost, because of any putatively better fit with the facts but because it helps us “to determine when theoretical statements grasp invariant [i.e., transhistorical] regularities of social action as such and when they express ideologically frozen relations of dependence that can in principle be transformed” (Habermas 1971: 310). Rosenberg is not wrong when he argues that “writing better history” is not identical with consideration of the “immanent logics of emancipation”
What’s Critical?
137
or that the study of the “objectivist” world of “social structures” and “empirical facts” is not satisfied by “the exploration of the forms of human subjectivity” (Rosenberg 1991: 636). The point is, however, that to preoccupy oneself with the former to the neglect of the latter, as Rosenberg does, is surely as limiting as the inverse. Indeed, it has been a common complaint of reviewers of his work that his focus on structures and processes (e.g., modes of production) has led to a “profoundly reified account of ‘social relations between people’” (Walker 1994). Indeed, ironically for a Marxist, Rosenberg has written “a Marxist analysis with very little discussion of class or class struggle” (Pettman 1995). Indeed, this complaint is doubly ironic in that it parallels the critique Rosenberg has himself directed at others, for example, at Hobsbawm (Rosenberg 1995). And finally, whereas one may fully support the proposition that international relations should commit itself to serving the ideals of reason and freedom, once again, one can surely raise questions about what this means in practical terms. Does it mean, as Rosenberg argues, that the “principal contribution” of scholarly work in this regard is “the illumination of the objective, structural responsibility of individuals and groups for particular outcomes” (Rosenberg 1994b: 105)? And if so, how should this be understood? Mervyn Frost argues that the effort to separate facts and values in Rosenberg’s work results in a rather impoverished conception of the place and role of normative theory (Frost 1994). And should we follow Mills in affirming that the proper role of the social scientist is to remain aloof from practical struggles, that taking part in grassroots organizing and political actions is to abdicate one’s role and “to display . . . a disbelief in the promise of social science and in the role of reason in human affairs” (Mills 1959: 192; cf. Aronowitz and Giroux 1985)? In short, in every case rather serious questions present themselves. One cannot fault a theorist like Mills, of course, for not having anticipated contemporary objections to his understanding of social science. It does not seem unreasonable, however, to expect present-day proponents of Mills’s version of social science to acknowledge—indeed, to engage—these objections. Regrettably, Rosenberg fails to do either. This raises the question of why. And here, I think, we get to the underlying problem. Rosenberg is unwilling or unable to engage these issues, for to do so would require him to move beyond his narrowly conceived notion of historical materialism to become a participant in the metatheoretical debates being carried out by other variants of critical theorizing in the discipline. Specifically, it would mean taking seriously the arguments advanced by IR theorists inspired by the Frankfurt School and Gramsci, feminist theory, and postmodernism, who have engaged one another on themes ranging from the construction of identity to the conduct of social inquiry in the absence of secure foundations, the role of public intellectu-
138
Critique in Critical IR Theory
als, and the promise of Enlightenment values such as reason and freedom in an age when those promises have too often proved to be justifications for established power and privilege. Lamentably, it would appear that Rosenberg does not consider these metatheoretical efforts to be of much value. Critical theory, he tells us, “seems in constant danger of ditching into a sea of philosophical generalities.” As for postmodernism, it “hardly bear[s] thinking about” (Rosenberg 1994b: 86f.)—though it does, at least, get thought about enough to be mentioned. Feminist theory is, unfortunately, not so lucky. It should be noted in this regard that Mills, while employing the sexist terminology of his time, did acknowledge that gender was important for understanding social phenomena (Mills 1951: 75, 172–178). The consequences of not engaging these metatheoretical offerings, however, is that Rosenberg misses out on a number of insights that are crucial for his plan to put the discipline of international relations on a more adequate footing. Perhaps most crucially, there is the issue of an adequate diagnosis of what ails the discipline. Rosenberg is fairly straightforward about what he sees as the problem: It is the continuing dominance of realism. And there is a certain plausibility to this; realism is guilty of the many sins that Rosenberg (and others) have attributed to it. But for those who have engaged seriously with the arguments of critically oriented philosophical traditions such as the Frankfurt School, postmodernism, and feminist theory—and there is more agreement among them than is often recognized—there is also something unsatisfying about this diagnosis. After all, it is not only international relations that has been marked with (1) a lack of attention to history, (2) a failure to provide substantive explanation, and (3) a tendency to atomize the social relationships it studies. Nor is international relations alone in lending support to social structures of domination and injustice. These criticisms have been made of a wide range of social sciences—disciplines in which the tradition of political realism does not exist. Accordingly, international relations is not unique. More important, the similarities between it and other social sciences would suggest that realism is, at best, the disciplinary manifestation of that which (mis)orients mainstream social science as a whole—namely instrumental reason, most clearly manifest in the positivist “logic of investigation,” which continues to inform so much of the research in contemporary social science. Now it should be noted that the elements of the positivist logic of investigation—(1) the correspondence theory of truth, (2) the methodological unity of the sciences (natural and social), and (3) the quest for valuefreedom—although identifiable in realism, are independent of the traditional realist emphases on anarchy, states as actors, and endemic conflict in the resulting self-help system. This is significant. For what it means is that
What’s Critical?
139
even if one abandons traditional realist assumptions—even if one begins to think in terms, say, of interdependence, a plurality of actors, and cooperation as well as competition—if one reconstitutes one’s approach to the study of world politics on the basis of instrumental reason’s positivist logic of investigation, the resulting analysis will be plagued by many, if not all, of the limitations identifiable in realist scholarship. So although it is true that repeated efforts to displace realism by means of a reconstituted neoidealist tradition—whether it be liberal internationalism, complex interdependence, neoliberal institutionalism, or peace research—have failed, there is good reason, given the shared commitments of both the realist and idealist traditions to the positivist logic of investigation, to question whether much would have been gained even had these efforts been successful (for an interesting critique of Wallerstein’s world systems theory along similar lines see Aronowitz 1981). In short, insights developed at the level of metatheory have significant implications for any attempt to reconstitute the discipline of international relations on a more humanistic, emancipatory footing. What metatheoretical discussions have made clear is that a research agenda that is formulated exclusively in terms of the requirement to think historically and substantively will never be in a position to clarify its (by definition) unexamined assumptions and formulations. And a theoretical tradition that is unclear about its metatheoretical fundamentals can easily fall prey to internalizing the very assumptions and prejudices that constitute the unexamined backdrop of mainstream social science—ironically, the very intellectual agenda that theoretical efforts such as Rosenberg’s international imagination are intended to counter. Cynthia Weber No less than Wendt’s and Rosenberg’s, Cynthia Weber’s contributions to the discipline have solicited considerable attention (including Neufeld 1996, upon which the following section draws). Her work on sovereignty, in particular, is noteworthy in that it represents a serious engagement with what remains a major stumbling block to moving the discipline forward in an emancipatory direction: mainstream IR’s conception of the state. Whereas one may speculate about the source of its appeal, there is no denying that the notion of the state as a rational, utility-maximizing, ahistorical given of world politics has proven to be remarkably robust within mainstream circles. Outside those circles, however, the observation that the state is undertheorized is a common one. Indeed, the failure to problematize the state is seen as both a cause and an indicator of the generally impoverished nature of theorizing within the discipline as a whole. Cynthia Weber’s Simulating Sovereignty theorizes the state in terms of
140
Critique in Critical IR Theory
IR theory’s “essential modifier” for the state: sovereignty. She does this through a rereading of foreign policy discourse on intervention. Her analysis takes as its starting point the essentially uncontested nature of the concept of sovereignty. Yet as variations across time and place indicate, state sovereignty is anything but stable or uniform. Therefore, argues Weber, one should view sovereignty less as a state of being than as something inferred from practice. Accordingly, sovereignty marks not the location of the foundational entity of international relations theory but a site of political struggle. This struggle is the struggle to fix the meaning of sovereignty in such a way as to constitute a particular state—to write the state—with particular boundaries, competencies and legitimacies available to it. (Weber 1995: 3)
Weber pursues her analysis of state sovereignty by focusing on a particular question: How is the meaning of sovereignty fixed or stabilized historically via practices of political intervention? It is Weber’s contention that the practice of intervention is a crucial site for the stabilization of sovereignty given that discussion of intervention invariably raises questions about whether sovereignty is invested in particular localities, leaders, or sets of practices. When state practices do not fit the shared understandings of what a sovereign state must be, interference is legitimate; when, however, state practices are in accordance with intersubjective understandings of statehood, intervention is prohibited (Weber 1995: 4). Thus when we focus on intervention practices, it is possible to identify what kinds of practices constitute legitimate forms of being, for example, sovereign states. Weber argues that the sovereign state must be understood in terms of two distinct kinds of representation. The first is political representation, by which the domestic community authorizes the government to speak on its behalf. Less familiar but equally vital is symbolic representation, by which questions are settled regarding who is and is not a member of the domestic community and what the range of authority of a domestic community is. In short, symbolic representation, when successful, produces a meaningful referent invested with sovereign authority, the effect of which is the sovereign state. To investigate the process of symbolically producing the state, Weber reviews the interventions in Spain and Naples by the Concert of Europe, U.S. interventions in the Bolshevik and Mexican revolutions during the Wilson era, and the interventions in Grenada and Panama by the Reagan and Bush administrations. For the first two sets of cases, Weber works in terms of an interpretive approach derivative of the work of Michel Foucault. Here the questions posed are the following: How is truth produced by a diplomatic and scholarly community of judgment, and how is truth (a sovereign foundation or a community) represented? In the latter
What’s Critical?
141
cases, however, Weber moves from Foucault’s view of truth as an effect of power to consider “what happens when it is no longer possible to represent sovereign foundations?” (Weber 1995: 31) because there are “no ultimate referents, no truth, or (and this is the same thing) so many signs of the truth that truth has no meaning” (Weber 1995: 38). In other words, the question is no longer the Foucauldian one of “How is sovereignty represented?” but rather one derivative of Jean Baudrillard: “How is sovereignty simulated?” (Weber 1995: 10). Weber’s work is consistently readable. Substantively, she makes a very compelling case that the sovereignty-intervention boundary is a fruitful site to investigate the social construction of the modern state. Equally significant in terms of the present discussion is the fact that her efforts also stand as an example of critical theorizing—in this case, from the postmodernist shore of the modern-postmodern divide. First, there is a clear concern with metatheoretical exploration of the process of theorizing as required by reflexivity. Second, there is an explicit adoption of an interpretive approach to the social world that sees the intersubjective meanings deriving from discourse as fundamental to understanding all dimensions of society. And finally, there is a clear sense that Weber’s theorizing is oriented to promoting social change consistent with her commitment to “do feminist politics” (Weber 1994a: 340). As in the case of Wendt and Rosenberg, however, there are aspects of Weber’s work that seem to work against its critical thrust. I will begin again with the theme of reflexivity and then move through that of an interpretive approach and social criticism in support of emancipatory practice. Questions regarding reflexivity are prompted by a response Weber offered to an earlier discussion written by Robert Keohane (1989). In his article, Keohane reviewed Sandra Harding’s well-known typology of feminist empiricism, feminist standpoint theory, and feminist postmodernism with the objective of evaluating their potential to contribute to the advancement of our understanding of world politics. Finding weaknesses in both the first and the third in terms of the standards of mainstream social science, Keohane concluded that feminist standpoint offered the greatest promise and advocated that feminist standpoint theorists make common cause with neoliberal institutionalism against the continuing dominance of neorealism. To begin, one can certainly forgive feminist theorists for being suspicious of Keohane’s intervention. As Ann Tickner has noted, Feminists find communication . . . with scholars trained in social scientific methodologies equally difficult because of the lack of agreement as to what counts as legitimate scientific inquiry. Since all these feminist approaches question the claim that women can simply be added to existing theoretical frameworks, it is predictable that misunderstandings will
142
Critique in Critical IR Theory compound when those working within the scientific tradition suggest that feminist approaches can be incorporated into conventional IR methodologies. Indeed, feminists have a legitimate fear of co-optation; so often women’s knowledge has been forgotten or subsumed under more dominant discourses. (Tickner 1997: 620)
Nonetheless, there is something unsettling about the tack Weber takes in responding to Keohane’s commentary. Specifically, Weber charges Keohane with serious “criminal” behavior, including a textual “mutilation” and “attempted murder” of the “feminist body” (Weber 1994a: 348). What warrants these serious charges, argues Weber, is Keohane’s refusal to accept the plurality inherent in the “multifaceted feminist body” and to see “international relations theory from at least three perspectives at once, no one of which is privileged over others” (Weber 1994a: 339). In short, the problem with Keohane’s treatment of feminist IR is that he does not “look through feminist lenses”; rather he “looks at them” (Weber 1994a: 339). There is no question that Keohane looks at feminist lenses. He does this, moreover, with the clear purpose of drawing distinctions between the different perspectives and of making judgments about their relative merits. One can, of course, question the standards he applies and the conclusions he draws regarding the optimal alliance of feminist standpoint and neoliberal institutionalism. Still, it can also be argued that the willingness to make distinctions among approaches—to ask the question, For whom and for what is this theory, and how does it compare to others?—and to make reasoned judgments about contending perspectives on the basis of their politico-normative content is a fundamental part of theoretical reflexivity. This argument would hold, furthermore, in the case of differing perspectives within feminist IR as much as in any other practice in the field. Indeed, it can be argued that it has been precisely the willingness of feminists to engage in this kind of reasoned assessment of (incommensurable) approaches that has made feminist IR a leading example of reflexive thinking in the discipline (Neufeld 1995: 64–68). From this perspective, the problem in Keohane’s intervention is not that he attempts to draw distinctions but that his newfound reflexivity is too little, too late. The alternative Weber seems to be promoting, however—the refusal to privilege one perspective over another—contains within it the real danger of a “flabby pluralism” (see Bernstein 1991: 335–339). If this is a misinterpretation of Weber’s position—if, in fact her difficulty lies with the specific criteria by which Keohane makes his judgments and not with the principle of making judgments about the relative merits of contending theoretical approaches—then it would be useful to know what appropriate criteria would be. In other words, what kinds of criteria could be applied in assessing the relative merits of feminist empiricism, feminist standpoint, or feminist postmodernism that would not entail a mutilation of the feminist body?
What’s Critical?
143
Similarly, in terms of her interpretation of the social world, one can raise questions. There is no doubt that analysis of discourse has its place in critically oriented work. Still, social life is not reducible to discourse alone, and those who make discourse their focus must be cognizant of the danger that their work will devolve into a “linguistic idealism” if it is not linked to an analysis of extradiscursive material conditions (Best and Kellner 1991: 27). In Weber’s discussion of sovereignty, however, it is not clear how this link is to be made. If one accepts, for example, the argument that the state is not given but produced symbolically, one is still left with some basic questions unanswered, perhaps the most important of which is, Whose interests are served by the social arrangements sustained by the representational projects under examination? At the least, some indication of how the kind of analysis carried out here could be combined with analyses focusing on differential rewards that fall along class, race, and—particularly notable by its absence from the work of a feminist theorist—gender lines in the current global order would have been useful.2 A related set of questions can be raised with regard to the implications of this work for political practice. It can be argued that what bridges the modernist-postmodernist divide within current critical IR theory is the shared “concern to facilitate a politics of resistance among the globally disenfranchised” (George 1994: 200). One can assume that this concern is also part of Weber’s postmodernism and her commitment to doing feminist politics. An important part of this project is identifying points at which resistance might be organized in the interests of the transformation of the global order. In this regard, Weber suggests that there are widening cracks in the foundation of that order: “Representational projects and the strategies by which they are effective depend upon the creative deployment of symbolic resources that are not inexhaustible” (Weber 1995: 10). “With respect to sovereign statehood,” she notes, “we may be reaching an exacting point when enactments of sovereign statehood in practice are depleting their own resources to the point where there is little room for creative redeployment of these resources” (Weber 1995: 10). Beyond these very general intimations, however, there is little that addresses directly the question of how a politics of resistance among the globally disenfranchised might be organized or how a feminist politics is to be carried out.
Conclusion This analysis has proceeded from the assumption that metatheoretical attentiveness to the question of what constitutes a critical theory is an important part of ensuring that current efforts to develop a critical approach to world politics meet with success. It is true, of course, that metatheoretical discus-
144
Critique in Critical IR Theory
sions can never satisfy on their own. Metatheoretical debates about what constitutes a critical theory do not automatically provide an adequate theoretical account of historical developments that can, in turn, shed light on addressing substantive problems. Accordingly, theoretical-empirical explorations must be carried on parallel to metatheoretical ones (see, for example, Cox 1987; Enloe 1993). Neither suffices in the absence of the other. But then this is precisely the point. It is interesting to consider how the interests of mainstream social science stand in relation to metatheoretical discourse. If it is true that metatheoretical critique is necessary to challenge mainstream theorizing at the most fundamental level, then is it any wonder that so many mainstream theorists seem intent on inculcating new generations of social scientists with the strongest possible antipathy to metatheory? And who can doubt that the theoretical mainstream has been extremely successful in this regard? How else to explain the widespread hostility to all things metatheoretical? How else to account for the neglect of—and even the barely disguised impatience with—metatheoretical discussion even within the work of those with an explicit commitment to critical inquiry? Ultimately, Max Horkheimer’s observation is still a valid one: Though there may be periods when one can get along without metatheory, in the present context “its lack denigrates people and renders them helpless against force” (Horkheimer 1968: 308). Significantly, Horkheimer also supplies what may be the most appropriate response to the animosity directed at metatheory: Insist that “today the whole historical dynamic has placed philosophy at the centre of social actuality, and social actuality at the centre of philosophy” (308) and appreciate that hostility to metatheory “is really directed against the transformative activity associated with critical thinking” (Horkheimer 1972: 232). Fulfilling the promise of the critical study of world politics requires recognizing that his statements hold true for the discipline of international relations as much as any other—and perhaps more than most. Nancy Fraser has observed that “no one has yet improved on Marx’s 1843 definition of critical theory as ‘the self-clarification of the struggles and wishes of the age’” (Fraser 1989b: 113). What is undeniable is that in the current context, the struggles and wishes of the age are increasingly intertwined with global-level structures and processes. As a consequence, the self-clarification of emancipatory struggles and wishes at the beginning of the twenty-first century perforce must be conducted in globally sensitive terms. And here there is certainly cause for optimism. Notwithstanding existing limitations and lacunae, it does not seem unreasonable to expect that critical IR theory will soon be in a position to make a meaningful contribution to this broader quest for human dignity in our global polis. And when it does, we shall finally have the definitive answer to the question, What’s critical about critical IR theory?
What’s Critical?
145
Notes The title of this chapter alludes to Nancy Fraser’s “What’s Critical About Critical Theory? The Case of Habermas and Gender” (Fraser 1989b). 1. Bertolt Brecht’s poem, “An die Nachgeborenen,” which hangs on my office wall, makes this point most poignantly: To Those Who Come After You, who will surface Out of the flood In which we went under Bear in mind When you speak of our failings Also the dark times That you escaped. We walked after all Changing countries more Often than our shoes Through class wars Despairing When there was only injustice And no outrage. Of course we know: Even hatred Of baseness Distorts one’s disposition. Even anger About injustice Makes one’s voice hoarser. Alas, we Who wanted to prepare the ground For kindness Were ourselves incapable Of being kind. You however Once the stage has been reached Where human beings are One another’s helpers Consider us With forbearance. —Bertolt Brecht (1939: 143; translation, M. Neufeld) 2. The parallel with Rosenberg is striking. In one case we have a Marxist theorist who does not interpret history in terms of class struggle; in the other, we have a feminist theorist who does not interpret history in terms of gender. What is particularly puzzling is that Weber does provide elsewhere a gender-framed analysis of one of the case studies featured in her book (see Weber 1994b).
PART THREE THE PRACTICE AND PRAXIS OF CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY
9 THE PRACTICE, AND PRAXIS, OF FEMINIST RESEARCH IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Sandra Whitworth
What happens when critical and feminist international relations (IR) theorists go out into the world and actually talk to the people they study? This chapter argues that the most important contribution of feminist and critical theories of international relations has been to open up, as Steve Smith writes, “just what counts as the subject matter of international relations” (S. Smith 1996: 38), but there has been little corresponding analysis of the political and practical implications of conducting critically informed research in IR. The chapter proceeds in three parts. The first is a brief outline of the way in which critiques of the mainstream discipline of IR have resulted in a self-consciousness about how we ask questions in IR, about what gets included and what remains excluded. The second provides a summary of some of the directions my own research is taking and some of the ways this reflection on the posing of questions has permitted me to ask feminist and critical questions about UN peacekeeping. In the third section, I use some of my own research experiences to argue that critical and feminist IR theories have been almost completely silent on theorizing about or thinking through the political implications of conducting research on so-called marginalized communities. Part of this silence reflects the focus by critical theorists on the theoretical challenges that have been developed thus far; considerably less work has been done on actual research. It is important to emphasize that the point here is not to lament, as Robert Keohane has done in the past and Alexander Wendt more recently, the absence of an identifiable research program in critical IR (Keohane 1988; Wendt 1995). Rather, the point is to take up an observation by Mark Neufeld that the “translation of the meta-theoretical gains 149
150
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
of the restructuring process into advances in the analyses of specific topics remains to be effected” (Neufeld 1995: 5). That translation, it is argued here, needs to engage a series of problems, not least of which is the acknowledgment of our embeddedness at all times in prevailing global power relations and the extent to which even critically informed and progressive research projects reproduce and conform to those power relations.1 In this chapter I seek to explore some of the questions that arise in such circumstances and argue that critical theorists must become more engaged in some of the political complexities of conducting critical and feminist research in IR if it is to remain committed to praxis, that is, if it is to remain committed to theorizing and acting on the world in order to change it.
The Contributions As has been noted, critical IR and feminist IR have focused on the ways questions are asked and on the fact that some issues in international relations are problematized, whereas others are not. This focus has been accomplished, as Steve Smith notes, through what began as an epistemological critique and the observation that the subject is implicated in and not separable from the object of study (S. Smith 1996; see also Linklater 1996b). As Mark Neufeld writes, “It is because of the possibility of methodologically ‘factoring out’ the identities of the individual researcher that objective knowledge,” politically neutral knowledge, was assumed to be possible at all (Neufeld 1995: 33; see also Smith, Booth, and Zalewski 1996a, 1996b: 6). Likewise, the rejection of positivism has meant a rejection of the notion that there can be such a thing as a politically neutral analysis of external reality (Linklater 1996b: 281). In other words, and following Robert W. Cox’s classic 1981 observation, theory is “always for someone and for some purpose” (Cox 1981: 128). Whereas mainstream theorists have always theorized in order to provide policy-relevant advice to state elites, critical and feminist IR theorists engage with the “lived injustices” or “lived suffering” of marginalized groups. Feminist IR and critical IR theorists are concerned with those processes of domination made invisible by the mainstream’s concern with states, power, and anarchy and committed to those who, as Cynthia Enloe writes, are deeply affected by international politics but “aren’t in a position to call the tune” (Enloe 1989: 2). Uncovering the impact of international relations on those previously rendered invisible will give us, she notes, not only a richer and more accurate empirical sense of the world but also some insight into the more theoretical question of how politics are made. This
Feminist Research
151
insight joins very neatly with critical IR’s commitment to an emancipatory politics because in observing, as Enloe does, that what is made can be remade, there is the explicit recognition of the possibility, at least, for an emancipatory politics, a politics of change aimed at transforming relations of inequality and domination.
The Project In my own work on peacekeeping, I begin with the argument that the image of peacekeeping as a benign, altruistic, and morally superior form of military force, which is so pervasive in multilateral and certain national contexts, tells us more about self-identification—about how the UN or certain “contributor” peacekeeping countries seek to present themselves—than it does about what actually happens when peacekeeping missions are deployed to various countries around the world (Whitworth 1995, 1998). I have tried to illustrate this argument in part by asking Cambodian women about the impact of the peacekeeping mission (the UN Transitional Authority in Cambodia, or UNTAC) on their lives. I am concerned, for example, about the fact that a whole series of questions about peacekeeping never get asked. Peacekeeping itself is never problematized in mainstream literatures; instead, peacekeeping is taken to be an unproblematic and obviously good thing, an important instrument in maintaining peace and order in the post–Cold War world. As Alan James describes it, peacekeeping is “an enormously useful device” (James 1995: 265). For Steven Ratner, it is “a way of and process for securing important, shared values” (Ratner 1995: 1). With considerable consistency, a similar picture is depicted in most mainstream accounts: The collapse of the political stalemate of Cold War politics has created new opportunities for the UN at the same time that new sources of conflict have emerged; through peacekeeping missions, the UN has been called in to address an ever-increasing number of these conflicts; these missions are sometimes successful, but a series of problems have emerged that must be addressed by academics and policymakers. These are problems of efficiencies, finances, and control. They are, in short, technical problems, and technical problems are answered by technical experts. Thus not only are a whole series of questions not asked but whole groups of people(s) are never consulted when questions about peacekeeping are raised. It is not at all unusual within mainstream accounts of peacekeeping, for example, that evaluations of peacekeeping missions are published without the authors ever bothering to go to the country in which the peacekeeping mission was deployed to seek the opinion of the people
152
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
who lived through the mission, to find out whether local experience conforms in any way to expert opinion (see, for example, Heininger 1994; Utting 1994 is an important exception). Thus I went to Cambodia hoping to develop an analysis of the gendered nature of the peacekeeping mission. I also went there with a sense, from writers such as Chandra Mohanty, Caren Kaplan and Aihwa Ong, of the tendency of Western feminists to homogenize and universalize the experiences of “third world women” and in particular to portray them strictly as victims of various processes, whether imperialism, capitalism, or, in my case, peacekeeping (Mohanty 1991a, 1991b; Kaplan 1994; Ong 1988). As Mohanty writes, “Few studies have focused on women workers as subjects—as agents who make choices, have a critical perspective on their own situations, and think and organize collectively against their oppressors” (Mohanty 1991a: 29; emphasis in original). Thus I hoped also to learn, by going to Cambodia, of the ways in which women (and men) were involved in the UNTAC mission, whether acting in or against it. UNTAC is cited by the UN and regarded by many mainstream observers as something of a success story for the UN.2 William Shawcross, speaking at the general assembly of the International Nongovernmental Organizations (NGO) Forum on Cambodia, called it an “international triumph” (cited by Jennar 1994: 145; see also Ledgerwood 1994; Heininger 1994: 1–8; Utting 1994: 3 and passim), and UN Secretary-General Boutros Boutros-Ghali has written that the “international community can take satisfaction from the peacekeeping operation it mounted and supported in Cambodia” (Boutros-Ghali 1995: 55; see also the Economist, June 19, 1993: 36). The success, achieved in an eighteen-month mission in Cambodia, included the reduction of violence, the repatriation of some 370,000 Khmer refugees, and the conduct of a relatively free and fair election in which some 4 million people, or 85 percent of Cambodia’s registered voters, participated (Munthit 1993: 3; Thayer and Tasker 1993: 10; see also Doyle 1995; Doyle and Suntharalingam 1994). The UN claimed as well, again in the words of Boutros-Ghali, that the mission “boosted Cambodia’s economy by raising funds internationally for economic rehabilitation and expansion throughout the country” (Boutros-Ghali 1995: 54; see also Curtis 1994: 56–58). The UNTAC effort also achieved some important successes with regard to women in Cambodia. Most notably, the freedom of association that prevailed in many respects during UNTAC and the efforts of the UN Development Fund for Women (UNIFEM) to incorporate women’s issues into the general election resulted in public education and information campaigns in the print media and on radio and television. Additionally, the four-day National Women’s Summit brought together Cambodian women
Feminist Research
153
from all sectors of society to identify and prioritize women’s issues in order to lobby political parties contesting the election and then later the government itself (Report of the National Women’s Summit 1993; Channo 1993a). The Women’s Summit has been credited with facilitating the emergence of an indigenous women’s movement in Cambodia as well as a number of indigenous women’s NGOs, which in turn have been credited with a very effective lobby of the Cambodian government such that important equal rights provisions eventually made it into the new Cambodian constitution (interviews by the author, Phnom Penh, March-April 1996).3 Though UNTAC was considered a success in many respects, there are also some discussions of problems associated with the mission. For example, the UN failed to achieve a situation of political neutrality, as pledged in the 1991 Paris Peace Agreement, in part because the Khmer Rouge withdrew from the demobilization and cantonment process and threatened throughout the mission to disrupt the election campaign (Amer 1993; Curtis 1994: 59; Doyle 1995: ch. 4; Doyle and Suntharalingam 1994: 124–127). Likewise, the presence of UNTAC may have diminished, but did not stop, political violence, which was aimed at both political party members and ethnic Vietnamese and resulted in a mass exodus of ethnic Vietnamese, many of whom were second- and third-generation Cambodians (Curtis 1994: 60; Eng 1992: 4; Barrington 1993: 1; Jennar 1994: 148). These are obviously very serious concerns, but another series of issues emerged throughout the UNTAC mission that are seldom discussed in UN documents or mainstream accounts of the mission. Though credited with helping to create the emergence of a fledgling women’s movement as well as a number of women’s NGOs, the UNTAC mission also resulted in a number of important negative consequences for women in Cambodia. These include the reported exponential increase in prostitution to serve UNTAC personnel. The Cambodian Women’s Development Association estimates that the number of prostitutes in Cambodia grew from about 6,000 in 1992 to more than 25,000 at the height of the mission (Channo 1993b; Arnvig 1994: 166–169; Kirshenbaum 1994; interviews, Phnom Penh, March-April 1996). Some reports indicated that the majority of prostitutes were young Vietnamese women, though these estimates are more likely a result of anti-Vietnamese sentiment than any reflection of reality (Swain 1992; Asian Recorder, May 21–27, 1993; interviews, Phnom Penh, March-April 1996). While the presence of prostitutes was not new, and by many accounts frequenting prostitutes is a regular feature of many Cambodian men’s behavior, Cambodians were nonetheless alarmed by the dramatic increase in prostitution and noted that prior to UNTAC it was quite hidden in Cambodian society but became something that was very prevalent and open
154
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
(interviews, Phnom Penh, March-April 1996). The rise of child prostitution has also been linked in some NGO reports to the arrival of UNTAC (UNICEF 1995: 1–2 and appendix 2). The widespread use of prostitutes was raised by the Khmer Rouge as part of their efforts to undermine the peace process when they accused peacekeepers of being too busy with prostitutes to check on the presence of Vietnamese soldiers (Swain 1992). As Judy Ledgerwood wrote: “Some Cambodians were more inclined to believe Khmer Rouge propaganda that UNTAC was collaborating with the Vietnamese to colonize Cambodia when they saw UNTAC personnel taking Vietnamese ‘wives’” (Ledgerwood 1994). The influx of nearly 23,000 UN personnel and the dramatic rise in prostitution also appears to have resulted in a dramatic rise in cases of HIV and AIDS. The World Health Organization (WHO) reported that 75 percent of people giving blood in Phnom Penh were infected with HIV (this figure is considered inflated by some observers); another report indicated that 20 percent of soldiers in one French batallion tested positive when they finished their six-month tour of duty (Swain 1992; Asian Recorder, February 5–11, 1993).4 UNTAC’s chief medical officer predicted that as many as six times more UN personnel would eventually die of AIDS contracted in Cambodia than had died as a result of hostile action (Peach 1993). As criticism toward UN personnel within Cambodia grew, a number of what Judy Ledgerwood describes as “telling” actions were announced. Peacekeepers were warned to be more discreet, for example, by not parking their distinctive white vehicles outside massage parlors and in red-light areas and by not frequenting brothels in uniform (Asian Recorder, April 16–22, 1993; Ledgerwood 1994: 8; Arnvig 1994: 165). A second response was to ship an additional 800,000 condoms to Cambodia (Reuters Library Report, November 18, 1992). In addition to prostitution, sexual abuse and violence were alleged. Raoul Jennar reported that in 1993, “in the Preah Vihear hospital, there was for a time a majority of injured people who were young kids, the victims of sexual abuse by UN soldiers” (Jennar 1994: 154). A number of interviewees reported frequent claims of rape and sexual assault brought to women’s NGOs during the UNTAC period; these claims often emerged many days or weeks after the alleged rapes, and thus evidence could not be collected and claims could not be substantiated to the satisfaction of UN officials (interviews by the author, Phnom Penh, March-April 1996; see also Kirshenbaum 1994: 13). It is also a widely shared view among many Cambodian women and men that the phenomenon of “fake marriages” was widespread during the UNTAC period. Simply put, a UN soldier would marry a Cambodian woman, but only for the duration of his posting to Cambodia, at which point he would abandon her. Some women were reported to have been
Feminist Research
155
abandoned as far away as Bangkok and left to make their way home. In addition to these emotional traumas, fake marriages were enormously shameful for women in a society that, like most societies, has very strict norms about what is appropriate behavior for “good” women (interviews by the author, Phnom Penh, March-April 1996). In part as a response to the sexual harassment that prevailed during the UNTAC mission, an open letter was delivered to the UN SecretaryGeneral’s Special Representative in Cambodia, Yasushi Akashi. In the letter, 165 Cambodian and expatriate women and men accused some UNTAC personnel of sexual harassment, of violence against women and against prostitutes, and of being responsible for the dramatic rise of prostitution and HIV/AIDS (Phnom Penh Post, October 11, 1992: 2; Business Wire, January 11, 1993). Akashi responded by saying that it was natural for hotblooded young soldiers who had endured the rigors of the field to want to have a few beers and to chase “young beautiful beings of the opposite sex” (Colm 1992; Swain 1992). After an outraged response, Akashi pledged to assign a community relations officer to hear the complaints of the Cambodian community (Colm 1992; Phnom Penh Post, November 20–December 3, 1992: 2). Finally, and in contrast to the claims by Boutros-Ghali about UNTAC contributions to economic development in Cambodia, the UNTAC mission has been blamed for economic dislocation. Grant Curtis reports that with skyrocketing inflation, the price of a kilogram of high-quality rice rose from 450 riels to a high of 3,000 riels and settled eventually at 1,800–2,000 riels; the price of fish and meat rose by 80 percent; housing rental prices increased at least four times, and UNTAC personnel often paid Phnom Penh–based rents at the provincial level, resulting in increases there also. UNTAC did contribute somewhat by hiring locals but also drew most of the few trained or experienced Khmer away from Cambodian administrative structures and into UNTAC, and salary payments to local staff composed less than 1 percent of total local expenditure. Finally, the riel was devalued by 70 percent during the UNTAC mission (Curtis 1994: 59–65; see also Davies 1993; Klintworth 1993; Berdal 1993: 46). In situations of economic dislocation and inflation, the most vulnerable members of society become even more vulnerable, and within Cambodia women compose a large proportion of the vulnerable.
The Argument The ways in which critical and feminist approaches to international relations have opened up “what counts” in IR permitted me to ask a series of
156
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
questions about peacekeeping that are rarely posed within the mainstream literature. It is worth noting, however, that whereas the mainstream literature might ignore these kinds of questions, the account here comes as little surprise to local activists and NGOs. Talking to activists and to men and women who lived in Cambodia during the UNTAC mission—shifting one’s gaze—made it possible to untangle and challenge depictions of peacekeeping as a straightforward success. This kind of analysis has a series of implications. For one, it permits activists and progressive academics in both contributor and host countries to resist the almost homogeneous depictions of peacekeeping as a self-evidently positive military activity. It allows us to challenge what has become, through peacekeeping, the reassertion of militaries and militarism in only slightly altered guise. It can make visible the enormously complex circuits of power that are entailed in any security mission, whether it is an invasion or a peacekeeping deployment, and reminds us that the politics of peacekeeping concerns as much thinking through the politics of gender, race, and class relations as it does UN finances, the implementation of peace treaties, or chains of command. There are, then, important insights to be gained by this kind of research; actually conducting the research to make these claims led me to reflect on the extent to which we have not begun to problematize doing research in a way that is consistent with political, ethical, and theoretical commitments to which we lay claim by being critical or feminist IR scholars. What do we do as researchers in countries such as Cambodia? The worst-case scenario evolves as follows: We parachute in to a very poor country, probably carrying around our waist or otherwise hidden in pockets distributed throughout our clothing (because we are afraid) four or five times as much money as the average local person makes in a year. We live cheaply, but we can still afford the best of what is available and so live well. Having lived cheaply, we receive the added benefit of praise from our university’s financial administrators for our economic efficiencies. We ask people for their time and their stories, which we take away (we steal them) and write up in a language we (but not necessarily they) understand, in a manner that serves our (but not necessarily their) research interests and political agendas. After we write up their stories, we become famous or, at the very least, get tenure, promotion, more money, a book contract, and so on.5 Whereas some anthropologists and sociologists (especially but not exclusively feminist anthropologists and sociologists) have begun to debate the political and ethical implications of conducting research in such situations, there is relatively little such debate or concern raised within IR. There is, for one, far less of a tradition of fieldwork (itself a contentious term) in IR, and to the extent that there is, this work has usually entailed
Feminist Research
157
interviews with elite decisionmakers. This lack of debate is true of mainstream IR but also of critical and feminist work. Although this lack does not mean that the dilemmas of conducting research go entirely unremarked—for example, Cynthia Enloe notes the importance of the women we research speaking for themselves, and Simona Sharoni problematizes the political and ethical dilemmas of being both an insider and an outsider in her own work on women in the Israeli-Palestinian conflict (Sharoni 1995)—there is little in the way of a sustained discussion of the various ways to acknowledge and negotiate some of these dilemmas. In some cases the debates in anthropology and sociology suggest that because of the numerous concerns and issues surrounding fieldwork, anthropologists and sociologists should “study up,” that is, reject the discipline-defining practice of conducting research on “primitive” or “exotic” others—those who have relatively less power—and study those who have power (D. Wolf 1996: 2; Mohanty 1991a: 31). But this approach provides no solution to the feminist or critical IR researcher because to the extent we have studied people in IR at all, we have generally “studied up”—whether we have focused on presidents, secretaries of defense, chief executive officers, or venture capitalists. Studying the powerful is thus not very helpful in a discipline that is only just beginning to discover that there are marginalized groups and peoples in the world who are as much a part of world politics as, for example, the president of the United States or the chief executive officer of a multinational corporation. So what can be done? Debates in anthropology have looked to empowering research subjects, conducting participatory research, breaking down positivism’s distinction between subject and object, coauthoring between the researcher and the researched, and so on. But such responses have also been subject to critiques with many asking how effective such approaches are (D. Wolf 1996: 19–48). Some writers such as Judith Stacey have observed that the breakdown of the distinction between researcher and researched and the pursuit of more empathetic research techniques could, in some ways, be even more exploitative, such as when a feminist researcher becomes “friends” with the women she is researching. Under such circumstances, she notes, the friend–research subject may reveal far more than she would have otherwise, far more than she may want to reveal, as a result of the greater intimacy that has been established (Stacey 1991; cf. D. Wolf 1996: 20). Some researchers offer to give back to local women’s organizations, providing time, skills, and services in exchange for the time and effort those researched have taken away from their own work. But there is some consensus that such contributions are ultimately transitory, and no matter what a researcher contributes to the researched, the researcher still has enormous power, not the least of which is to leave, to go home. The same
158
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
concern is raised around coauthorships, which although giving voice to the researched, do not address the problems of inequality in terms of mobility; nor do they usually address the problem of the researcher’s power to determine the purpose of the research in the first place and the reception of that research once it has been published and distributed (D. Wolf 1996: 26–34; Kaplan 1994: 139). It is, after all, the researcher who gives voice, has the power to give or take away, and remains the center of power and the project (Kaplan 1994: 142). Some researchers have devoted energies, in both their research and their writing, to try to locate themselves, to acknowledge the researcher as a positioned subject just as much as the researched in order to avoid the problems of assuming that the researcher has a stable, fixed, and unproblematic identity, whereas the researched does not. But again, cautions are noted; Daphne Patai has observed that paying respect to difference without actually changing the research ends up sounding empty and apologist (Patai 1994; cf. D. Wolf 1996: 35). This account of the various dilemmas posed by conducting research is by no means exhaustive and is intended only to highlight a number of the concerns and the ways in which they are being debated by feminist anthropologists and sociologists. Because of the depth and seeming intractability of the dilemmas posed, some have suggested that the appropriate recourse is not to engage in such research at all, to withdraw because it is so deeply problematic. If conducting research—even apparently progressive research—always reproduces an us/them, researcher/researched dichotomy, is the only, or appropriate, response a nihilist one? Margery Wolf notes that such a response is as politically irresponsible as not thinking through these questions at all. It leaves all research to the nonfeminist and noncritical researchers who have gone before and who will continue to conduct their work uninformed by any sense of the importance of an emancipatory politics and largely unconcerned by the relations of power and domination in which they are involved through their research activities (M. Wolf 1996: 216; see also D. Wolf 1996: 37–38). Suggesting that we withdraw from conducting research because it is problematic also reveals a great deal about what we, as critical or feminist IR scholars, expect from the research enterprise. The suggestion implies that we expect to feel comfortable, are on a “quest for rapport and unconditional acceptance” (Kaplan 1994: 150), and presume that feminist or critically informed research exists somehow above or beyond the lived material reality in which we find ourselves. It implies a response that in the end refuses to take seriously the words of Daphne Patai: “Self-reflexivity does not change reality. It does not redistribute income, gain political rights for the powerless, create housing for the homeless, or improve health” (1994: A52). Withdrawal from research would also deprive us of the most impor-
Feminist Research
159
tant insight that can be gained from conducting critical or feminist research in IR: We are as implicated in prevailing relations of power and domination as our mainstream predecessors, and because we view ourselves as oppositional and critical, we are in many ways less prepared than they to acknowledge this implication. This insight makes more complicated our perception of the circuits of power with which we are engaged, whether they be in relation to the subjects we research or the professionals we interact with. It reveals the need to see these interactions as integrally related and to politicize and historicize, as Caren Kaplan writes, “the relations of exchange that govern literacy, the production and marketing of texts, the politics of editing and distribution, and so on” (Kaplan 1994: 139). More important still, it means, again in Kaplan’s words, turning the terms of inquiry “from desiring, inviting and granting space to others to becoming accountable for one’s own investments in cultural metaphors and values” (139; my emphasis). Accountability will never mean that we can rest comfortably with our role as researchers and writers, but it can mean extending our critical concerns beyond the questions we ask to include the politics of how we ask—and answer—them.
Conclusion The argument in this chapter has been that although critical and feminist IR scholars have opened up what counts in the study of international relations, they have not begun to think carefully about the politics of conducting research on groups of people with relatively less power and privileges. They have noted that the investigator is implicated in the object of study, but only as they begin to give substance to this claim will they come faceto-face with the material lived reality of its implications. The debates and discussions of feminist anthropologists and sociologists suggest some practical ways of thinking through these dilemmas, but it is important to underline the extent to which their responses will always remain, at best, partial. Indeed, they must. The invisibilities and silences of which we accuse mainstream theorists will too quickly become our own if we do not soon engage in a sustained discussion of the practical and political implications confronting us in the conduct of critical and feminist research in IR.
Notes The author is grateful to the Social Science and Humanities Research Council of Canada for financial assistance received in support of this project.
160
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
1. I am grateful to Liz Philipose for this formulation. 2. The following pages are drawn from Whitworth 1998: 177–181. 3. UNTAC was cited as having contributed in another positive way to women’s lives: The Project Against Domestic Violence in Phnom Penh reported that in a context where few cases of domestic violence are ever reported to authorities and fewer still are prosecuted, one provincial judge described the only criminal case of domestic violence she had ever presided over as one in which UNTAC officers had brought in a man caught beating his wife in a marketplace (Zimmerman, Samen, and Savorn 1994: 137–142). 4. Most observers note that although UNTAC was not responsible for bringing HIV and AIDS to Cambodia, it did contribute to their spread. 5. Though this account reflects in part my own experiences, thinking through these experiences and trying to organize them has been much inspired by D. Wolf 1996, which covers these issues in far more detail than I do here.
10 DELIBERATIVE POLITICS, THE PUBLIC SPHERE, AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY Kenneth Baynes
A great deal of recent work in normative political theory dealing with international relations (IR) seems to have taken a decidedly cosmopolitan tone. I have in mind not only the important work of Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge but also many recent books, among them David Held’s Democracy and the Global Order (1995), James Rosenau’s Along the DomesticForeign Frontier (1997), Richard Falk’s On Humane Governance (1995), and Benjamin Barber’s Jihad vs. MacWorld (1995). Whether they place a renewed emphasis on human rights and the need for “global constitutionalism,” recognize the increasing globalization of the economy and the important role for both governmental and nongovernmental international organizations in new forms of “cosmopolitan governance,” or call anew for a “global civil society” to counter the expansion of both global consumerism and national tribalisms, the trend seems to be away from the exclusive or unrestricted sovereignty of nation states toward some form of cosmopolitanism. My purpose in the following remarks is to relate some of the concerns in these discussions to the recent work by Jürgen Habermas in legal and democratic theory. My guiding hypothesis is that each may have something to gain from the other: Habermas has not devoted a great deal of attention to international relations in his work on democratic theory (Mertens 1996), although in some of his more recent work, he has begun to compensate for this deficit (see, e.g., Habermas 1996a, 1997). This recent work has, in turn, given rise to a certain ambivalence in his position: On the one hand, he has expressed some support for the idea of a world government with coercive authority (Habermas 1996a, 1996b: 514, 1997). On the other hand, his general discussion of democracy in Between Facts and Norms (1996b) seems more or less to consider the nation state to be the 161
162
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
locus of democracy. This ambiguity is evident, I think, even in his idea of Verfassungspatriotismus, which implies at least some form of ongoing attachment or allegiance to the nation state even if it is primarily its own historically nuanced interpretation of universalistic constitutional principles (Habermas 1989b: 249–267; 1996b: 466, 500). At the same time, some of the recent work pointing to both the real possibility and indeed the practical necessity of a new cosmopolitanism— and I am thinking here in particular of Barber, Falk, and Rosenau—may nonetheless be able to find further conceptual resources in Habermas’s normative reflections and, in particular, in the less substantial or “proceduralist” conception of popular sovereignty and democracy he has proposed. In the following, I first sketch Habermas’s recent conception, noting some of its central features. Then I examine some concerns among recent “cosmopolitans,” especially those arguing for a more differentiated conception of sovereignty. Finally, by way of conclusion, I offer some reflections on the idea of a cosmopolitan public sphere.
*
*
*
In Between Facts and Norms Habermas introduces his model of procedural democracy by way of a contrast between two highly stylized alternatives (Habermas 1996b: 267f.; see also 1994b): liberal and republican (or communitarian). These have become familiar reference points in recent discussions. Cass Sunstein, for example, has recently summarized the liberal model well: “Self-interest, not virtue, is understood to be the usual motivating force of political behavior. Politics is typically, if not always, an effort to aggregate private interests. It is surrounded by checks, in the form of rights, protecting private liberty and private property from public intrusion” (Sunstein 1991: 4). By contrast, republicanism characteristically places more emphasis on the value of citizens’ public virtues and active political participation. Politics is regarded more as a deliberative process in which citizens seek to reach agreement about the common good, and law is not seen as a means for protecting individual rights but as the expression of the common praxis of the political community. With his procedural democracy Habermas attempts to incorporate the best features of both models while avoiding the shortcomings of each. In particular, along with the republican model, procedural democracy rejects the liberal vision of the political process as primarily a process of competition and aggregation of private preferences. However, more in keeping with the liberal model, Habermas regards the republican vision of a citizenry united and actively motivated by a shared conception of the good life as unrealistic in modern, pluralist societies.1 Moreover, since political discourses involve bargaining and negotiation as well as moral argumentation,
Deliberative Politics
163
the republican, or communitarian, notion of a shared ethical-political dialogue also seems inappropriate. According to discourse theory, the success of deliberative politics depend not on a collectively acting citizenry but on the institutionalization of the corresponding procedures and conditions of communication, as well as on the interplay of institutionalized deliberative processes with informally constituted public opinions. (Habermas 1996b: 298)
What is central for this conception is not a shared ethos but institutionalized discourses for the formation of rational political opinion. This idea of a suitably interpreted deliberative politics lies at the center of Habermas’s model of a procedural democracy. In a deliberative politics, attention shifts away from the final act of voting and the problems of social choice that accompany it (see also Manin 1987; Miller 1992). The model represents an attempt to take seriously the fact that often enough preferences are not exogenous to the political system but “are instead adaptive to a wide range of factors—including the context in which the preference is expressed, the existing legal rules, past consumption choices, and culture in general” (Sunstein 1991: 5; see also Elster 1983). The aim of a deliberative politics is, accordingly, to provide a context for a transformation of preferences in response to the considered views of others and the “laundering,” or filtering, of irrational or morally repugnant preferences in ways that are not excessively paternalistic (Goodin 1985). The conditions for a more rational politics (that is, a political process in which the outcomes are more informed, future oriented, and other-regarding) can be improved, for example, by designing institutions of political will formation so that they reflect the more complex preference structure of individuals rather than simply register the actual preferences individuals have at any given time. Specific proposals for realizing the ideals of a deliberative politics could range from something like James Fishkin’s idea of a “deliberative opinion poll” to alternative procedures of voting and modes of representation (Fishkin 1990; McLean 1991; Young 1989). One could, in this sense, even speak of an extension of democracy to preferences themselves, since the question is whether the reasons offered in support of them are ones that could meet the requirements of public justification.2 What is important for this notion of deliberation, however, is less that everyone participate—or even that voting be made public—than that there is a warranted presumption that public opinion is formed on the basis of adequate information and relevant reasons and that those whose interests are involved have an equal and effective opportunity to make their own interests (and the reasons for them) known. Two further features serve to distinguish Habermas’s model of procedural democracy and deliberative politics from other recent versions of a deliberative democracy. First, this version of deliberative politics extends
164
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
beyond the more formally organized political system to the vast and complex communication network that Habermas calls “the public sphere.” [Deliberative politics] is bound to the demanding communicative presuppositions of political arenas that do not coincide with the institutionalized will-formation in parliamentary bodies but extend equally to the political public sphere and to its cultural context and social basis. A deliberative practice of self-determination can develop only in the interplay between, on the one hand, the parliamentary will-formation institutionalized in legal procedures and programmed to reach decisions and, on the other, political opinion-building in informal circles of political communication. (Habermas 1996b: 274–275)
The model suggests a two-track process in which there is a division of labor between weak publics (the informally organized public sphere ranging from private associations to the mass media located in civil society) and strong publics (parliamentary bodies and other formally organized institutions of the political system). Habermas takes these terms from Nancy Fraser, who used them to describe Habermas’s two-track conception of democracy (see Fraser 1992). In this division of labor, weak publics assume a central responsibility for identifying, interpreting, and addressing social problems: For a good part of the normative expectations connected with deliberative politics now falls on the peripheral structures of opinion-formation. The expectations are directed at the capacity to perceive, interpret, and present encompassing social problems in a way both attention-catching and innovative. (Habermas 1996b: 358)
However, decisionmaking responsibility, as well as the further filtering of reasons via more formal parliamentary procedures, remains the task of a strong public (e.g., the formally organized political system). Second, along with this division of labor between strong and weak publics and as a consequence of his increased acknowledgment of the “decentered” character of modern societies, Habermas argues that radical democratic practice must assume a “self-limiting” form. Democratization is now focused not on society as a whole but on the legal system broadly conceived (Habermas 1996b: 371). In particular, he maintains, it must respect the boundaries of the political-administrative and economic subsystems that have become relatively independent of the integrative force of communicative action and are in this sense autonomous. Failure to do so, he believes, at least partially explains the failure of state socialism (Habermas 1990b). For Habermas, the goal of radical democracy thus becomes not the democratic organization of these subsystems but rather a type of indirect steering of them through the medium of law. In this connection, he also
Deliberative Politics
165
describes the task of an opinion-forming public sphere as that of “laying siege” to the formally organized political system by encircling it with reasons without, however, attempting to overthrow or replace it (Habermas 1996b: 486–487 [appendix 1]). These two features raise a number of difficult questions about the scope and limits of democratization. Given the metaphorical language often employed in his discussion, it is not obvious what specific proposals for mediating between weak and strong publics would follow from his model. Some have questioned, for example, whether he has not conceded too much to systems theory, and Nancy Fraser, in an instructive discussion of Habermas’s conception of the public sphere, raises the question whether there might not be other ways in which the division of labor between strong and weak publics could be drawn (Fraser 1992: 135f.; cf. Cohen and Rogers 1992). Habermas’s own response, I think, would be that an answer to these questions will not be found at the level of normative theory but depends on the empirical findings of complex comparative studies. A second, more general question that arises in connection with this model of democracy is whether Habermas’s confidence in the rationalizing effect of procedures alone is well founded. In view of his own description of weak publics as “wild,” “anarchic,” and “unrestricted,” the suspicion can at least be raised whether discursive procedures will suffice to bring about a rational public opinion (Habermas 1996b: 308). To be sure, he states that a deliberative politics depends on a “rationalized lifeworld” (including a “liberal political culture”) that “meets it halfway” (Habermas 1996b: 302; see also Habermas 1990a: 207–208; Offe 1992). Thus for Habermas, a genuinely deliberative politics will require a sufficiently “disenchanted” world in which normative questions can be distinguished from truth claims as well as a more or less liberal background culture (or “civil society”) in which questions of personal morality can be distinguished from questions of political or social justice. Still, without more attention to the particular “liberal virtues” that constitute the shared political culture and give rise to some notion of shared purposes, it is difficult to see how Habermas’s model can address some of the concerns raised by more recent politics of identity and the apparent loss of any notion of a common or shared political community in the modern liberal state (Dworkin 1988; Macedo 1990; see also Buchwalter 1992: 576). Finally, in connection with our present focus on international relations and global democracy, a third general question can be raised: Has Habermas drawn all of the relevant or even most appropriate conclusions from his own proceduralized interpretation of democracy and popular sovereignty? Given Habermas’s attempt to minimize any substantive dimension to the notion of a popular will and to emphasize instead an idea of popular sovereignty that is found in “those subjectless forms of communi-
166
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
cation that regulate the flow of discursive opinion- and will-formation,” the question can be asked what role, if any, more traditional territorial political boundaries ought to play in his conception of democracy (Habermas 1996b: 486). I have already referred to a certain ambivalence on this issue in Habermas’s work. Nonetheless, it is also the case that recent reflections on some possible forms of a cosmopolitan democracy might find additional conceptual resources in Habermas’s own two-track, procedural approach. For example, his distinction between strong and weak publics might also perform an important function at the international level, and his remarks on the self-limitation of democracy would seem to support recent calls for a more differentiated or dispersed conception of sovereignty. Let me first recall some of this discussion concerning a new cosmopolitanism.
*
*
*
The new cosmopolitanism, or universalism, itself has taken different forms (not all of which are equally inimical to the nation state, though all would challenge its claims to undivided internal and external sovereignty). One form is a renewed insistence on respect for human rights that transcends national boundaries and concerns—reflected, for example, in the revival of interest in theories of international justice (Beitz 1979; Vincent 1986; Pogge 1994). Another form is expressed in the call for a new world order with greater power delegated to international governmental bodies such as the UN. Finally, still others argue for a global constitutionalism or global governance in which power and authority is shared among the three systems of the nation states, international governmental institutions, and nongovernmental organizations and citizens’ associations of various sorts (see especially Falk, Johansen, and Kim 1993; Rosenau 1997). Without specifically endorsing any one of these proposals to the exclusion of another, I would like to explore an alternative way to address some of the deeper concerns that motivate them. My remarks fall within the range of what might be called Kantian cosmopolitanism, since they preserve an important role for the nation state but nevertheless question the conception of exclusive sovereignty assumed in most democratic theory. In other words, rather than a shift from the nation state to a world state in which the underlying conception of sovereignty remains unchallenged, I would like to explore the possibility of a more differentiated conception of external sovereignty that parallels a proposal I have made elsewhere (in response to the communitarians) for a more differentiated conception of internal sovereignty (Baynes 1992, 1997). As David Held points out in his informative essay “Democracy and the Global System,” modern republican theory, including recent democratic theory, generally works with an unquestioned conception of political sover-
Deliberative Politics
167
eignty in which the state is conceived as “a circumscribed structure of power with supreme jurisdiction over a territory accountable to a determinate citizen body” (Held 1991: 223). Democratic theory in particular assumes a remarkably unitary conception of sovereignty in its commitment to what Held calls a “symmetrical” and “congruent” relationship between political decisionmakers and the recipients of political decision: In fact, symmetry and congruence are assumed at two crucial points: first, between citizen-voters and the decision-makers whom they are, in principle, able to hold to account; and secondly, between the “output” (decisions, policies, etc.) of decision-makers and their constituents—ultimately, “the people” in a delimited territory. (Held 1991: 198)
The idea of sovereignty presumably strengthens this general conception of democracy both by localizing the power and authority in a single agency that can be held accountable to the citizenry and by defining through territorial boundaries the relevant group for which the sovereign is responsible and to which it can be held accountable. Internal and external sovereignty thus mesh well with this common interpretation of democracy. However, as Held (along with many others) points out, this conception of sovereignty is barely recognizable in the contemporary world. Trends toward global interconnectedness have both modified and constrained the exercise of sovereignty and called into question its assumptions about symmetry and congruence. Processes of globalization have produced structures of decisionmaking that are less tied to the legal jurisdiction of the nation state and hence also less accountable; at the same time those decisions still made within the legal framework of the nation state frequently have consequences that go well beyond national territorial borders. In support of this claim regarding increased constraint upon not only the state’s de facto autonomy but also its sovereignty, Held points to structural changes within national political economies and the growing power and maneuverability of multinational corporations, to recent developments in international law, and to the emergence of hegemonic powers and power blocs (like the North Atlantic Treaty Organization [NATO] or the European Union [EU]) that make it difficult for independent nation states to pursue policies exclusively on their own terms. Held then concludes: These processes alone warrant the statement that the operation of states in an ever more complex international system both limits their autonomy and impinges increasingly upon their sovereignty. Any conception of sovereignty which interprets it as an illimitable and indivisible form of public power is undermined. Sovereignty itself has to be conceived today as already divided among a number of agencies—national, regional, and international—and limited by the very nature of this plurality. (Held 1991: 222)
168
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
Following a suggestion of Hedley Bull, Held describes the results of these trends toward globalization as a kind of “neo-medieval international order—a modern and secular counterpart to the kind of political organization that existed in Christian Europe in the Middle Ages, the essential characteristic of which was ‘a system of overlapping authority and multiple loyalties’” (Held 1991: 223). In contrast to Hedley Bull, however, Held suggests that the model of overlapping authorities and criss-crossing loyalties may continue to offer some normatively attractive features. In his essay “Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty,” Thomas Pogge has also proposed a model of differentiated or dispersed sovereignty in connection with a cosmopolitan ideal: What I am proposing instead is not the idea of a world state, which is really a variant of the pre-eminent state idea. Rather, the proposal is that governmental authority—or sovereignty—be widely dispersed in the vertical dimension. What we need is both centralization and decentralization—a kind of second-order decentralization away from the now dominant level of the state. (Pogge 1994: 99)
As Pogge goes on to point out, differentiated or dispersed sovereignty is not simply the product of actual social, political, and economic trends; considerations of peace and security, global economic justice, and environmental preservation provide reasons for preferring such dispersed sovereignty from a normative point of view as well. Equally important for Pogge is the consideration of democracy itself: “Persons have a right to an institutional order under which those significantly and legitimately affected by a political decision have a roughly equal opportunity to influence the making of this decision—either directly or through elected delegates or representatives” (Pogge 1994: 105). For Pogge, as for Held, increasing global interdependence requires that new forms of decisionmaking be developed that are able to secure simultaneously mechanisms for local autonomy and effective input and accountability on global issues that impact individual lives—in other words, both centralization and decentralization in a dispersal of state sovereignty. Of course, as Held also points out, these trends have not made the nation state irrelevant or obsolete, and the trends are themselves highly ambivalent so far as concerns the values of global justice, peace and security, and—perhaps especially—democratic rule (see also Rosenau 1997: 232; D. Miller 1995). However, what they nonetheless indicate at a normative level is the need to think creatively about global constitutionalism in ways freed from the unitary conception of external sovereignty (assumed in most contemporary democratic theory, including that of Habermas). For example, although a simultaneous democratization and strengthening of the powers of the UN in the post–Cold War world remain one obvious (and
Deliberative Politics
169
desirable) option, a single centralized world government with coercive police powers is not the only alternative to the current system of nation states. Other possibilities for global constitutionalism that would bring together in democratically creative ways the existing system of states, international governmental institutions, and a global civil society comprising a variety of nongovernmental organizations and citizens’ associations remain to be explored. It is in this context that some of Habermas’s proposals concerning a procedural and two-track conception of democracy are most relevant for normative theorizing. On the one hand, his division of labor between weak and strong publics draws attention to the important role of civil society—as a domain analytically distinct from both the economy and the administrative state—in processes of communication and the formation of public opinion. This tripartite model provides a useful framework within which issues of global democracy can be discussed and the increasingly fashionable idea of a global civil society located (Lipschutz 1996). This model identifies neither the territorial administrative state nor the transnational market economy as the primary locus for the identification, thematization, and communication of relevant issues and concerns—that is, the formation of public opinion—but the vast and pluralistic network of associations and citizens’ groups that compose the informal public sphere within civil society. Relevant in this context as well, although it should not be overestimated, is the development of new telecommunications technology and forms of global communication media that provide a powerful tool for citizens’ groups to convey information rapidly and widely and thereby shape public opinion (for a balanced discussion, see Barber 1997: 208–228). This conception of civil society, with its corresponding weak publics, is not, however, a panacea, and as Habermas himself notes, the mere presence of global communication media does not alone ensure more reasoned and informed deliberation among the relevant parties (see Habermas 1992b: 456; see also Baynes 1994). On the other hand, the idea of strong publics—which bear responsibility for accountable decisionmaking in Habermas’s theory—can be imagined in a more dispersed and overlapping manner along the lines proposed by Held, Pogge, and others. In fact, it is precisely the procedural conception of democracy—one not tied to a specific ethnic or national identity—that provides occasion for rethinking this idea of dispersed sovereignty along more functional and less territorial or substantialized lines. Of course, the idea of cosmopolitan democracy or global constitutionalism itself raises extremely difficult questions of accountability and democratic legitimacy. Like the corresponding differentiation of internal sovereignty, the differentiation of external sovereignty would have to proceed in a way that would ensure that the various authorities remain accountable to
170
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
the parties affected by their actions. Such authorities would also have to be constituted in a way consistent with basic individual rights and principles of democratic legitimacy. I have no more specific recommendations to offer in this regard other than to refer again to some of the tentative proposals for a democratic neocorporatism. At a minimum, however, the conception of differentiated (internal and external) sovereignty would seem to require both a corresponding cosmopolitan and pluralist public sphere capable of taking up in different ways and at various levels problems and thematic issues bearing on the formation of international policies and institutional forums of decisionmaking that would guarantee accountability to those most affected by the decisions made.
Notes 1. Habermas cites Frank Michelman’s “Law’s Republic” as an example of this sort of republicanism; he might also have referred to some of the writings of Charles Taylor. Habermas’s own position seems closest, however, to the “Madisonian” republicanism of Cass Sunstein (Sunstein 1988). 2. Although I think Donald Moon overestimates the dangers of “unconstrained conversation,” especially for individual privacy rights, he points to the difficult question concerning the kinds of institutional design that are appropriate to help ensure that the deliberations conducted in unconstrained conversation influence the process of decisionmaking. Should there, for example, be a system of public voting (see Moon 1991)?
11 CREATING COSMOPOLITAN POWER: INTERNATIONAL MEDIATION AS COMMUNICATIVE ACTION Deiniol Lloyd Jones
In his Keywords, Raymond Williams notes that the term mediation has “long been a relatively complex word in English” and that “it has been made very much more complex by its uses as a key term in several systems of thought” (Williams 1988: 204). As Williams points out, mediation has been used in a political sense to describe the reconciliation of adversaries, in a metaphysical sense to describe the reconciliation of humans with their own nature, and in a religious sense to describe the reconciliation of humanity with a transcendent God. The meaning of mediation is traditionally complex, and in this chapter I discuss some of these complexities. Unfortunately, perhaps, I wish to complicate things further by demonstrating how new thinking about international relations (IR) creates an alternative account of agency and international mediation. I hope that the critical account of mediation introduced in this chapter will become a “keyword” in the now prevalent postpositivist, realist international relations vocabulary. In this chapter I discuss the topic of international mediation from a perspective informed by critical IR theory. Concentrating on questions of agency and practice, I attempt to answer the following questions: What agents in international politics are mediators? What strategies or tactics do they employ? Three sets of answers to these questions are explored: the power political, or geostrategic; the facilitative, or problem solving; and the critical, or cosmopolitan. The first two approaches are traditional in the sense that they represent a fairly well known body of writing. The third approach is a new paradigm based on insights into the practical and theoretical failures of the existing debate. A brief definition of the new approach might proceed as follows. 171
172
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
Mediation is the application of democratic public law and the creation of a dialogic community in a situation of conflict. Mediation is the creation of cosmopolitan solutions to international disputes. Owing to the complexity of this task, the likely mediators will be coalitions of states embedded in regional security frameworks committed to the realization of a cosmopolitan international order. Mediation as communicative action demands the creation of what I will call cosmopolitan power. I use this phrase in two senses: The mediator is a cosmopolitan power, and the political agreement that results from a critical mediation process creates cosmopolitan power. Viewing the topic in terms of the creation of cosmopolitan power combines the normative agency of the facilitative approach with the recognition that forms of strategic and instrumental action are often needed when mediating disputes. Yet mediation as communicative action is not geostrategy plus facilitation where the two forms of diplomacy remain discrete forms of action to be employed during different phases of conflict resolution’s long cycle of reform. Rather, mediation as communicative action is a distinct paradigm that combines unique forms of practice and a distinct normative thrust. Cosmopolitan power, democratic public law, and the dialogic community were all absent from the Oslo process, the most recent mediated peace process between Israel and Palestine and the focus of the concluding section of the chapter. Arguably, and contrary to popular opinion, this process collapsed because of reasons that were internal to its nature rather than for reasons imposed, as it were, from the outside—for example, the assassination of Yitzhak Rabin or the election of a Likud government, though these events were obviously influential. Some of the reasons for the failure of Oslo, I suggest, stem from the absence of the type of mediation I describe in this chapter.
Mediation in Our International System Mediation is a form of conflict resolution that stresses the vital role of a third party in the process of creating peace and facilitating agreement between erstwhile disputing actors. Mediation plays a prominent role in contemporary international affairs. The constitution of the only form of contemporary international government refers to mediation as a form of conflict resolution. Article 33 of the UN charter requires all parties to an international dispute that is likely to “endanger the maintenance of international peace” to submit to a mediation process. Whenever historic or epoch-making international events make the headlines, a mediator has often played a role in shaping these events. The prominence of this type of international politics, where a few individuals make decisions that may
Creating Cosmopolitan Power
173
affect the lives of millions, entails the need for serious critical analysis and debate within the theory of international relations. Forms of critique can be fruitfully applied to international mediation. Critical IR theorists should always strive to peer beyond what Noam Chomsky calls “language in the service of propaganda” (Chomsky 1992). As George Orwell writes in his essay “Politics and the English Language,” “Adjectives like epoch-making, epic, historic, unforgettable, triumphant, age-old, inevitable, inexorable, veritable, are all used to dignify the sordid processes of international politics” (Orwell 1984: 352). Typically, and unfortunately, these ideological and honorific adjectives are all used in connection with mediated “peace processes,” “new world orders,” and the like and obscure more than they illuminate. The media may parrot “peace process” as if in a trance—to refer, for example, to the mere fact that some sort of negotiations are taking place. However, the theory of international relations is rightly charged with giving some normative direction and sense to the empty tokens of popular conflict-resolution discourse. But despite mediation’s unhealthy relationship with what Orwell calls the sordid processes of international politics, serious commitments to maintaining international order are going to have to rely, at least in part, on relatively informal mediation processes. For in the absence of any clear form of global government, mediations, sanctioned by the rules of a normatively structured international order, could represent an informal diplomatic tool capable of pursuing just and workable political settlements to contemporary international conflicts.
The Failures of Power Politics Existing forms of mediation agency and practice are flawed. There are two forms of agency and practice—the power political, or geostrategic, and the facilitative, or problem solving. These traditions may be associated with, on the one hand, the social philosophy of positivism and, on the other hand, the more interpretivist, or hermeneutic, tradition of social philosophy—the historic rival to the growth of the “human sciences.” The former relies on a distinction between facts and values or power and morality. The latter emphasizes the intersubjective constitution of social reality. In the power political approach, third parties are neorealist states. Third parties become involved in conflicts to increase their power relative to other actors in the anarchical structure of the international system. Mediation may represent an opportunity for a third party to gain power and leverage, or it may be necessary to avoid certain unwanted costs. In this analysis, costs and benefits are conceived in realist terms—control over economic, political, and military resources. The power political approach
174
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
also tends to emphasize absolute rather than relative gains. On this understanding, mediation is a form of bargaining where actors trade tangible goods. Thus for power politics, the cultural or moral ends of a society have to be transformed into a tradable item if they are to enter into the mediation process. For example, national rights over a historic capital could be traded for concessions on trade terms or lower interest rates. Culture and morality are rationalized by the power political mediation. There are problems facing the power political approach. Power political–geostrategic agency rests on what Linklater has called the immutability thesis—the view that the international system is a structure of competitive strategic relationships; this structure is immune to historical change and banishes questions of the good or the right from international politics (Linklater 1996b). However, there is no conclusive evidence, whether historical, empirical, or philosophical, to support the structuralist argument. It is commonly recognized within the theory of international relations that the conditions of moral agency—ought to implies can—are not systematically banished from international discourse altogether. Whether they like it or not, mediators are moral agents. A further problem is that societies in conflict experience severe or acute forms of crisis that affect social relations at levels “below” the state. Crises of societal reproduction both threaten and involve the store of cultural knowledge, the individual personality, and the possibility of social integration (Habermas 1984, 1989a). However, power political agency works on a state-to-state level. States and the realities and facts of power constitute the stuff of society and history for the power political view— what Barry Buzan calls the “timeless wisdom” of realism (Buzan 1996). There is thus a danger that power political agency will create political orders without social roots or a historical basis. Edward Said discusses the Camp David agreements in these terms. Said argues that the agreements in the Middle East in the late 1970s were an artificial structure imposed on the “natural” course of history and events (Said 1979: 171). A fundamental problem is that power political approaches subsume the regional dynamics of a conflict under a wider struggle for global mastery and power; thus they prime a local conflict with all the tensions of global politics. We can see that process occurring during the late 1960s and early 1970s when U.S. secretary of state Henry Kissinger intervened in the Arab-Israeli struggle on the basis of a Cold War mentality. Sinai I and II plus the Camp David agreements lifted the local conflict between Israel and the states on its borders above the concerns of international law. They also reduced the autonomy of the regional actors who found themselves unable to pursue local policies without the necessary blessing from the superpower patron. Though the Cold War is over, these regional reflections of global dynamics continue to influence history, and they render conflict resolution
Creating Cosmopolitan Power
175
extremely difficult. Israel, for example, still benefits from massive financial and military aid dispensed by the remaining superpower, and many, including those within Israeli society itself, argue that this aid makes the possibility of compromise with Israel’s Arab neighbors, particularly the Palestinians, more rather than less remote. Where all forms of local political life are forced to link themselves to a global mind-set that has remote origins, there often follows a lack of regional responsibility. All sorts of strange ideologies that purport to explain and unify the complex realities of global society are created, and these ruin the chances of a sensible regional politics. As we shall see, the Oslo process tried to remedy these difficulties by placing responsibility for conflict resolution in the laps of regional actors—the Israeli Labor government and, more significant, the Palestine Liberation Organization (PLO). The collapse of the Soviet Union by 1991 “naturally” assisted this goal. Yet the resurrection of regional autonomy was also an intentional political act. The Americans were not informed about the “success” of the secret backchannel in Oslo until it had actually produced an agreement. Supporters of the Oslo channel trace its success, at least in part, to the resurrection of regional autonomy through facilitation. Although local politics can never be entirely separated from global concerns, in the case of Oslo the aim was to short-circuit the political and media circus in Washington by bringing the disputants face-to-face.
The Failures of Facilitation Facilitators tend to be small states or nonstate actors, such as academics or church leaders, who are committed to social change. Facilitators recognize the social or intersubjective character of reality and argue that even atomized strategic action may require a shared consensus about the rules of social life before it can take. In a power political model, the two sides have to be prepared to bargain with each other, and this attitude implies a certain degree of mutual recognition. Facilitators note, however, that cognitive and existential psychological obstacles can stand in the way of conflict resolution based only on strategic bargaining. Cognitive barriers to negotiation may involve problems of poor information and decisionmaking in uncertainty. Here facilitators act as conduits of information, reassuring disputing actors of mutual rationality and thus enabling virtuous cycles of cooperation. More significant, however, are existential psychological barriers to dialogue. Individuals who live through acute international conflict often console themselves with stories of their own virtue and the wickedness of others; facilitators call this dynamic the demonization of the other. Even where these stories or narratives are obviously exaggerated, they persist in the cultural and historical memory and
176
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
make forward-looking forms of politics extremely difficult to construct. Facilitators create a social setting where dialogue can resume as the other becomes recognized as a potential moral agent in, to use Hans-Georg Gadamer’s phrase, “a fusion of horizons.” Problems facing the facilitator stem from the fact that the facilitator lacks strategic power. Or rather, the forms of strategic power possessed by the facilitator are limited to the application of social psychology—what Michael Banks and Chris Mitchell call “dispassionate theory” or “formal technique” (Banks and Mitchell 1996: ix). Facilitators are masters of communication in the problem-solving workshop. They “sell” social scientific expertise. But to gain influence with disputants, facilitators must, in a sense, prostrate themselves before the disputants in the conflict situation. Like a psychoanalyst, they must offer tact, secrecy, and privacy, and they must avoid introducing their own values and opinions into the conflict situation. In a world of playground bullies, facilitators must act, according to one Norwegian facilitator, as the friend to both sides. Facilitators must be trusted and must not appear as a threat. Thus private individuals, academics, and weak or small states in the international system make successful facilitators. The Norwegians, for example, owed their place as facilitators in the Oslo process to their possession of these qualities. The Norwegians offered secrecy. They had no obvious strategic interest in the outcome of the dispute other than the universal goal of peace and stability, and, owing to their weakness, disputants could claim that no outside powers were interfering with state security, especially important in the case of Israel. However, given that facilitative action is, as it were, value free, abstract, and more concerned with instituting procedures, how does facilitation propose to achieve its normative goals—the goals that Banks and Mitchell refer to as “stability, peace, justice, progress and legitimised authority” (Banks and Mitchell 1996: viii)? A recent attempt to marry facilitation with the creation of substantive normative goals has involved the introduction of critical political practice. Mark Hoffman argues, for example, that facilitation, “emphasises the centrality of an analytic and relational empathy, a shared sense of ‘otherness,’ which becomes discernible through something like a process of Habermasean ‘communicative ethics’” (Hoffman 1995: 10). Jay Rothman, another academic who has thought long and hard about these issues, also refers to Habermas’s political ethics (Rothman 1992). Habermas has strong links with the traditions of interpretative sociology; thus the turn toward Habermas on the part of the theory of facilitation is a sensible and understandable one. The hope is that facilitation can (1) take account of the rational redemption of moral and political claims, (2) still remain at a formal or procedural level, (3) deliver on the promise to achieve substantial
Creating Cosmopolitan Power
177
normative goals, and (4) retain the strong links with the tradition of interpretative sociology. Although these recent developments in the theory of facilitation are a step in the right direction, facilitation faces a fundamental problem. Facilitation theory works with the assumption that conflict is based on the inability to engage in forms of dialogue rather than on an unwillingness to engage in forms of democratic dialogue. Or rather, any unwillingness to engage in democratic dialogue is the result of social-psychological obstacles rather than a political or moral commitment. I call this argument the objection from rational intransigence. In facilitation theory, intransigence toward dialogue is the result of distortions in communication that the parties may themselves view as irrational in the sense that their existence is recognized by a disputant to impede the pursuit of goals that the disputant actually identifies as an interest. In this situation, the facilitator acts like a psychoanalyst assisting the disputants’ own efforts to move the political process forward. However, the objection from rational intransigence points out that intransigence toward the creation of, for example, the dialogic community can be, for one or more disputant, a political or moral end in itself. Here, obstacles to the intersubjective construction of political reality are the result of conscious or deliberate obstructions to the democratic process. Thus one or more disputant (1) may understand, cognitively, the conflict situation perfectly and (2) may have the social and psychological ability to recognize the other yet (3) may still have no desire to enter into a politics more attuned to dialogic relations. In a situation of rational intransigence, the application of a facilitative technique may merely give the upper hand to the intransigent party. Edward Said puts the point in the following way. Assessing the efficacy of the problem-solving workshop, he writes: “Can one imagine endorsing similar discussion between a few well intentioned German and French intellectuals during the occupation of France?” (Said 1995: 35). Said argues that dialogue must be rooted in action. In terms of the Israeli-Palestinian conflict, for example, Said prefers the intifada to the Oslo process and argues that the former is an “authentic intellectual idiom” and not merely a “discourse of politics” (Said 1995). The references to Jürgen Habermas in the literature of facilitation to date have more in common with Habermas’s earlier model of critical social theory that was based on the idea of unconscious, systematically distorted communication. They neglect the later emphasis on moral-deontological theory. For the critical analyst, however, violent social conflict can also occur because there are political forces oblivious to the moral duty that demands that political orders be redeemed with reference to the right. This stance is rational intransigence, and it is hard to see how facilitators could combat it given that their power is limited to the application of social-psy-
178
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
chological techniques. Facilitators are correct to turn to critical practice to boost their normative and practical energies. As a result, however, they have to accept the deontological side to critical practice, which, in the discourse ethics of Habermas, for example, distinguishes between right and wrong and not merely between the rational and the irrational, the conscious and the unconscious.
Creating Cosmopolitan Power We start to remedy some of the difficulties with the preceding approaches when we turn toward the recent critical writing in international relations. Mediation as communicative action begins with a set of normative standards rooted in Kantian political theory. Habermas, for example, turns Marxist sociology back to its Enlightenment roots in order to provide a defense of reason capable of withstanding the worst ravages of postmodern skepticism. Habermas’s normative understanding is Kantian in character. The mark of moral consciousness in discourse ethics—Habermas’s boldest statement of moral theory—is deontological (concerned with duty), cognitivist (aiming to deliver moral knowledge), formal (it does not prescribe substantive injunctions), and universal (the moral point of view is deemed to apply across time and space). The debates surrounding Habermas’s attempt to breathe life into the Enlightenment project are too wide in scope to detail here. However, the test of universalism is applied only when events threaten the basic fundamental and generalizable interests of disputing. The results of communicative action are always open to revision in the light of new knowledge and experience. The application of the rules of procedural justice is itself a moral question.1 A critical mediator wishes to create a peace process based on a principle of universalization. As Habermas writes, “All affected can accept the consequences and the side effects its general observance can be anticipated to have for the satisfaction of everyone’s interests and these consequences are preferred to those of known alternative possibilities for regulation” (Habermas 1990a: 65; my emphasis). Put rather succinctly, the principle of universalization embodies and creates what David Held has called “democratic public law,” or it embodies and creates what Linklater has called the “dialogic community” (Held 1995, Linklater 1998). What strategies and tactics are involved in this process, and are these different from the strategies and tactics as described in the previous paradigms? Is the critical mediator a power politician or a facilitator? Or are there alternative forms of practice that can be called critical mediation practice? Critical forms of practice can be discerned by examining the problems
Creating Cosmopolitan Power
179
facing the introduction of the principle of universalization. A discourse theory of morality has a vision of an ideal society in which all parties can enter the political process as equals. These parties judge any claim that may be advanced, and they do so without any prior assumption about the nature of ultimate outcome other than the desire that it should embody the results of democratic procedure. In Habermas’s terms, cosmopolitan morality presupposes postconventional reasoning. The problem, however, is that his ideal can be approximated only in reality—if it can be realized at all. For example, disputing parties may not be able to discuss certain positions in the context of the dialogic community without immediately losing public office. It is unlikely that a political party in Israel, for example, could campaign for national rights for Palestinians and also remain in power. Thus the application of democratic law and the attempt to realize the ethics of the dialogic community may result in a hopeless antagonism between the mediator and one or more of the disputants with the result that the mediator is disqualified as an impartial outside agent. One of the strengths of facilitation, it might be argued, is that it works with a concept of politics more attuned to the real problems of protracted social conflict. One of the strengths of power politics, it might be argued, is that it does not have overly idealistic ambitions for the international world. These objections are important. Does it follow, however, that all forms of mediation practice are facilitative or power political? The answer to this question is no. Mediation can combine might with right, to put the matter colloquially, if it aims at the creation of cosmopolitan power. I mean this term in two senses. First, the mediator can become a cosmopolitan power, a power capable of commanding resources and influencing outcomes, even in a situation marked by rational intransigence. Second, the mediator can work to create cosmopolitan power in the context of the dispute. If we conceive of the mediator as a cosmopolitan power, it is possible to avoid both the problem of amorality that is posed by the power political approach and the problem of weakness in the face of rational intransigence, which is posed by the facilitative approach. The mediator intervenes as a resourceful, strategic third party that aims to strengthen the forces of democracy and dialogue within the region in dispute. This approach is similar to what one writer has recently called a “governance-based approach” to international mediation. F. O. Hampson writes: “Governance-based approaches see the challenge of peacebuilding and third party involvement in terms of the creation of participatory governance structures, the development of new social norms, and the establishment of the rule of law and democracy” (Hampson 1997: 737). The critical approach attempts to ensure that those parties who are committed to negotiations in a dialogic community receive all the diplomatic, technical, economic, and political support necessary to defeat the forces of intransigence.
180
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
There are, of course, risks associated with this approach. The intransigent parties are likely to regard the external power as hostile and might aim to disrupt its plans. And rather than forcing a compromise, the mobilization of democratic power may actually lead to an escalation of the conflict. Hampson notes: “Governance-based approaches underestimate the difficulties of democratisation and the unstable political forces that may be unleashed by democratic institutions and processes in societies unaccustomed to democracy and the rules of law” (Hampson 1997: 737). Furthermore, this type of intervention is likely to be expensive and difficult to manage. It would involve long-term commitment and expense measured in political, economic, and diplomatic terms. For these reasons, cosmopolitan forms of mediation practice are best managed by coalitions of states embedded in regional security frameworks. This type of organization would have the resources needed for cosmopolitan mediation. The likely agents of critical mediations would be coalitions of states, international institutions, organizations, and nonstate actors bound together through treaty and mutual obligation whose foreign policies are motivated by the creation of cosmopolitan democratic public law. Like the power political paradigm, the critical approach involves states. Yet there are significant differences between the critical and the power political approach in terms of identifying the relevant actors. First, the critical or cosmopolitan mediator does not exist in a neorealist moral philosophy or history. The cosmopolitan mediator believes in the possibility of profound and meaningful historical change. Second, the activities of these states are subject to moral and political standards enshrined in treaty and law that are derived from cosmopolitan political principles, for example, those detailed in the thought of theorists such as Habermas, Held, and Linklater. Basically, critical mediators are neo-Kantians on the international stage. Third, the critical approach emphasizes the importance of building coalitions. In the power political paradigm, the mediator is normally a sovereign, unitary, and discrete actor—either, for example, a single state or a superpower. The critical mediator, however, is not a solitary unit, and the hope is that the process of coalition building will avoid the worst sins of national self-interest and that egoism and political projects containing more generalizable interests will emerge as a result. Like the facilitative paradigm, the critical approach works with a more culturally sensitive social philosophy, and it shares the ambition that mediation can create social change and a normatively desirable outcome. However, unlike the facilitative paradigm, the critical approach insists that change in international conflict involves large-scale historical processes that can be altered and harnessed only by medium-to-large international entities—such as coalitions of states embedded in regional security frameworks. International politics requires political, economic, legal, and even
Creating Cosmopolitan Power
181
military resources that are beyond the reach of facilitating small states and certainly beyond the reach of private individuals. Strategy for communication involves the creation of cosmopolitan power. This is not the neorealist power of the solitary international actor. But it is a power that has more in common with the traditional, realist understanding of mediating power than the facilitative reliance on the power to induce communication through successful social psychology. This type of power is made manifest when coalitions of large-scale international actors, mediated through international institutions, are created in pursuit of common goals. It is a form of power akin to what political philosophy calls “action in concert” (Arendt 1958). In addition, and unlike the facilitator, the critical mediator will not work through private backchannels. For the most part, the activities of the critical mediator will be open to public scrutiny. Because these activities involve highly visible international actors, they will be impossible to conceal. Thus, in some small measure, I attempt to offer a distinct set of answers to the practical questions of agency. First, I have detailed the types of actors who can be identified as critical mediators. Second, and in contrast to power political and facilitative approaches, I have defined a unique set of strategies. The critical mediator is a coalition of states embedded in a regional security framework that is committed to a world order based on cosmopolitan principles. In its attempt at conflict resolution, this actor would attempt to mobilize the forces committed to the creation of democratic public law. The critical mediator is cosmopolitan power creating cosmopolitan power. I wish now to highlight some of the points already made and expand on the analysis by turning toward the question of the Oslo Accords and process and the role of the Norwegian small-state facilitation. This mini–case study should cast further light on how a critical approach to international mediation can make itself a reality. Future progress in this dispute will require critical, or cosmopolitan, mediation.
The Radical Intimacy of the Hearth: Norway in the Middle East The normative argument for the Oslo Accords rests quite clearly on the case that the accords embodied mutual recognition. For a start, the accords contained letters of mutual recognition that were designed to underpin the legitimacy of the substantive agreements. In his letter to Yitzhak Rabin, Chairman Yasir Arafat, on behalf of the PLO, agrees to “recognize the right of the State of Israel to exist in peace and security.” Rabin, in his letter to Arafat, states, “The Government of the State of Israel had decided to recognise the PLO as the representative of the Palestinian people.” Many of
182
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
those who supported the accords in 1993 fastened onto this issue of mutual recognition. They argued that although the accords had many flaws and although many stumbling blocks would arise, mutual recognition had changed the basic dynamic of the conflict. Efraim Karsh, for example, echoes the arguments about symbolism and mutual recognition: The Declaration of Principles . . . signed on the White House Lawn on 13 September 1993, was a watershed in the one-hundred-year war between Arabs and Jews. After a century of denial and rejection, of bloodletting and bereavement, Arabs and Jews have finally agreed to bury the hatchet and settle for peace, based on mutual recognition and acceptance. (Karsh 1994: 1)
When we apply the normative standards of critical mediation agency as previously detailed, however, the arguments about mutual recognition do not seem so secure. The twin issues of statehood and security dominated the Oslo process. The Palestinian delegation hoped, eventually, to create a Palestinian state. The Israeli delegation looked to ensure the security of an Israel expanded, to a greater or lesser degree, into the territory captured during the 1967 war. The final version of the Declaration of Principles (DoP), which was completed in August 1993 after months of negotiation, reflected the central dynamic of Oslo—a dynamic that placed the core Israeli demands for security in a partially expanded state at the center of the process while marginalizing the Palestinian national demands. Consider, for example, Article IX and Article VII(5) of the agreed minutes to the Declaration of Principles. Article IX states that “both sides will review jointly laws and military orders presently in force in remaining spheres”—the remaining spheres being defined as those that are not the responsibility of the Palestinian Council. Thus in the West Bank and Gaza as a whole (1) Israeli military law would remain in place after Oslo and (2) the remaining spheres are subject only to the review of the various joint committees charged with implementing the agreement. This may seem like an interim or compromise position. However, lest there be any misunderstanding about the future dynamic, any eventual undertaking or obligation to withdraw militarily is negated by Article VII(5) of the agreed minutes. This article states, “The withdrawal of the military government will not prevent Israel from exercising the power and responsibilities not transferred to the [Palestinian] Council.” The Palestinian Council now has authority over direct taxation, tourism, and other social matters. Thus military and security policy in the West Bank and Gaza as a whole remains subject to Israeli sovereignty. This much is made explicit in Shimon Peres’s account of the Oslo negotiations (Peres 1995: 392). Thus it is no accident that since 1993 Israel has retained effective control over the West Bank and Gaza. Five years after the 1993 Washington
Creating Cosmopolitan Power
183
ceremony, Zone A, 3 percent of the West Bank, was under complete Palestinian control. The Palestinian National Authority directed both security and civilian policy. Zone B, 24 percent of the West Bank, was under joint Israeli security and Palestinian civilian control. Zone C, 72 percent of the West Bank, was under complete Israeli control, as if the Oslo Accords had never happened. From the normative point of view it is arguable that they never did. By 1999, the Oslo process had effectively stalled. When we examine questions of agency, there are a number of reasons for the lack of critical normative standards in the Oslo project. One can highlight, for example, the fact that the DoP was negotiated before the letters of mutual recognition. Habermas might argue that this is a “performative contradiction.” The argument would be that one cannot discuss the nature of intersubjectivity in international relations before recognizing the other as a potential moral agent. It is also possible to highlight the lack of legal and negotiating skills in the Palestinian delegation. Abu Mazen, one of the principal Palestinian agents in Oslo, writes: “We did not review the texts with a legal consultant for fear of leaks. . . . I tried to make use of the remnants of the legal knowledge I had acquired while studying law at Damascus University, but I could not draw much comfort from them” (Mazen 1995: 162). Focus, however, on the causal role or power of the Norwegian facilitation. The Norwegian form of facilitation was perhaps the most significant contribution to the fact that Palestinian national demands were ignored in the Oslo process. The problems stem from the fact that Norwegian thirdparty agency exists inside “the radical intimacy of the hearth”—a phrase I use to describe the strange amalgamation of the domestic and the international that makes up the character of the Norwegian facilitation. Conducting negotiations with the Palestinians through the radical intimacy of the hearth is a rational strategy for Israel. Israeli leaders are not keen on the idea of a Palestinian state; they also wish to preserve the ethnic character of the Jewish state. These twin goals thus present a problem. Political relationships have to be established between Israeli and Palestinian leaders, given the proximity of the populations. However, these relationships cannot be international; as such they would imply the existence of a Palestinian state. Nor can they be domestic; such a footing would fatally compromise the idea of the Jewish state. The small-state Norwegian facilitation is the perfect solution to this dilemma. The Oslo process and accords are not part of Israeli domestic politics. But, existing in the radical intimacy of the hearth, they do not represent normal international politics. Norwegian facilitation is poised somewhere between the domestic and the international. It emphasizes the relationships of the hearth—warmth, intimacy, empathy, and friendship—yet it claims that these relations are appropriate in the international world. Norwegian government officials were
184
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
involved in the process; yet they intervened as private individuals. The Oslo process helps sustain the existential status of the Palestinians and it helps the Israelis negotiate with their adversaries without implying anything about their national status under international law. The Palestinians are maintained in their space between the domestic and the international by a peace process that also exists in this space. They are neither citizens of Palestine nor citizens of Israel. They exist in a political limbo. The understanding of facilitation proposed by officials in the Norwegian government at the time of Oslo reinforces this point. There exists a strange blurring of the domestic and the international in the mind of the facilitator. In public, the Norwegians were allowed to develop the stance of the sovereign power—one that, in appearance at least, is committed, principled, and substantial. When international politics actually becomes a reality, however, the Norwegian official stance evaporates into nothing in terms of facilitation. Thus Jan Egeland, deputy foreign minister at the time of Oslo, states: The whole trick was to keep it secret. As long as the parties knew that the world knew nothing about the Oslo channel, it was not that important what we would say in public, as long as they felt that we did not try to maneuver them into any kind of position. They were never really concerned with what I would say on the television, for example, as long as I didn’t try to push either side to meet the other. (interview by the author, August 1996)
Here the representative of the small state acts in a substantial manner where it doesn’t count and retreats in the only place where it does count. Reality exists in fantasy and fantasy in reality. Facilitation is the appearance of international politics without the reality or the obligations. Facilitative processes may have their strengths. But one of their most obvious weaknesses is that they can help perpetuate the condition of statelessness. It is hard to achieve national recognition in the radical intimacy of the hearth. The failures of Oslo could be remedied if future mediations in the conflict between Israel and Palestine are of a cosmopolitan character. A cosmopolitan power creating cosmopolitan power is the only recipe for long-term stability and justice. A cosmopolitan mediator is important for a number of reasons. First, because the cosmopolitan power is made up of states embedded in regional security organizations, it follows that any interaction that involves this power is a full-blooded form of international politics. Mediation involving cosmopolitan power implies that disputants are international actors; they are actors who command the attention of international organizations. This status is highly important in the case of the Israeli-
Creating Cosmopolitan Power
185
Palestinian dispute. As noted, it is hard to achieve international recognition in the radical intimacy of the hearth. Recognizing that the struggle for national self-determination lay through international recognition, the PLO had always sought a conflictresolution process based on an international conference. Faisal Husseini described the reasons for this position in 1991. We Palestinians, we the PLO, are strong when the game is governed by the rules. It is this same approach that leads us to demand an effective role for the UN and Europe, that makes us demand that the negotiations unfold under the twin banners of international legality and implementation of UN decisions. (Husseini 1991: 107)
A cosmopolitan mediation is also important, as any conflict resolution between Israel and Palestine needs to recognize that justice requires national rights for both parties in the dispute. A cosmopolitan mediation will strive to create a dialogic community that embodies the mutual recognition of validity claims. But the cosmopolitan mediator is important for strategic as well as moral reasons. Given the existence of radical political forces in the region that are opposed to mutual recognition, a third party is needed that can strengthen the forces of democracy and compromise. A conflictresolution process in this part of the world will continue to demand the attention of outside powers—to help shape the balance of power, to oversee implementation, to offer guarantees and financial and technical help. Given the costs involved in such an undertaking, the cosmopolitan mediator will need the resources of a number of states embedded within regional security frameworks. The shocks and upheavals that occur in this part of the world from time to time can be absorbed by international coalitions more easily than by isolated nation states. Thus the outside role cannot be left to the powerless facilitator. Nor can it be left to the remaining superpower (the United States). This is a power that continues to subsume regional dynamics under a wider geopolitical strategy. Instability at the regional level is the result. A cosmopolitan mediation needs the power of an international actor without the dangerous and potentially arbitrary unilateralism of the superpower. When mediating powers are coalitions of states, it is less likely that factional or sectional interests will prevail and dictate policy. Policy will have to reflect a plurality of interests. It is vitally important that the third party use all its power to impede the intransigent. This is another reason to be suspicious of the mediating superpower. The material support offered by the United States to the Likud government after 1996 is no way for a neutral mediator to behave if the forces of intransigence are eventually to be overcome. The creation of cosmopolitan power requires that only forces committed to the dialogic com-
186
The Practice and Praxis of Critical IR Theory
munity receive outside aid and that intransigent forces feel the material consequences of their unwillingness to compromise and engage in dialogue. Where might we find this cosmopolitan mediating power in the world in which we actually live? Future research in this area should perhaps concentrate on the potential role of the European Union (EU). The EU is unlikely to act against the wishes of the United States; nor, given Germany’s past, is it likely to put real pressure on Israel. However, there are signs that the EU is becoming frustrated by its exclusion from a political process that it funds to a greater degree than any other organization. And all the countries of the EU realize that they are affected by any instability on the EU’s borders. The question arises, Can European politicians afford to leave the peace process to the Americans? I think that the answer is no. Peace requires not just security but a measure of justice, and the history of U.S. mediation tends to suggest that Israeli demands for security in an expanded state are privileged over Palestinian claims for justice. Although the EU will not, in the immediate future, step into the role of the cosmopolitan mediator, it will have to develop a policy of some sort toward this part of the Middle East. Doing nothing is not really an option. And anything short of secure national rights for both parties is a recipe for further instability in the Middle East as a whole. A cosmopolitan approach to a possible third-party role is a necessity in this context. It is not a result of abstract academic theorizing. It has to be admitted that we are unlikely, in the short to medium term, to see such a power emerge. However, it is the role and purpose of critical thinking in international relations to examine the case for the emergence of such a power, its likely shape and nature, and the tactics and strategies it may employ. Philosophy works with the future. It judges the present in the light of the possible. But philosophy also works with the past. It is vitally important to remember that the international world has changed beyond recognition over time. If there is a source of hope for critical thinking in the theory of international relations, it is the thought that the sheer pressure of events will always create the unexpected. Life, whether chemical, biological, or political, exists in a state of flux. Equilibrium is inherently unstable. Although theory must always be rooted in the actual, it is not unrealistic to ask some pressing questions about the international institutions that define the politics of the present day.
Notes 1. Habermas creates a distinction between moral and ethical discourses. Of course, the distinction needs to be made with reference to particulars. Nevertheless,
Creating Cosmopolitan Power
187
the broad idea is that moral discourses pertain to a set of goods that no human being can reasonably live without, whereas ethical discourses pertain to the self-understanding of a particular community. Many political disputes are actually about whether an issue represents a generalizable interest and, therefore, ought to be open to a wider consensus. For example, the issue of Jerusalem is seen by opinion in Israel to be a matter for Israel to decide, whereas the Palestinians and the international community, at least in theory, claim that this issue requires consensus. The fact that people dispute a particular rendition of the principle does not, however, detract from the validity of the general distinction.
PART FOUR COMMENTARIES
12 “OUR SIDE”? CRITICAL THEORY AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Chris Brown Critical Theory—see, Frankfurt School —Oxford Companion to Philosophy (Honderich 1995) Contemporary critical theory in English-language international relations may best be understood as today’s manifestation of a long-standing democratic impulse in the academic study of international affairs. —Craig N. Murphy in this volume You ought to read Marx, he is the only completely scientific economist on our side. —William Morris to a friend and comrade (cited in Thompson 1977: 761)
As the other chapters in this volume make very clear, there is no general agreement as to the contribution that critical theory can make to the study of international relations (IR). None of the authors represented here can quite match the precision of the editor of the Oxford Companion—whose determination to restrict critical theory to a narrow meaning no doubt reflects accurately the predilections of a particular kind of analytical philosophy—but Andrew Linklater and Kenneth Baynes are certainly writing “in the shadow” of the Institute for Social Research in Frankfurt; and N. J. Rengger and Kimberly Hutchings are clearly influenced by the scholarly tradition that produced the Frankfurt School. In contrast, although even Craig Murphy himself would not wish to argue that all contemporary manifestations of the democratic impulse could be described as critical, his chapter, along with those of Robert Cox, Jeffrey Harrod, and Sandra Whitworth, is eclectic in its sources and influences. Mark Neufeld reviews three writers—Alexander Wendt, Justin Rosenberg, and Cynthia Weber— none of whom could be described as critical theorists in any narrow sense 191
192
Commentaries
of the term, which is a rather surprising choice in view of the Frankfurtian tone of his earlier work (Neufeld 1995). Faced with this diversity, one is tempted to think that critical IR theorists are best understood in terms of the kind of theory they are not doing rather than in terms of any common commitment. Thus, critical theorists are not engaged in the neoutilitarian, rational choice theory characteristic of contemporary (neo)realism and (neo)liberalism in international relations, and critical international political economists oppose the economic orthodoxy of the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and its intellectual progenitors. However, and again, this oppositional frame of mind is not, in and of itself, sufficient to delineate an approach. If critical theory is to influence international relations it will have to stand for something, not simply act as a catchall term to describe the disaffected. In trying to establish what the role of critical theory has been in twentieth-century social and political thought, and could be in twenty-first-century international relations theory, we may find it helpful to begin with an obiter dictum of a nineteenth-century socialist, internationalist, agitator, novelist, poet, and visual artist—the extract from the correspondence of William Morris that heads this chapter. Morris was a committed left agitator, well versed in the politics and economics of the socialist movement of his day; the terms he uses to recommend Marx to a comrade are revealing. Marx is a scientific economist who is on our side. “We” have a side; our side is the side of the people, the wretched of the earth, the dispossessed, the proletariat, the “workers by hand and brain.” The other side is that of the capitalists, autocrats, imperialists, and other oppressors. These two sides have histories stretching back in time to medieval peasants’ revolts— explored in Morris’s The Dream of John Ball—and beyond and will disappear only after the final revolution (see “News from Nowhere” in Morris 1986). We look to theorists who are on our side—students of international relations will recall Robert Cox’s injunction that “theory is always for someone and for some purpose” (Cox 1981: 128)—but we expect them to be scientists, indeed, “completely scientific.” This, according to Morris, is where Marx scores; he is a scientific economist who is on our side. Note well that we are not on his side; he is on ours. In the 1880s, the idea that our side might be defined as Marxist would have seemed absurd to Morris. Marx was exciting to Morris because he provided something that Morris recognized to be missing in much of his own work—an account of the “laws of motion” of capitalist society—not because he provided an allencompassing social doctrine, much less a normative theory of society (Brown 1992a). Unwittingly, in this aside Morris highlighted three of the central questions for radical thought and action in the twentieth century, questions that all branches of critical theory, widely or narrowly defined, have felt obliged
“Our Side”?
193
to address. What is the relationship of radicalism in general—our side—to the legacy of Karl Marx? How is our side affected by those movements in the philosophy of science in the twentieth century that have put in doubt the possibility of a “completely scientific” social theory? And most fundamentally, can we still think of our side as possessing a kind of unity, or are there now many sides, many axes of oppression and resistance? The rest of this chapter explores these three questions and their relationship to the possibility of a critical international relations theory.
Our Side and the Contested Legacy of Marx and Engels In the 1880s Morris could, unselfconsciously, think of Marx simply as a figure on our side, but for much of the twentieth century things were not like that. The relatively loose and eclectic Socialist International, which held together British Fabians and Labourites, German Social Democrats, Russian Bolsheviks, and French Socialists without attempting to impose ideological uniformity, collapsed in 1914 with the outbreak of World War I (Kolakowski 1978). Prior to 1914, most of the members of the Second International thought about economic affairs in broadly Marxian terms (perhaps filtered through the work of German-speaking, Marx-inspired economists such as Rudolf Hilferding and Rosa Luxemburg or adapted by British radical liberals such as John Hobson or Henry Brailsford) but adopted political strategies appropriate to their particular circumstances (parliamentary here, revolutionary there) and moral philosophies according to their predilections—Christian nonconformist in Great Britain, neo-Kantian in much of Germany, Tolstoyan for many Russians (but not, of course, Lenin’s Bolsheviks). After the Great War everything had changed. The general radicalization brought on by the collapse of European liberalism in 1914 promoted extremism of the right and left, and the victory of the Bolsheviks in Russia (and, perhaps more significant, the failure of socialist revolutions elsewhere) brought to prominence the most intolerant, authoritarian strain of Marxism then available. When Marxist-Leninism became Stalinism and dialectical materialism (“dia-mat”) became an official ideology with answers to all questions, from political strategy to art (socialist realism) and science (Lysenkoism), the legacy of Marx became a killing matter and not simply an issue for intellectual discussion. By the late 1920s the old socialism movement was bitterly divided between, on the one side, an increasingly totalitarian, Soviet-run Communist International issuing edicts in the name of scientific socialism and, on the other, a loose alliance of social democratic and labor parties committed to reformism and the ballot
194
Commentaries
box and increasingly skeptical of Marxian economic theory. The 1930s saw a new softer communist strategy in the face of fascism—social democrats moved from being “social fascists” to potential partners in a Popular Front—but, if anything, the two wings moved further apart. Franklin Roosevelt’s New Deal in the United States and the emergence of Keynesian economic theory (owing more to radicals such as Hobson than to Marx) seemed to offer a third way between communism and capitalism. It is in this context that critical theory in its original, Oxford Companion to Philosophy sense emerges. The founders of the Institute for Social Research in Frankfurt were consciously attempting to preserve, extend, and deepen a tradition of nondogmatic Marxian thought. In an attempt to counteract the simplicities of Soviet-style scientific socialism, they developed the Hegelian roots of Marx’s thought. Unwilling to become Stalinists but alienated from the increasingly reformist German Social Democratic Party, they turned away from politics and economics and toward philosophy and culture—a step Perry Anderson sees as characteristic of Western Marxism (Anderson 1979). At the heart of their enterprise remained the project of emancipation—the Enlightenment commitment to freedom, the belief that social thought and political action ought to be oriented toward liberation—even though the unfolding disasters of the 1930s and the flight of the Institute for Social Research to the United States induced a culture of pessimism that ultimately resulted in Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer’s Dialectic of Enlightenment (1944/1979), in which the Enlightenment project is put into question and found wanting. What is less clear about the Frankfurt School is not its commitment to but rather its account of the agency of emancipation. A good part of the school’s deviation from Marxism lay in its skepticism about the positive role of the proletariat—there were too many working-class Nazis in Germany in the early 1930s for illusions on this score—but if not the proletariat, who, or what? Arguably the founders of the Frankfurt School were too close to Marx to provide an answer to this question. Eventually it is the successors of the founders who provide a kind of answer to the problem of agency, at the expense of greater distance from Marx. Herbert Marcuse, from the older generation, rather implausibly invested the lumpenproletariat and déclassé students with the historic role of the working class (Marcuse 1972b), whereas writers such as Habermas, and later still Axel Honneth, look elsewhere altogether than class and productive relations for the driving force behind social change. Insights derived from developmental psychology, discourse ethics, and a neoHegelian “struggle for recognition” provide a moving force in human relations, a role that class conflict no longer can perform (Habermas 1990a; Honneth 1995b). Ultimately, the heirs of the Frankfurt School and critical theory in this restricted sense leave Marx well behind; he becomes one
“Our Side”?
195
influence among many, perhaps less significant than Kant, albeit more significant than anyone else. How does this shift work with critical theories of international relations? Here we see one of the many divides in the field. Critical theorists such as Linklater and David Held have, for the most part, followed the standard Frankfurt trajectory and left Marx some way behind them—their current concerns with cosmopolitan democracy and post-Westphalian political community have everything to do with late-Frankfurt themes such as inclusion and exclusion, recognition and moral development, but very little to do with traditional Marxian notions of class and production (Linklater 1998, Held 1995). Critical international political economists, in contrast, remain largely wedded to Marxian categories, albeit updated where appropriate. The title of Robert Cox’s major work, Production, Power and World Order: Social Forces in the Shaping of History (1987), tells its own story without calling on that author’s not-altogether-serious description of himself as “your friendly neighbourhood Marxist-Leninist subversive” (Cox 1986: 249). Cox’s seminal 1981 article, cited previously, although one of the foundation documents of critical IR theory, does not draw on the Frankfurt School, and its inspiration is clearly classical Marxism with Antonio Gramsci rather than the Institute for Social Research as the main interwar reference point. This affiliation is at the programmatic level, but much of the actual political economy of this branch of critical international relations theory is Marxist-Leninist in inspiration rather than Marxist as such, filtered through the “dependency” school of center-periphery analysis, which was in turn heavily influenced by the U.S. Marxist Paul Baran (Baran 1957). Bill Warren, a more orthodox Marxist, traces this link in his Imperialism: Pioneer of Capitalism (1980), in which he relates 1960s and 1970s writings on the development of underdevelopment to Lenin’s declaration of 1917 that capitalism had reached its highest stage and was now a degenerate social form. This point cannot be pressed too far; as the chapters by Cox, Harrod, and Murphy in this volume make clear, there is more to critical international political economy than the point would suggest, but the basic thrust behind this work is clearly more in line with the Marxist tradition than is the case with critical IR theory as such. The position of writers such as Cox and Harrod appears to be based on the argument that it is possible to employ a great deal of Marxist (Leninist) economic thought without accepting responsibility for Marxist (Leninist) political practice; one can, as it were, unpackage Marxism and pull out the good bits (the account of the laws of motion of capitalist economies) while leaving the bad, totalitarian, bits behind. Whether this is in general a viable strategy is contestable—especially in the light of the doubts about a politics largely based on production, which will feature in the following discussion
196
Commentaries
of “our side”—but it has become particularly difficult to follow in the context of the collapse of the Soviet Union and the people’s democracies in 1989–1991. Although these societies clearly suffered a political crisis— partly induced by pressures from outside—they also fell because the root idea upon which they were constructed, that it is possible to plan an economy by reference to need rather than purchasing power and without employing the mechanism of the market, proved false. As Alec Nove demonstrated before the fall, a feasible socialism cannot be constructed on the basis of a fully planned economy (Nove 1983). Moreover, the idea of a world in which scarcity has been abolished seems even less credible in an era of environmental consciousness than it did a generation or two ago, when the leaders of the Soviet Union committed that country to the hubristic schemes for physical transformation, the debris of which their successors are still struggling to cope with. In short, whereas it might once have made sense to think that Marxian economics are part of the solution to the world’s ills, it now seems clear that they are no more than another way of posing the problem of industrialism. As with Frankfurt School thought on agency, however, it is by no means clear what the implications of this point are, that is, what a nonMarxist critical international political economy might look like. An understandable desire to resist the human suffering caused by too rigid an application of neoliberal economic remedies by institutions such as the IMF obviously constitutes part of the new problematic but is no substitute for a positive take on the world economy. What a plausible positive economic policy for our side might look like today is by no means clear if the aim is to distinguish an explicitly critical theory of the world economy from the work of radicals such as Will Hutton or Paul Hirst (Hutton 1995; Hirst and Thompson 1996). The problem is deepened by the difficulties with the notion that “we” have a side anymore. This issue will be discussed further on, but first some thoughts on the nature of science need to be aired.
What Does It Mean to Be “Completely Scientific” Today? Morris termed Marx the most completely scientific thinker on our side, and Marx would have agreed wholeheartedly. Although critical of the kind of bourgeois methods promoted by John Stuart Mill and committed to “the dialectic”—in which a reawakening of interest has recently been called for by Christian Heine and Benno Teschke in a debate in the pages of Millennium—and although employing some formulations that have been used by later constructivist scholars, Marx had no doubt about the scientific value of his work (Heine and Teschke 1996; Millennium 1997). He in fact
“Our Side”?
197
sent a copy of Volume 1 of Das Kapital to Charles Darwin, explicitly equating their respective achievements. Moreover, along with most progressives of the age, he believed that scientific truth necessarily promoted his cause. If, as Kant suggested, Enlightenment meant humanity’s emergence from its self-incurred immaturity, then science had a major role to play in this emergence. The (scientific) truth would set us free. It is interesting to note a similar faith expressed by those indefatigable social researchers, the Fabians Sidney and Beatrice Webb. When presented with a legacy earmarked for the promotion of socialism, they used the money to found the London School of Economics without stipulating that the research conducted at that institution be explicitly socialist; their faith was that high-quality social research would necessarily promote the cause of socialism irrespective of the intentions or predilections of the researcher. On the darker side, a similar faith in the value of scientific truth underlay the Eurocentrism of virtually all varieties of progressive thought in the nineteenth century, famously expressed in Marx’s contemptuous dismissal of the “rural idiocy” of village life in India, where the natives worshipped monkeys and cows rather than dedicating themselves to self-emancipation (Marx 1973). Some echoes of these ideas can still be found at the beginning of the twenty-first century, but in general the experiences of our time have not been kind to these habits of thought. We are only too aware that the products of science can kill as well as preserve life. It is not necessary to be a Green to see that environmental degradation is a by-product of a mind-set that sees nature simply as a resource to be used by humans for their own purposes; the faith that scientific progress will always work with the grain of the interests of humanity is hard to sustain on the record of the twentieth century. However, a more fundamental challenge to progressive thought is posed by shifts in our understanding of the nature of scientific truth. A characteristic feature of most versions of the philosophy of science and scientific methodology in the twentieth century was a move away from “foundational” thinking (Brown 1994a). Conventional accounts of scientific method nowadays stress the provisional nature of scientific truth—now to be equated with unrefuted hypotheses—and the extent to which the observer is required to decide what the implications of an experiment are, this decision being underdetermined by evidence (Chalmers 1982). More radical accounts stress the interconnections of truth and power and our inability to think without frames of reference that cannot, themselves, directly be put to the test (Bernstein 1979). These shifts in thinking have obvious implications for the relationship between the natural and the social sciences—in particular for the notion that these discourses (a favored term today, reflecting current understanding of the importance of language) share a common methodology, common goals (the production of causal
198
Commentaries
explanations), and a common commitment to value-free research, a notion conveniently (perhaps sometimes too facilely) summarized as positivism. One feature common to all varieties of critical theory in general, and critical international relations theory in particular, is their hostility to positivism—although it should be noted that not all critics of positivism are critical theorists.1 In the 1930s one of the founding texts of the Frankfurt School was Horkheimer’s “Traditional and Critical Theory,” in which he argues forcefully that social research cannot be based on the notion of a value-free science and an instrumental conception of reason (“our side,” yet again, is crucial), and part of the Frankfurt School’s critique of Soviet Marxism was based on the facile scientism of that doctrine—and its technophilia, perfectly caught in Lenin’s equation: “communism = socialism + electrification” (Horkheimer 1972). However, since these early days, critical theory’s response to antifoundationalist thought has taken a number of different directions, and here again, we can see the many, often contradictory, varieties of critical international relations theory clearly displayed. Modern Frankfurt School writers, in particular Habermas, and international relations theorists who draw inspiration from this direction—in particular Linklater and Mark Neufeld—have been troubled by what they take to be the potentially conservative implications of a radical antifoundationalism and have sought to reestablish criteria of truth, most prominently via Habermas’s account of discourse ethics and communicative action (Habermas 1984, 1989a). Modern epistemology has undermined the idea of truth as correspondence to reality; truth as consensus endorses local standards and is, on the face of it, essentially conservative, but to surrender the notion of truth altogether is, on this account, to open the way to irrationalism. Instead the answer is to establish truth by consensus, but a consensus achieved via dialogue under circumstances in which considerations irrelevant to truth are excluded, in which the force of the better argument can come through. A central issue here—for Habermas but also, perhaps especially, for his followers in critical international relations theory—is the nature of this dialogue and whether any particular voices are heard louder than others. Clearly voices cannot be excluded arbitrarily, and it would be wrong to suggest that either Habermas or his followers employ Eurocentric or gender-based criteria to restrict the voices that can be heard. The more compelling criticism is that although these and other dissenting voices are heard, the cost is that dissenters are obliged to speak in a particular kind of way, using, as it were, “received pronunciation” rather than the dialects they employ in everyday life. As Linklater’s chapter in this volume makes clear, the key question is the extent to which the requirement of dialogue is compatible with the maintenance of difference. Adherents of other varieties of critical theory—variously termed both by themselves and by critics as late modernist, poststructuralist, or post-
“Our Side”?
199
modernist—criticize the project of trying to reestablish truth with a capital T, seeing no need to provide their truth claims with transcendental backing. These authors—largely missing from this volume but criticized occasionally herein—regard the search for new foundations for truth as, at best, ill conceived, at worst as part of the process of normalization, or overcoming difference, already too prevalent in our society. Living without truth may involve becoming entangled with the paradoxes of relativism, but as William Connolly puts it, “the postmodernist thinks within the code of paradox because only attentiveness to paradox can loosen the hold monotonic standards of identity have over life in the late modern age” (Connolly 1988: 339). Writers such as James Der Derian, David Campbell, Michael Shapiro, and Christine Sylvester have made major contributions to contemporary (critical?) international relations theory while working within this code of paradox (Der Derian 1992; Campbell 1992; Sylvester 1994; Shapiro 1997). The gap between this kind of critical theory and the critical theory of the Frankfurt School and its followers is very wide; indeed, much of Habermas’s later theoretical work has been directed toward attacking postmodernism and poststructuralism, the (mainly French) “young conservatives,” as he has been wont to refer to them (Habermas 1987). This may be a case of Freud’s “narcissism of small differences” in action, especially since the Frankfurt School and the Left Bank have in common the fact that they take the problems of truth seriously, in a way that some “critical” theorists who have stayed closest to old-style Marxism clearly do not. Jeffrey Harrod’s use of the metaphor of unmasking in his chapter in this volume is revealing here: The notion that it is possible for the social theorist to reach down to the reality that lies under the mask is precisely what is put in question by critical theorists of a postmodern or even, perhaps, a Frankfurt School orientation. There is, of course, something quite attractive about the idea of putting aside these problems and concentrating on “real people” and “real places,” as another critical theorist somewhat impatient of epistemology has put it (Booth 1991b). The difficulty with this strategy is that problems with truth, dialogue, and difference soon spill over from matters of epistemology into matters of substance, and that is the case on this occasion. The issue of difference raises the most basic question of all—whether we still have, or have ever had, a “side” at all.
Two Sides, Many Sides? Critical International Theory—A Case for Closure The writings of Morris and Marx show that both were very well aware of the complexity of the class structure of their world—not simply those complexities generated by intermediate classes such as the petite bourgeoisie
200
Commentaries
but also those complexities that were the product of the existence within capitalist social formations of precapitalist strata (Marx 1968a). Nonetheless, a certain Manichaeanism pervades their work. Things are moving in the direction of a world in which our side will directly confront their side; in the name of science Marx tries to avoid portraying this confrontation as one between good and evil, but that thought is rarely far from the surface of his work. A world penultimately composed of two sides seems the only logical result of the theory of history espoused by Marx. The notion that human development takes the form of successive modes of production (“stages”)—ancient slavery, medieval feudalism, modern capitalism, a socialist-communist future—is central to historical materialism, and this idea explains why Marx could be so dismissive of societies that had not been part of this trajectory (Marx 1968b). “Asia” had been stagnant, outside this dynamic sequence of human development; it needed to be brought into world history by European imperialism—not, of course, that the imperialists understood that this was what they were doing. In the end, or rather just before the end, our side will consist of all the oppressed and dispossessed, all the downtrodden, the wretched of the earth, led by the proletariat, the industrial working class; their side will consist of all oppressors of every kind—a shrinking band led by capitalists—who will be swept away in the revolution, after which there will be no sides at all. Famously, Marx himself refused to be drawn in on the nature of postcapitalist society, but William Morris, in News from Nowhere, provides a compelling fictional picture (along with an account of how this utopia emerged that is Leninist avant la lettre). How did twentieth-century critical theory respond to this scenario? As already noted, the Frankfurt School in the 1920s, 1930s, and 1940s was understandably skeptical about the emancipatory role of the working class. The workers were too readily seduced by Nazi or, for that matter, Stalinist propaganda. Moreover, the cultural resources available for the development of an emancipatory working class had dried up. Here is the real dialectic of enlightenment: The very material forces that Marx had seen as the basis for a future emancipation lay behind this cultural desert. Under the influence of capitalism and the uneducated taste of the bourgeoisie, culture divides into a high culture that is increasingly inaccessible and avant-garde and a low culture of diminishing worth whose greatest achievement today is the advertising jingle.2 The Frankfurt School did not, however, abandon the idea of a unidirectional linear history; indeed, its pessimism was precisely based on the view that this history, the only one available, was turning out badly. And whatever might be said about the difference between critical and traditional theory, it remained the case that the scientific knowledge developed in the West was qualitatively superior to that produced else-
“Our Side”?
201
where and that, as Habermas and his followers still insist, Western rationality is central to the prospects for emancipation. Habermas and his IR followers no longer think in terms of revolution as the precondition for emancipation, and as noted previously, their dialogic commitment extends to all comers of all genders, continents, and cultures. It remains moot whether this strategy is as open as it seems. It is certainly the case that whereas in the nineteenth century the Enlightenment project of emancipation seemed dominated by, if not officially limited to, white males, today different genders and races are incorporated; neither sexism nor racism can play any part in determining who is on our side, and multiculturalism on the left attempts to make our side as open as possible to the contributions of other cultures. However, a basic problem remains: Our side in the Marx-Morris sense was based on the notion that all forms of oppression could ultimately be contextualized and organized by the relationship of individuals to property—the ownership of the means of production in Marx’s terms, wealth more generally for Morris. It is this context that lies behind Marx’s metanarrative and that still informs the more Marxinfluenced of contemporary critical theorists. But is it really the case that this metanarrative still stands? Postmodern politics suggests not; indeed, one might note, not altogether frivolously, that Britain’s New Labor Party, the most successful of postmodern political groupings, is explicitly dedicated to the notion that there is a third way between our side and their side (Giddens 1998). This notion is in the context of politics in a postindustrial society, but there is a less frivolous, much wider point to be made here. Our current world order produces many losers as well as a few winners, but it is by no means clear that all the losers are on the same side, part of some global rainbow coalition in which the newly industrialized workers of the “South” join hands with the displaced industrial workers of the “North,” oppressed women in northern India make common cause with demonized radical Islam, Hindu nationalists develop affinities with gays in Zimbabwe or inner-city African Americans, and so on. On the face of it, emancipation for some of these subordinate groups may involve the continued oppression of others; in any event the simplicities of the world of William Morris and Karl Marx seem gone forever. Here lies the most significant divide in critical international relations theory. Those critical theorists closest to the Frankfurt School and, a fortiori, those closest to Marx, Lenin, and Gramsci hold to the faith that ultimately there is only one side for us—that through dialogue difference can be preserved and exclusion ended or, in the latter case, that, contrary to appearance, differences in gender, race, and culture in the last resort are significant only because of politico-economic structures. Other critical theorists—postmodernists and their ilk—further from Marx and skeptical of
202
Commentaries
the capacity of dialogue to establish truth reject this project, looking instead to celebrate difference and develop social theory and political practice on the basis of cultural diversity. Does it make sense to think of these two bodies of thought as part of the same broad critical movement? Rather, it seems better to accept that there are divisions here that cannot be papered over. This chapter began with the Oxford Companion starkly equating critical theory with the Frankfurt School. If we bear in mind that there are no ideological tests for admission to the Frankfurt School and no definitive Frankfurt School positions, only a Frankfurt School perspective, perhaps it would be best to abandon extreme eclecticism and admit that this is, indeed, the most helpful, least confusing, way to think of critical theory.
Notes This overview of the debate on critical theory and IR is based loosely on my contribution to the proceedings of the conference held at the University of Wales, Aberystwyth, in 1996, which was the starting point for this volume. I have also had the opportunity to review most of the other chapters in this volume in draft form. I am grateful to all the contributors and participants in the discussions at that most productive and convivial weekend, and in particular to Richard Wyn Jones, who has had the unenviable task of shaping the proceedings into book form. 1. This may be a convenient point at which to clarify the relationship between critical IR theory and constructivist IR theory. Briefly, constructivism and critical theory share an opposition to positivism, but the radical impulse associated with critical theory is not necessarily to be found in the writings of constructivists. Thus, for example, Friedrich Kratochwil has employed the Wittgensteinian notion of a constitutive rule in ways that are clearly and necessarily antipositivist but that endorse many of the existing rules of international society (Kratochwil 1989, 1995). Similarly, Alexander Wendt’s employment of structuration theory is antipositivist, but his work remains essentially within a state-centric framework (Wendt 1987, 1992). It should be noted that the structuration theory favored by Wendt is wholly incompatible with the Wittgensteinian distinction between constitutive and regulative rules, on which Kratochwil’s work is based. That two of the most important figures in constructivism differ at such a fundamental level casts severe doubt on the coherence of the school; perhaps the best way to understand constructivism is as yet one more oppositional tendency within the U.S. academy, a banding together of scholars who have little in common other than their opposition to the prevailing positivist orthodoxy in U.S. international relations—though, as previously suggested, much the same might be said of critical IR theory. 2. Adorno traces this process in terms of the history of music, arguing that “after The Magic Flute [1791] it was never again possible to force serious and light music together” and that thereafter, bourgeois philistinism took over (Adorno 1938/1982). Roger Scruton has recently commented on the absurdity of this claim (Scruton 1997: 468–474). Apart from the obvious fact that the bourgeoisie has been the main patron of “serious” (including atonal and avant-garde) music for the past two centuries and that many nineteenth-century composers wrote tunes that were whistled in the streets by ordinary folk as well as listened to at La Scala and Covent
“Our Side”?
203
Garden, there has rarely been so rich and varied a combination of serious and light music as in the United States of the 1930s and 1940s, when Adorno wrote his jeremiads. From Louis Armstrong and Duke Ellington to George Gershwin, Cole Porter, and a host of lesser talents, this was a time of extraordinary creativity, and Adorno’s inability to recognize this richness can only be attributed to a sad snobbishness or the closure of a mind at the end of its tether.
13 WHAT IS INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS FOR? NOTES TOWARD A POSTCRITICAL VIEW Alexander Wendt
A book on critical theory and international relations is at once also a book on positivism and international relations, since it is in relation to positivism that critical theory is constituted. Whereas positivism generally affirms the possibility of separating fact and value, distinguishing subject and object, and achieving objective knowledge about the world, critical theories1 generally deny these separations, stressing the entanglement of facts and values, the breakdown of subject-object distinctions, and the relativity of all knowledge claims to someone or some purpose. Positivism is the other to critical theory’s self. Many of the differences in this binary stem from different answers to perhaps the first question of any discipline of international relations, namely, What is IR for? If we had to pick one description of what positivists are after, it might be policy relevance. IR should try to explain how the international system works so that policymakers can use that knowledge to preserve the aspects of it we like and change those we don’t. Robert Cox has famously called this a problem-solving approach to social science, in which the goal is to solve problems within, and thus reproduce, the existing order (Cox 1981). In contrast, perhaps the most common answer that critical theorists give to the question is emancipation. IR should try to uncover the deep structures that make the existing order possible and identify alternatives to those structures so that we can liberate ourselves from their oppressions. Moreover, since the existing order is defended by policymakers, critical theory is aimed primarily at policytakers, especially in civil society, and thus reflects a democratic impulse in scholarship compared to positivism’s perhaps more technocratic one (see Murphy, Ch. 4, this volume). As a result of these different political agendas, social scientific knowledge 205
206
Commentaries
is thought to require different forms: lawlike generalizations about past behavior for positivists, reflexive understandings of deep structure for critical theorists. There is much to recommend this framing of the positivist-critical debate, but the distinction between problem solving and emancipatory theory can also get quite blurry, since both are ultimately about making the world a better place. Few positivists in IR are committed to reproducing the existing international order for its own sake. A vocal minority—realists— have a principled belief that it is impossible to transform the character of anarchic systems and that trying to do so can therefore be dangerous. But a majority—including both liberal cosmopolitans and rational choice institutionalists—are committed to reform of the international system. To be sure, reform implies preservation of at least some features of the status quo and to that extent can be discounted as problem solving within the existing order. But that interpretation doesn’t do justice to the depth of reform sought by many positivists—protection of human rights, abolition of war, collective security, global distributive justice, environmental cooperation, an international rule of law, and so on. It also neglects the fact that most critical theorists themselves would preserve features of the existing order; few are advocating permanent revolution. The problem here is that problem solving and emancipation are inherently relative to questions of who and what. A practice or theory could count as problem solving by one standard and emancipatory by another. The recent effort to abolish antipersonnel land mines is a good example: In most respects this enterprise takes the deep structure of international politics as given, but for the individuals whose lives are saved, who’s to say that it is not emancipatory? The positivist-critical binary seems to make it difficult to be both policy relevant and emancipatory at the same time. One way to begin thinking about transcending the positivist-critical binary is to see it as a problem of time horizons. Positivists tend to operate with a relatively short time horizon. Policy relevance means relevant today with a view toward next month or at most next year. Given such a time frame, major structural change of the system cannot realistically be on the agenda, although significant emancipatory efforts might be made on a local or microbasis. Critical theorists tend to operate with a longer time horizon, envisioning changes over years or even decades. Given that horizon, major structural transformation is a real option. Where both sides fail, however—and this failure is the reason they tend to talk past each other—is in linking the two time frames. The positivist emphasis on predictive power as a measure of theoretical success might seem to offer a natural bridge between short- and long-range thinking, but in social scientific practice prediction has usually meant retrodiction, and generalizations about the past are not a very reliable guide to the
What Is International Relations For?
207
future in a complex, uncertain world. And indeed, few positivists make forecasting an important part of their work (for an interesting exception, see Bueno de Mesquita, Newman, and Rabushka 1996). Critical theorists tend to neglect the short run. Despite getting equal billing from Andrew Linklater with normative and sociological inquiries, praxeology, in effect the science of linking ends to means, is probably the least developed of critical theory’s three agendas (Linklater, Ch. 2 in this volume). The result of both tendencies is that as an intellectual community, we in IR are not very good at thinking about how the world community can act today to realize its interests over the long term. The problem of long-range choice and satisfaction is not an easy one, either practically or conceptually, in part because it involves uniquely difficult, essentially epistemological, issues of knowledge and rationality: If the present is complex and the future radically uncertain, then it is not clear what rationality even means, let alone what rational choices should be. For different reasons traditional positivist and critical views of social science are not well equipped to address these problems, which may help explain their neglect. Nor do I have any solutions here. What follows is only a very preliminary, and quite speculative, survey of issues. But it does advance a conception of what IR should be, for that approach at least speaks to the problem. The overall aim of this conception is a science (broadly defined) for purposive control over the constitutional evolution of the world system. A presumption of such an inquiry is that the world system today is in fact evolving a constitutional order, perhaps in a manner analogous to the way that Britain evolved a constitution. Realists might doubt this presumption, foreseeing only a continued war of all against all, and they may prove right. But the range and depth of institution building in contemporary world politics—the UN, European Union (EU), World Trade Organization (WTO), North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO), and so on—combined with U.S. preponderance for the foreseeable future, are such that the possibility of global constitutionalism should at least be considered as a premise. And if we’re going to evolve a constitutional order anyway, it makes sense to think scientifically (again, broadly defined) about how we might direct that process. Recent scholarship on global governance and European constitutionalism has begun to do this (see Rosenau and Czempiel 1992; Falk, Johansen, and Kim 1993; Young 1994; Onuf 1997; Ikenberry 1998; Weiler 1997). IR nevertheless largely lacks such a science today. As long as that remains the case, IR will have little to offer policymakers, or -takers, in the way of useful strategies for institutional reform, and whatever befalls the system in the long run will happen to it (and us), rather than be what we sought to bring about. Evolutionary control is ultimately about collective self-control in the face of the future.
208
Commentaries
There are various ways to think about the kind of control sought in such a project: constitutional “design,” social “engineering,” evolutionary “guidance,” system “steering,” collective “character planning,” and so on (see, respectively, Goodin 1996, Turner 1998, Banathy 1998, Luhmann 1997, Elster 1983). These metaphors have different inflections and requirements that might be interesting to compare. But here I address only one, steering, and use it to illustrate the larger problematic. The spirit of my inquiry is postcritical, by which I mean a view of what social science is, for that view combines emancipation, which can occur only by deep transformation of the existing order over the long run, with the positivist willingness to think scientifically about that task. In a sense this combination of science and emancipation is what critical theory, in the early Frankfurt School, was originally all about, and to that extent the argument of this chapter is very much in a traditional critical vein. However, among critical theorists today, those with postmodernist sensibilities tend to reject the idea of science altogether, and even most of those who are opposed to postmodernism (such as Marxists) tend to shy away from the science part of the equation because of its association with positivism. Given the antipositivist, antiscience connotations of contemporary critical theory, therefore, adding post to critical seems necessary to capture my meaning, even if that means merely getting back to square one. Thus this chapter echoes some of the themes expressed in Nicholas Rengger’s and Andrew Linklater’s contributions to the volume, and indeed it might be seen as taking off from Linklater’s suggestive remarks about praxeology. In the next section I define what I mean by steering and locate it in the context of two views of where social order comes from. I then discuss three questions that a science of steering raises—Who’s driving? Where should we go? How do we get there?—and show how these questions create difficulties for traditional positivist and critical conceptions of social science. I conclude with some thoughts about what a science of steering would need to look like.
The Idea of Steering Evolutionary steering can be seen as a way of navigating between two views of where social order comes from—in Friedrich Hayek’s terms, “spontaneous” and “constructed” order (Hayek 1973).2 The issue at stake between these views is the extent to which the outcomes of social evolution can be or are intended. Since this issue concerns the ability of human agents to deliberately create and control the structures in which they are embedded, it involves something of an agent-structure problem, although one different from that in my earlier discussions (Wendt 1987; see also
What Is International Relations For?
209
Pettit 1993). Here the question is the degree of freedom and voluntarism versus structural determinism in the historical process; there it was whether agents or structures can be reduced to each other. The spontaneous-order tradition holds that social orders are an unintended consequence of various actions. Order emerges spontaneously from the complex concatenation of human activities, structured by preexisting institutions but over time unwittingly transforming those institutions as well. The reasoning here is evolutionary, depicting a process that operates behind the backs of actors, and indeed one of the principal mechanisms by which it is thought to work is through the selection of certain practices and institutions over others (on Hayek’s theory of cultural selection, see Vanberg 1986 and Hodgson 1991a; cf. Adler 1991). Practices and institutions that meet the needs of agents tend to survive, whereas those that do not are selected out. Competition is therefore a good thing, since as a discovery procedure it helps societies determine what works and what doesn’t. We can think of this argument as putting structure before agency, determinism before voluntarism, since it locates the ultimate mechanism of historical change in the logic of social structures rather than in the foresight of purposeful agents. To that extent it reflects a welcome humility about the human condition. However, despite its focus on structure, it would be a mistake to interpret this view as saying that agents are irrelevant (which would be odd for the libertarian Hayekians), for two reasons. One is that social structures have the effects they do only because of the activities that instantiate them. Human behavior is necessary to “carry” all social structures, and so even the most structurally determined outcomes happen only because of what people do. But creating outcomes unintentionally is different from doing so intentionally; thus it might be useful to call the former “action” and the latter “agency,” or something like that. The other way in which agents matter is that human beings are purposeful creatures who in their daily lives are constantly intervening in history, trying to bend bigger or smaller parts of it to their will. And often they succeed: On the local level, over the short term, many outcomes are intended. Thus the point being made by spontaneous-order theorists must be that it is only on the more macroscopic level, over the longer term, that deliberate control is not really possible. A constructed order, then, is one in which institutional and perhaps distributive outcomes are deliberately chosen by some agency.3 The parameters of social order are intended rather than unintended; freedom rather than determinism drives evolution; agency rather than structure is what counts. There are relatively few successful pure constructed orders historically, domestic or international, but there are some. The U.S. Constitution is perhaps the most brilliant example, and Western academics and policymakers are now busily trying to replicate its success with constitutional engineer-
210
Commentaries
ing in Eastern Europe and elsewhere. Successful constructed orders are harder to find in international politics, but the European Union and perhaps the UN are plausible candidates. The idea that social order can be subjected to purposive choice reflects an Enlightenment faith in human reason and will quite at odds with the spontaneous-order tradition. Yet looking at modern societies, which are incredibly complex systems that on balance function remarkably well, one is tempted to ask, How could such systems not be the product of design? Could they have arisen all by themselves, just by accident? However, just as the beauties of nature do not necessarily reveal the workings of a god, the theory of spontaneous order shows that often what seem to be the products of design are actually the products of an invisible hand, whether of a market, anarchy, balance of power, or whatever (Ullmann-Margalit 1978). Once the false positives of designs by unintended consequences are taken out, it seems clear that most long-term developments in social evolution fit the spontaneous- better than the constructed-order model. This is probably particularly true in international relations, where there is no single designer. In domestic politics there is usually a centralized, corporate actor (the state) that can guide the evolution of society. But the anarchy of the international system is defined as such by the absence of a unified agent, by a proliferation of agents who are often in conflict. Individual great powers may sometimes achieve hegemony, but historically their ability to institutionalize international orders has been limited and transitory. In an anarchy it is unclear how a constructed order could ever get off the ground. Advocates of spontaneous order might add that this is just as well, since the record of constructed orders in domestic life has been often one of spectacular failure and totalitarianism. Communism, fascism, and perhaps now the welfare state are all failed attempts to direct social evolution and were hugely costly in human and material terms. Insofar as it contributed to the outbreak of World War II, the League of Nations, one of the few multilateral efforts to design an international order, fared little better (for a good critique of what amounts to constructed-order thinking about international organization, see Gallarotti 1991). These examples sound a powerful cautionary note about the dangers of overconfidence in our ability to control social evolution, which has been internalized by libertarians and critical theorists alike. Yet it would be a mistake to reject altogether the attempt to shape social evolution, since there are also good reasons to worry about putting too much faith in a spontaneous approach. First, natural selection can take decades or even centuries to select for fit institutional forms, during which time all sorts of misery are possible. Human sacrifice and feudalism were both spontaneous rather than constructed orders; would it not have been better if some advocates of constructed order had existed back then to
What Is International Relations For?
211
deliberately bring those institutions to an end earlier than natural selection did? Second, trusting spontaneous order can encourage political complacency; had the U.S. Founders been Hayekians, for example, it is not clear how they could have justified designing a constitutional order for the United States.4 Third, the functions of social science seem too limited in this approach. If social scientists should not be trying to anticipate and shape the future, whether that means telling us that human sacrifice is bad or a constitution is good, what should they be doing? Social science seems to have an inherent constructivist sensibility. Finally, whether or not our efforts are doomed to failure, it seems to be our nature as human beings to try to influence the world around us. We all do this on a microscopic level every day, and we expect our leaders to do it on a macroscopic level over the long term. Thus there seems little point in telling decisionmakers not to make choices with a view toward the future. The point should be rather to use insights from the critiques of constructed order to help them do so more effectively. There are, then, pluses and minuses to spontaneous and constructed orders. Inevitably, the best path lies somewhere between the extremes. One way to think about something in between, to capture what is useful about constructed orders while remaining within a spontaneous approach overall, is with the metaphor of evolutionary steering. As I shall use the term, which I borrow from Niklas Luhmann,5 steering assumes that social orders, and perhaps especially international ones, mostly develop behind people’s backs through evolutionary dynamics of natural selection and social learning (see Wendt 1999: ch. 7). Most of what happens in social life over the medium to long run is not intended by anyone, policytakers or -makers. Thus the most that we can expect of steering is to channel, nudge, or guide evolution along in certain directions in an effort to avoid really bad outcomes and perhaps bring about a few good ones. Rather than determine particular events, the objective could be only to influence broad, developmental tendencies. This approach might sometimes involve efforts at conscious design in the sense of discrete moments of institutional reform, but it’s more about day-to-day guidance of the evolutionary process itself, trying to exploit its internal dynamics so that it moves—of its own accord, as it will—in a preferred direction. Relative to a pure constructed order, that is a very modest conception of human agency, but it would still constitute a considerably higher degree of purposive choice than we currently have about international politics. Three aspects of this conception of steering seem noteworthy, especially in light of the positivist/critical binary: instrumental rationality, goal directedness, and reflexivity. First, steering is about control and as such involves instrumental rationality, relating ends to means (cf. Luhmann 1997). It is a looser form of control than that which animates the construct-
212
Commentaries
ed-order approach, but for critical theorists, who often seem uncomfortable with any kind of instrumental rationality, it may still smack of the putatively technocratic ethos of positivism. Much of this unease stems from the fact that instrumental rationality is often used to control others, usually without their consent. Steering, however, is largely about controlling the self, the collective, global self, over time (how that self is constituted is an important issue raised further on). Although having an instrumentally rational component, self-command is less problematic normatively because in being applied to the self that component is intrinsically more accountable (Schelling 1984). If I make the ends-means calculation that going to college will improve my job prospects, I will have to coerce or discipline myself in the short run, but that is a matter very different from making such a decision for others. Second, the point of the control sought in steering is to bring about better outcomes than would naturally, or spontaneously, occur. One steers in order to go somewhere, and thus steering presupposes purpose, goal directedness, intentionality. Now, this statement in itself says nothing about the content of our purposes; a capacity for evolutionary steering could be used for good or evil. This is where the critical part of postcritical thinking comes in with a key normative constraint: Steering should be about emancipation, about freeing ourselves from the problematic social structures that cause war, human rights violations, racism, poverty, and so on. Critical theory, of course, already says this, but it tends to be better on emancipation from than emancipation to, and still weaker on how to get from here to there. Combining an emancipatory intent with an instrumental approach toward the future seems more likely to get us where we want to go. Finally, evolutionary steering depends on another important critical theory concern, namely reflexivity—understanding the role that our own beliefs and practices play in sustaining the social structures in which we are embedded. Here the connotations of the steering metaphor might be misleading. Steering a car on the road does not require much reflexivity. One should ideally know where one is going, of course, but since it is an external object (a car) that one is steering, there does not seem to be much need to know thyself to succeed. If steering a social system is ultimately about the evolution of a collective self, however, then knowing that self—how it is constituted, how it functions, and how it can be transformed—is crucial.
Problems of Steering Even if we interpret a construction problematic in world politics in the relatively modest terms of evolutionary steering, we still face hugely complex problems. In the first instance, it is not clear who the agent of global steer-
What Is International Relations For?
213
ing should be, and, in the second, what kind of constitution it should try to create. In other guises these two issues are already the subject of considerable scholarship in IR, and all I do in the following is reflect on them from a steering point of view. Something else that has been neglected in the literature is more interesting to me here: Regardless of who is steering or where they want to go, lurking in the background is an epistemological problem of knowing how to get from here to there, of long-range choice. In different ways all of these problems, and especially the last, challenge traditional positivist and critical conceptions of social science. I pretend no solutions here; my goal is merely to identify some questions that a science of steering naturally poses. Who’s Driving? If steering the international system presupposes a driver, then perhaps the first problem, analytically if not temporally, is constituting the subject, the intentional agent, who will be doing the driving. This problem has both practical and normative aspects. The intentionality of social systems is different from the intentionality of individuals in that it involves not a single agent but a collective one, a “we” or “plural subject” (Gilbert 1989). Plural subjects can take two basic forms—centralized, formally unitary organizations such as firms or states (a corporate identity or self) or decentralized teams of formally independent actors working together on a regular, harmonious basis (a collective identity or self).6 Both forms of agency might be relevant to steering the international system. Corporate steering agencies could be either greatpower hegemons who try to run the show on behalf of the system or international organizations with authoritative power—such as, increasingly, the EU—in which states merge their bodies. These would constitute international steering agencies on the centralized, domestic-analogy model. But the subject of international steering could also be a collective, a group of states and/or nonstate actors who retain their formal individuality but in practice cooperate closely in guiding the system. The great-power concert is an early manifestation of such a decentered agency; its spirit is found today in informal arrangements such as the Group of Seven (G7). A more institutionalized version of teamwork is represented by the idea of an international state—a formal structure of political authority that lacks an authoritative center but that can discipline its elements to cooperate, for example, the WTO or, perhaps, the EU (Picciotto 1991, Wendt 1994; also with specific reference to the EU, Caporaso 1996). And finally, also relevant to the constitution of a collective steering agency at the international level are “transnational public spheres” trying to keep states democratically accountable (Lynch 1999, Mitzen 1999). In short, the requirements of plural sub-
214
Commentaries
jectivity impose some limits on the individual elements (e.g., they have to work together), but these requirements can be met in various ways. No matter what their internal constitution, however, as every student of collective action knows, creating plural subjects is difficult and is compounded in international politics by the absence of centralized authority (anarchy). On top of the usual problems of free riding that make collective action difficult, anarchy creates incentives to pursue relative rather than absolute gains, making such action all but impossible. Indeed, realists have devoted much of their energy in recent years to showing why we should never expect anything more than episodic collective action in international politics. In contrast, nonrealists have worked equally hard to show that under certain conditions—where there is concern for the future, an expectation of continued interaction, relatively few actors, little likelihood of violence, and so on—actors can cooperate under anarchy, as they in fact often do in real life (much of the resulting debate can be found in Baldwin 1993). With deepening economic interdependence and a widening democratic peace, these conditions are gaining strength in the early twenty-first century, holding out the prospect that a capacity for international steering will coalesce. This prospect calls up the normative side of the question, however, namely who should be the subject of steering. Steering at the international level involves choices that could affect literally everyone in the world and thus raises serious questions of democratic accountability. This is especially true if steering is done at least in part by the currently most powerful actors in the system—states. States might be democratic at home, which would permit some accountability at the domestic level, but hardly any mechanisms exist yet at the system level to regulate their actions. This lack has already led to significant worries about a democratic deficit in the European Union, worries that are being allayed only partly by the gradual strengthening of the European Parliament, and there is every reason to think that other transnational accountability problems are going to become more intense over the coming decades as well (Held 1995). For this and other reasons, some critical theorists might object to the idea of states as subjects of international steering (if they didn’t object to the whole idea of steering in the first place), perhaps putting their faith in empowering global civil society instead. Indeed, although I can’t argue the point here, I suspect the issue that most reliably marks off scholars in IR as critical theorists is hostility toward the state (which makes sense, since states are the core of the given in international life that must be problematized). Those who see themselves as positivists are generally inclined to work with the state, whereas those who count themselves as critical theorists tend to treat states as the problem.7 From the standpoint of transnational democracy, antistatism might be a
What Is International Relations For?
215
good thing, but there are also other values at stake in steering, perhaps the most important of which is just getting things done, and that will require including states in the constitution of any future international steering agency. No other actor has remotely the potential for steering the international system as do states, and thus if we want to steer the system—a debatable goal, to be sure—we should exploit that fact. That still leaves us with the problem of making steering accountable, which is why it is important to make global civil society and public spheres part of the process. But the critical theorist’s concern with constituting a democratic subject of steering should not come completely at the expense of the positivist’s concern with constituting a viable one. Where Should We Go? Assuming that a capacity for system steering can be created, the question then arises of where we should use it to go. The answer is partly constrained by where we can go, since the evolution of the international system, like any social system, is path dependent. The world today is emerging from a deeply embedded state-centric approach to political community, and thus many places we might like to go—for example, a pure cosmopolitanism of open borders and human rights for all—are simply not available to us in the foreseeable future. And indeed, trying to create such a world before the conditions are right could lead to precisely the kind of imposed, illegitimate, and ultimately unstable order that critics of constructed order have long emphasized. Nevertheless, narrowing our vision to what is possible still leaves us with many options. These choices are in important part normative, reflecting competing values and visions of what such an order should look like. They have been the subject of considerable debate in political theory between cosmopolitans and communitarians, a debate in which the relative weight of the rights of individuals, groups, and states is at stake (for good overviews, see Brown 1992b and Van Dyke 1977). I don’t have anything special to contribute to this debate here, except two observations suggested by a concern with steering. First, more so than other conceptions of what IR is for, a steering problematic brings positive and normative inquiries naturally together. The positivist emphasis on separating facts and values encourages the isolation of normative thinking to political theory, whereas critical theory’s reluctance to think instrumentally and scientifically leaves empirical inquiries largely to positivists. Under the traditional models of what IR is for, in other words, there is not much for students of facts and of values to talk about. Each have their own domain, and there is little to bring them together. Figuring out where to go, in contrast, cannot be done except by talking
216
Commentaries
about facts and values together, and to that extent the steering problematic gives content and direction to both. Second, the problem of deciding where to go raises the question of whether the criteria we use to evaluate destinations should be substantive or procedural. Should we think about the goal of steering in an outcome-oriented way, aiming for particular goods, or more modestly in terms of process, worrying only about who is involved in decisionmaking and how it is carried out? A substantive approach seems more faithful to the basic idea of steering, but the existence in world politics of significant contestation about values argues for a procedural approach. And more interesting, so do the epistemological problems of knowledge and rationality in long-range choice, to which I now turn. How Do We Get There? Arguably the most fundamental problem of steering is choosing the right means to achieve long-term ends, because it exists no matter who the subject of steering is or where it wants to go. Even a perfectly accountable and politically correct driver faces the problem of navigating through time from a complex present to an uncertain future. Whereas the first two problems have been the subject of considerable IR scholarship, that is not true of this third one. The problem is at base epistemological in the sense that once we start thinking about the future—about time—in a way that gives meaning to our choices today, it becomes unclear what counts as informed, rational choice. The kinds of knowledge that positivists and critical theorists want to create are of relatively little help in thinking about how to relate the future to the present, and thus the problem of steering is most likely to yield new insights. The problem has various aspects, which I have grouped under two headings. The knowledge problem. This problem refers to the fact that it is simply very difficult, and perhaps impossible, to know how to control the evolution of social systems.8 We just don’t have the kind of knowledge, or at least not anywhere near enough of it, to successfully relate means to ends, at the system level, over the medium to long term. This constraint has both subjective and objective aspects concerning properties of the observer and of the observed. On the subjective side, the knowledge problem is the familiar one of bounded rationality. The issues here are the limited information-processing capabilities and cognitive biases of the human mind. Even if social systems are in principle knowable, creatures of our limited physical constitution cannot fully exploit this fact to achieve steering capacity. Serious as it is, however, bounded rationality is probably not the hard-
What Is International Relations For?
217
est part of the knowledge problem, which is that social systems might not be knowable in the first place. If the problem were ultimately subjective, we could hope that over time, with the march of social science and computer technology, we will be able to compensate for our cognitive limits and get better at steering. But there may be significant objective constraints on that prospect. The reason stems from the fact that to say we can know the future is to say it is already determined in the present. A knowable universe is a deterministic universe, or an “ergodic” universe, as Paul Davidson (1996) puts it. Yet there seem to be at least two features of social systems to suggest that they may ultimately be nondeterministic. One is complexity: nonlinear and chaotic dynamics that create randomness and unpredictability, stemming not from inadequacies in our cognitions or instruments but from reality itself. The other is uncertainty, where this is defined as distinct from risk—risk being a situation where one can define a probability distribution over future states, whereas uncertainty exists when such an effort is impossible because the domain of possible future states does not yet exist (on the differences between uncertainty and complexity, see Langlois and Everett 1992, and on the risk-uncertainty distinction, see Knight 1921). The theoretical and practical implications of uncertainty in this sense are quite radical and have been the subject of considerable debate in economics between mainstream Keynesians and heterodox Austrians and postKeynesians (see, for example, Lawson 1988, Kelsey and Quiggin 1992, Runde 1995). Complexity and uncertainty together support the famous “epistemological argument” against socialism, which shows that markets will inevitably be more efficient than command economies because central planners can never have as much knowledge of an economy as the decentralized knowledge produced by the price mechanism (see especially Hayek 1945), and this argument seems equally relevant to the problem of steering. In any case, it seems likely that since complexity and uncertainty will grow exponentially with the scale of the system and distance from the present, the knowledge problem involved in steering at the global level will be as difficult as it could possibly be. Paradoxically, however, it also seems to be the case that a nondeterministic, and therefore unknowable, environment is a precondition for steering in the first place—at least if the idea of steering implies, as I think it must, any sense of choice, intentionality, or free will. This is because in order to be meaningful as choice, an action cannot be predetermined. If it were the case that all our actions today were determined 100 years ago—as knowing the future today would seem to imply—then in what sense are those actions choices as opposed to just mechanical enactments of structural conditions? And if the future is already determined, in what sense could choices today make any difference? In short, the idea of steering seems to embody a contradiction: It assumes that what we do today makes a differ-
218
Commentaries
ence to the future; at the same time it requires foreknowledge of what will happen if we make those choices that vitiates their being choices at all. I don’t know how to resolve this contradiction, but it is the kind of paradox that emerges once we start thinking about time in a systematic, historical way (on historical conceptions of time, see Bausor 1983, Setterfield 1995). The rationality problem. Problems of time are perhaps even more salient for a second challenge of relating short-term means to long-term ends, which is that the definition of rationality, and therefore of rational choice, is ambiguous in that context. In day-to-day decisionmaking it seems useful to assume that to rationally choose means to maximize expected utility. But in decisionmaking over time, two of the three elements of this decision rule, expectations and utility, become problematic. Utility is problematic for a couple of reasons. First, it is not clear how future utility should be weighed against present utility. We might all agree that, other things being equal, it is better to consume utility today rather than tomorrow, but how much better, and what if things are not equal? External or structural conditions may sometimes provide an answer, but only sometimes. Thus in a Hobbesian war of all against all we are essentially forced to discount the future heavily, or else we won’t live long enough to enjoy it. But that external constraint is no longer present in the emerging constitutional order we’re talking about here, and thus we are more free to assign whatever value we like to future utility. How we do that will depend at least partly on normative judgments about our responsibilities to future generations, which reasonable people can disagree about. The issue of intergenerational justice brings up the second problem with measuring utility over time, which is that the subject to which we are attributing utility, who has utility, is not constant. Plural subjects are actually groups of individuals whose membership changes over time, so that even if there is a sense in which a future international steering agency is the same as one today, there is also a sense in which it is different (Wendt 1999: ch. 5). To that extent, decisions that we make about our long-term utility are actually decisions about the utility that others will get. As with the problem of weighing future utility, it is not clear what the criterion of rational should be under such conditions. The second component of the expected-utility framework, expectations, is equally problematic in historical time. The problem here is determining what constitutes a rational expectation about the future. What we have to go on is our past experience, and so some would say that the rational thing to do is simply extrapolate from that experience to the future. That assumption gains further support from the self-fulfilling nature of social expectations (Wendt 1999: ch. 4), which helps create institutional inertia and path-dependent development. However, we have already noted the par-
What Is International Relations For?
219
adox that it is a precondition for meaningful choice that agency not be determined by the past, which means that steering becomes possible precisely insofar as it deviates from past experience. And then there is the even deeper problem of constituting the present, the baseline knowledge about today from which rational expectations about the future are to be drawn. The problem here is that what we think about the present depends on what we expect in the future (see the very interesting discussion of this point in Parsons 1991). If we suddenly discovered that a giant meteor was going to destroy the earth in two weeks, the meanings most of us would assign to the present would radically change. To the extent that present and future are mutually constituted in this way, the idea of defining rational expectations on the basis of past experience begins to look incoherent (Bausor 1983). Maximizing expected utility, in short, is difficult even to conceptualize, much less to do, when historical time is brought into the equation. Thus it is not clear that using this formula to think about steering is rational. Indeed, in a widely cited article, Ronald Heiner has argued that given our inability to optimize under conditions of uncertainty, trying to do so may actually decrease our performance, and that we would do better—and in fact do do better—by simply following certain elementary rules of thumb that constrain our flexibility to choose rationally (Heiner 1983; see also Beckert 1996; cf. Langlois 1985). Whether this approach is right I don’t know, but it seems a question that a steering problematic needs to address.
The Limits of Positivism and Critical Theory These three questions about evolutionary steering are obviously difficult ones, and perhaps unanswerable. However, contemporary positivist and critical conceptions of social science don’t help matters much because in different ways each is ill equipped to address them, and the binary character of their debate makes it difficult to think beyond toward a synthesis. Positivism has difficulties with both the normative and positive aspects of steering. On the normative side positivists freely acknowledge silence because in their view science should be concerned only with facts, separated strictly from values. Yet as we saw, we cannot answer any of the three questions about steering without making normative choices. That does not mean that trying to separate facts and values is wrong, since there are purely explanatory, scientific aspects to steering. But it does mean that as long as our idea of IR is limited to positivism, we won’t be able to use our newfound knowledge for steering. What is more interesting, however, is that positivism—and here I mean only the logical empiricist version of positivism that has dominated IR since the 1960s—also runs into problems in what should be its strength, the
220
Commentaries
positive analysis of steering. This problem stems from the relatively poor fit of its ideal of science with the reality of the historical world. The goal of social science, according to positivism, is axiomatic theory based on lawlike generalizations about past experience—a worthy objective, to be sure, but one problematic for a science of steering for at least three reasons. First, the fact of complexity is likely to frustrate efforts to find the allimportant generalizations. The significant exception of the democratic peace aside, IR scholarship to date has failed to turn up many interesting behavioral laws on which we can ground theories. Second, even if IR scholars manage to find such laws, they will by definition be about the past and as such not a particularly reliable guide to the future, given the complex and uncertain nature of the world. Indeed, as we’ve seen, that the past would be a reliable guide to the future in some sense undermines the whole idea of steering, which presupposes a capacity to break with the past. And finally, making the discovery of behavioral laws a key objective of science is likely to make our theories more conservative, to blunt their critical edge, because in order to find laws we will have to take the institutions that generate them as given. That’s fine if our goal is problem solving within the existing order, but the point of steering, at least if we want to go anywhere, is to emancipate ourselves from that order (or its problematic aspects); that’s hard to do if we have taken the order as given. Behavioral laws are great to have, since they tell us something important about how the system in which we now find ourselves works, but if we want to change that system we also need knowledge of the deep social structures that make those laws possible. This last point reminds us that the troublesome requirement that a science of steering be based on behavioral laws is not intrinsic to positivism, understood broadly as the view that the scientific method is our best guide to how the world works, but only to the logical empiricist version of positivism, which is rooted in a Humean view of causality that makes laws necessary for knowledge. In recent years an alternative, scientific realist form of positivism has become dominant in the philosophy of science. Scientific realism is non-Humean and so less concerned with regularities of experience (for discussion of these issues, see Wendt 1999: ch. 2). In the realist view the emphasis in science should be not on behavioral regularities but on often unobservable causal mechanisms and deep structures, which in some conditions might generate regularities at the level of experience but in other conditions might not. There are various epistemological arguments for this proposal, but whatever their merits, it has the additional virtue here of coping more effectively than logical empiricism with the knowledge and rationality problems in evolutionary steering. Here, the basis on which we steer should be an understanding of structural logics and tendencies, even if we can’t predict specific events (Lawson 1995), and even if this requires
What Is International Relations For?
221
knowledge of behavioral regularities that are much harder to come by. What this suggests, therefore, is that if understood in realist terms, positivism could actually be a foundation for critical theory rather than always its other, a possibility arguably manifested in the fact that a realist view of science is implicit in Marxism, the origin of contemporary critical theory. Most critical theorists will want none of that proposal, perhaps, but without a scientific realist foundation it is difficult to see how they can help emancipate us from repressive structures in the world. Indeed, despite its praxeological concern, critical theory is also ill equipped for steering. This lack stems from the flip side of one of its main contributions to social science, namely, its democratic impulse. Critical theory encourages us to think about ways to make steering as accountable as possible, but too much concern for democracy can paralyze attempts to solve the problems of steering previously noted and thus to realize other values—like getting somewhere. I see this paralysis arising in three ways. First, critical theorists’ focus on empowering the weak makes it difficult for them to enlist the strong, especially states, in system transformation. Democratizing the world system by strengthening civil society is important, but global civil society will never be a primary agency of international steering and thus does not solve the problem of who’s driving. Oppositional politics make for fewer messy compromises, but given the weakness of civil society, refusing to engage states in system reform is in effect saying that we’re not going anywhere. Second, the critical IR literature, especially in its more postmodern forms, has shown little inclination to do the kind of rigorous and systematic empirical work about the contemporary international system that would reduce the knowledge problem in steering. In part this attitude reflects a healthy skepticism toward the narrow criteria positivists use to define rigorous and systematic (Walker 1989). However, it may also reflect a deeper, epistemological anxiety about making any claims about how the world really works, since truth can be a form of domination. Either way, the result is that critical IR scholarship has been not much interested in building a scientific understanding of our current situation and thus is in a poor position to help reduce our uncertainty about the future. This result relates to a third danger of critical theory’s democratic impulse, which is that it can lead to an anxiety about instrumental rationality altogether because it can be a basis for technocracy, bureaucratization, and totalitarianism. Yet instrumental rationality is also an essential part of steering, if only because steering involves means-ends calculations. A conception of social science that eschews instrumental rationality, therefore, will be an inherently partial one with respect to the steering problematic. In different ways, these three limits all contribute to a concluding danger in critical theory, which is a tendency toward utopian thinking, toward
222
Commentaries
idealism in the pejorative sense. Constrained—or liberated, as the case may be—from talking scientifically about how current structures work or how we can be emancipated from them, we are also relieved of the mental discipline that reality imposes. Idealism frees theory to speculate about normatively desirable outcomes but can also make for a certain lack of realism (for an example that illustrates both the promise and limits of this kind of thinking, see Archibugi 1995). And irrealism, in turn, can be a poor guide to action: The theory of the second best suggests that if the best outcome is unattainable, it may be irrational to pursue it if that pursuit prevents achievement of a second-best outcome (Goodin 1995). A science of steering requires creative speculation about desirable future states combined with objective analysis of current structures and constraints, not just one kind of knowledge or the other. In that light, even though the concept of evolutionary steering tends to fall between the cracks of the positivist/critical binary, by virtue of the fact that positivists and critical theorists bring different strengths and weaknesses to the issue, it is also an idea that by its nature might get them talking to each other.
Conclusion It is obvious that these remarks barely scratch the surface of some very complicated issues. But given the relative neglect of critical praxeology in IR scholarship, perhaps even a preliminary survey is useful. I want to make a last point about time and the role of expectations about the future in international politics, and about the kind of IR scholarship that would contribute to shaping those expectations. If policymakers (or -takers) think that the future will be just like the past, they will make choices today on that basis. And whether intentionally or not, those choices will generate the self-fulfilling prophecies that drive the evolution of the world system over the long run. What I want to emphasize here is the paradox of choices being made on the basis of expectations about the future, the actual character of which will depend on those very choices. If the concept of choice is to be meaningful, we have to assume that the future is open, and our expectations about it should therefore be treated as endogenously rather than exogenously determined. And that approach in turn creates a space for IR scholars to try to create expectations in much the same way that advertisers try to create tastes (see Parsons 1991). Because of path dependency those efforts are constrained in important ways by where the system is today. Yet because social evolution depends so much on the choices that people make, there is always room in principle for creating expectations that are not simply extrapolations from the past but that also reflect where we want to be in the future. To fully exploit this potential,
What Is International Relations For?
223
however, IR needs to think in a fundamentally forward-looking way rather than in the backward-looking way we mostly do now, and that will require thinking through some issues about time that have yet to be addressed much in IR. This conclusion raises the question of what a forward-looking, steering-oriented social science might look like. Perhaps the most well developed answer is the discipline of constitutional economics, essentially founded by James Buchanan, which is interested in choices among rules or constraints (Buchanan 1990; also see Vanberg 1994a and the journal Constitutional Political Economy). Work in this tradition has done much to clarify important problems of constitutional design and includes tentative applications to international politics as well (Sobel 1994, Vibert 1995). To be sure, constitutional economics is associated with an individualist ontology and libertarian ideology that some might find unpalatable. A question worth exploring is how much that ontology and ideology are integral to the science. But there are, in any case, other theoretical resources with which to build a science of steering, including the new constitutionalism in political theory and a growing body of theoretically informed empirical work on constitutional design in the European Union, the former Soviet bloc, South Africa, and so on (a sampling of this literature might include Horowitz 1991; Soltan and Elkin 1996; Weiler 1997; Elster, Offe, and Preuss 1998). An interesting feature of all this scholarship is that it is not easily classified as either positivist or critical but combines elements of both. Perhaps thinking about steering would be a way to put the positivist/critical binary to good use.
Notes 1. The plural here is important; even more so than positivism, critical theory today encompasses a wide range of epistemological, ontological, and political commitments, virtually the only common thread in which is rejection of positivism. Schools of thought often grouped under this heading include Gramscian and Frankfurt School Marxism, radical feminism, and postmodernism, among others. The characterizations of critical theory in this chapter apply more or less well to these different theories, and in some cases not at all. 2. Applied to constitutional evolution, Hayek’s distinction seems parallel to McIlwain’s (1940) between “ancient” and “modern” constitutions. 3. Hayek calls advocates of this approach constructivists, which may be confusing because the term means something different today in IR. Constructivists in IR also emphasize the role of agency in creating social orders but make no assumption that institutional outcomes are or should be intended. 4. In fact, Hayek himself has advocated constitutional designs (e.g., 1979); the problem, as otherwise sympathetic critics have noted (Witt 1994: 185–186), is that it is hard to justify this kind of interventionism within a spontaneous-order approach (cf. Vanberg 1994b: 190–195).
224
Commentaries
5. However, to the extent that I understand his treatment, he uses it to very different effect (see Luhmann 1997). My thinking on the balance between spontaneous and constructed orders is based on Prisching (1989), Hodgson (1991b), Wilke (1992), and Vanberg (1994b). 6. On teams, see Sugden 1993, and on corporate versus collective identity, see Wendt 1999: ch. 5. 7. This raises the question discussed by Neufeld (Ch. 8 in this volume) of the extent to which my own work can be considered critical. Although I have long seen myself as working in a critical vein (1987, 1992) and have once been asked to stand in for critical theory (1995), my thinking has always been state-centric and positivistic, on both counts giving it dubious credentials as critical theory. For a good discussion of the relationship between critical theory and constructivism in IR, see Price and Reus-Smit (1998). 8. The phrase “the knowledge problem” is Lavoie’s (1985); my treatment is somewhat broader.
References
Adler, Emanuel (1991) “Cognitive Evolution: A Dynamic Approach for the Study of International Relations and Their Progress,” in Emanuel Adler and Beverly Crawford (eds.), Progress in Postwar International Relations. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 43–88. Adorno, Theodor W. (1938/1982) “On the Fetish-Character in Music and the Regression of Listening,” in Andrew Arato and Eike Gebhardt (eds.), The Essential Frankfurt School Reader. New York: Continuum, pp. 270–299. ——— (1989) “Society,” Salmagundi 11–12 (Fall-Winter), pp. 144–153. Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer (1944/1979) The Dialectic of Enlightenment. London: Verso. Albert, Michel (1991) Capitalisme contre capitalisme. Paris: Seuil. Amer, Ramses (1993) “The United Nations’ Peacekeeping Operation in Cambodia: Overview and Assessment,” Contemporary Southeast Asia 15(2), pp. 211–231. Anderson, Perry (1979) Considerations on Western Marxism. London: Verso. Apel, Karl-Otto (1979) “The Conflicts of Our Time and the Problem of Political Ethics,” in F. Dallmayr (ed.), From Contract to Community. New York: Marcel Dekker. ——— (1980) Towards a Transformation of Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Archibugi, Daniele (1995) “From the United Nations to Cosmopolitan Democracy,” in Daniele Archibugi and David Held (eds.), Cosmopolitan Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 121–162. Archibugi, Daniele, and David Held (eds.) (1995) Cosmopolitan Democracy: An Agenda for a New World Order. Cambridge: Polity Press. Archibugi, Daniele, David Held, and Martin Kohler (eds.) (1998) Re-Imagining Political Community: Studies in Cosmopolitan Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press. Arendt, Hannah (1958) The Human Condition. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Arnvig, Eva (1994) “Women, Children and Returnees,” in Peter Utting (ed.), Between Hope and Insecurity: The Social Consequenses of the Cambodian Peace Process. Geneva: UNRISD, pp. 143–182.
225
226
References
Aron, Raymond (1966) Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations. London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson. Aronowitz, Stanley (1981) “A Metatheoretical Critique of Immanuel Wallerstein’s The Modern World System,” Theory and Society 10, pp. 503–520. Aronowitz, Stanley, and Henry Giroux (1985) “Radical Education and Transformative Intellectuals,” Canadian Journal of Political and Social Theory 19(3), pp. 48–63. Arrighi, Giovanni (1994) The Long Twentieth Century. London: Verso. Ashley, Richard (1981) “Political Realism and Human Interests,” International Studies Quarterly 25(2), pp. 204–236. ——— (1988) “Untying the Sovereign State: A Double Reading of the Anarchy Problematique,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 17(2), pp. 227–262. Ashley, Richard, and R.B.J. Walker (1990) “Reading Dissidence/Writing the Discipline: Crisis and the Question of Sovereignty in International Studies,” International Studies Quarterly 34(3), pp. 367–416. Augelli, Enrico, and Craig N. Murphy (1988) America’s Quest for Supremacy and the Third World: A Gramscian Analysis. London: Pinter. ——— (1998) “Consciousness, Myth and Collective Action,” in Stephen Gill and James H. Mittelman (eds.), Innovation and Transformation in International Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 25–38. Avineri, Shlomo (1972) Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Balch, Emily Greene (1910) Our Slavic Fellow Citizens. New York: Charities Publication Committee. ——— (1918) Approaches to the Great Settlement, introduction by Norman Angell. New York: B. W. Huebsch for the American Union Against Militarism. ——— (1927) Occupied Haiti. New York: Writers Publishing Company. Baldwin, David (ed.) (1993) Neorealism and Neoliberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Banathy, Bela (1998) “Evolution Guided by Design: A Systems Perspective,” Systems Research and Behavioral Science 15, pp. 161–172. Banks, Michael, and Chris Mitchell (1996) A Handbook of Conflict Resolution. London: Pinter. Baran, Paul (1957) The Political Economy of Growth. New York: Monthly Review Press. Barber, Benjamin (1995) Jihad vs. MacWorld. New York: Basic Books. ——— (1997) “The New Telecommunications Technology: Endless Frontier or the End of Democracy?” Constellations 4(2), pp. 208–228. Barrington, Kevin (1993) “Massacre Condemned But . . . ,” Phnom Penh Post, March 26–April 8, 1993, p. 1. Bartelson, Jens (1995) A Genealogy of Sovereignty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bausor, Randall (1983) “The Rational-Expectations Hypothesis and the Epistemics of Time,” Cambridge Journal of Economics 7(1), pp. 1–10. Baynes, Kenneth (1992) “Liberal Neutrality, Pluralism and Deliberative Politics,” Praxis International 12(1), pp. 50–69. ——— (1994) “Communicative Ethics, the Public Sphere and Communication Media,” Critical Studies in Mass Communication 11, pp. 315–326. ——— (1997) “Communitarian and Cosmopolitan Challenges to Kant’s Conception of Perpetual Peace,” in James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-Backmann (eds.),
References
227
Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant’s Cosmopolitan Ideal. Cambridge, MA, and London: MIT Press, pp. 219–234. Beckert, Jens (1996) “What is Sociological About Economic Sociology? Uncertainty and the Embeddedness of Economic Action,” Theory and Society 25(6), pp. 803–840. Beiner, Ronald (ed.) (1995) Theorizing Citizenship. Albany: State University of New York. Beitz, Charles (1979) Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ——— (1993) “Cosmopolitan Liberalism and the States System,” in Chris Brown (ed.), Political Restructuring in Europe: Ethical Perspectives. London: Routledge, pp. 123–136. Benhabib, Seyla (1993) Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics. Cambridge: Polity Press. Benhabib, Seyla, and Drucilla Cornell (eds.) (1987) Feminism as Critique: Essays on the Politics of Gender in Late-Capitalist Societies. Cambridge: Polity Press. Berdal, Mats R. (1993) Whither UN Peacekeeping? Adelphi Paper 281. London: International Institute for Strategic Studies (IISS). Bernstein, J. M. (1995) Recovering Ethical Life: Jürgen Habermas and the Future of Critical Theory. London: Routledge. Bernstein, Richard (1979) The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory. London: Methuen. ——— (1983) Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. ——— (1991) The New Constellation: The Ethical-Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity. Cambridge: Polity Press. Best, Steven, and Douglas Kellner (1991) Postmodern Theory: Critical Interrogations. New York: Guilford Press. Bloch, Ernst (1986) The Principle of Hope, translated by Neville Plaice, Stephen Plaice, and Paul Knight. Oxford: Blackwell. Bohler, D. (1990) “Transcendental Pragmatics and Critical Morality: On the Possibility and Moral Significance of a Self-Enlightenment of Reason,” in Seyla Benhabib and Fred Dallmayr (eds.), The Communicative Ethics Controversy. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 111–150. Bohman, James, and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann (eds.) (1997) Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant’s Cosmopolitan Ideal. Cambridge: MIT Press. Bokina, John, and Timothy J. Lukes (eds.) (1995) Marcuse Revisited. Lawrence: University of Kansas Press. Bonß, Wolfgang (1993) “The Program of Interdisciplinary Materialism and the Beginnings of Critical Theory,” in Seyla Benhabib, Wolfgang Bonß, and John McCole (eds.), On Max Horkheimer: New Perspectives. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 99–125. Booth, Ken (1991a) “Security and Emancipation,” Review of International Studies 17(4), pp. 313–326. ——— (1991b) “Security in Anarchy: Utopian Realism in Theory and Practice,” International Affairs 63(3), pp. 527–545. ——— (1995) “Human Wrongs and International Relations,” International Affairs 71(1), pp. 103–126. ——— (1997) “A Reply to Wallace,” Review of International Studies 23(3), pp. 371–377.
228
References
Boulding, Elise (1976) The Underside of History: A View of Women Through Time. Boulder: Westview Press. ——— (1997) “The Origin of Peace Studies,” introductory lecture to Peace and Justice Studies, Wellesley College, September 8. Boutros-Ghali, Boutros (1995) The United Nations in Cambodia 1991–1995. New York: UN. Braeckman, Colette (1997) “Comment le Zaïre fut libéré,” Le Monde Diplomatique, July. Brecher, Michael (1995) “Reflections on a Life in Academe,” International Studies Notes 20(3), pp. 1–8. Brecht, Bertolt (1939) “An die Nachgeborenen.” Gedichte, IV. London: MalikVerlag, p. 143. Brent, Douglas (1996) “Rogerian Rhetoric: An Alternative to Traditional Rhetoric,” in Barbara Emmel, Paula Resch, and Deborah Tenny (eds.), Argument Revisited, Argument Redefined. Beverly Hills: Sage, pp. 73–94. Bronner, Stephen Eric (1994) Of Critical Theory and Its Theorists. Oxford: Blackwell. Brown, Charles Calvin (1992) Niebuhr and His Age: Reinhold Niebuhr’s Prophetic Role in the Twentieth Century. Philadelphia: Trinity Press International. Brown, Chris (1992a) “Marxism and International Ethics,” in Terry Nardin and David Mapel (eds.), Traditions of International Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 225–249. ——— (1992b) International Relations Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. ——— (1994a) “Turtles All the Way Down: Antifoundationalism, Critical Theory and International Relations,” Millennium 23(2), pp. 213–238. ——— (1994b) “Critical Theory and Postmodernism in International Relations,” in A.J.R. Groom and M. Light (eds.), Contemporary International Relations: A Guide to Theory. London: Pinter, pp. 56–68. Buchanan, James (1990) “The Domain of Constitutional Economics,” Constitutional Political Economy 1(1), pp. 1–18. Buchwalter, Andrew (1992) “Hegel’s Concept of Virtue,” Political Theory 20(4), pp. 548–583. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, David Newman, and Alvin Rabushka (1996) Red Flag over Hong Kong. Chatham, NJ: Chatham House. Bull, Hedley (1977) The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics. London: Macmillan. ——— (1983) Justice and International Relations. The Hagey Lectures, University of Waterloo, Canada. Bull, Hedley, and Adam Watson (eds.) (1984) The Expansion of International Society. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Buzan, Barry (1996) “The Timeless Wisdom of Realism?” in Steve Smith, Ken Booth, and Marysia Zalewski (eds.), International Theory: Positivism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 47–65. Calhoun, Craig (1995) Critical Social Theory: Culture, History and the Challenge of Difference. Oxford: Blackwell. Camilleri, Joseph A., and Jim Falk (1992) The End of Sovereignty? The Politics of a Shrinking and Fragmenting World. Aldershot: Edward Elgar. Campbell, David (1992) Writing Security: United States Foreign Policy and the Politics of Identity. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
References
229
——— (1993) Politics Without Principle: Sovereignty, Ethics and the Narratives of the Gulf War. Boulder: Lynne Rienner. Caporaso, James (1996) “The European Union and Forms of State: Westphalian, Regulatory, or Post-modern?” Journal of Common Market Studies 34(1), pp. 43–88. Carr, Edward Hallett (1945) Nationalism and After. London: Macmillan. ——— (1946) The Twenty Years’ Crisis 1919–1939. London: Macmillan. ——— (1949) The Romantic Exiles. London: Penguin. ——— (1964) What Is History? London: Penguin. Chalmers, A. F. (1982) What Is This Thing Called Science? 2nd ed. Milton Keynes: Open University Press. Channo, Mang (1993a) “Women’s Day Highlights Gender Inequalities,” Phnom Penh Post, March 12–25, p. 1. ——— (1993b) “Sex Trade Flourishing in Capital,” Phnom Penh Post, February 12–25, p. 6. Chase-Dunn, Christopher (1989) Global Formation. Oxford: Blackwell. Checkel, Jeffrey T. (1998) “The Constructivist Turn in International Relations Theory,” World Politics 50 (January), pp. 324–348. Cheru, Fantu (1989) The Silent Revolution in Africa: Debt, Development and Democracy. Harare: Zed; London: Anvil Press. ——— (1997) “Global Apartheid and the Challenge to Civil Society: Africa in the Transformation of World Order,” in Robert W. Cox (ed.), The New Realism: Perspectives on Multilateralism and World Order. London: Macmillan for the UN University Press, pp. 205–222. Childe, Gordon (1942) What Happened in History? London: Penguin. Chomsky, Noam (1969) American Power and the New Mandarins. New York: Pantheon Books. ——— (1992) Chronicles of Dissent: Interviews with David Barsiman. Stirling: AK Press. Cochran, M. (1996) “International Ethics as Pragmatic Critique: Confronting the Epistemological Impasse of the Cosmopolitan/Communitarian Debate.” Ph.D. dissertation, University of London. Cohen, Jean (1990) “Discourse Ethics and Civil Society,” in David Rasmussen (ed.), Universalism vs. Communitarianism. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 83–105. Cohen, Joshua, and Joel Rogers (1992) “Associative Democracy,” in Pranab Bardhan and John Roemer (eds.), Market Socialism: The Current Debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 236–252. Coles, Romand (1995) “Identity and Difference in the Ethical Positions of Adorno and Habermas,” in S. K. White (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Habermas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 19–45. Colm, Sara (1992) “U.N. Agrees to Address Sexual Harassment Issue,” Phnom Penh Post, October 11, p. 1. Connolly, William E. (1988) “Identity and Difference in Global Politics,” in James Der Derian and Michael Shapiro (eds.), International/Intertextual Relations: Postmodern Readings in World Politics. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, pp. 323–342. Cox, Robert W. (1981) “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 10(2), pp. 126–155.
230
References
——— (1986) “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory” (with postscript), in R. O. Keohane (ed.), Neorealism and Its Critics. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 204–249. ——— (1987) Production, Power and World Order: Social Forces in the Shaping of History. New York: Columbia University Press. ——— (with Timothy Sinclair) (1996a) Approaches to World Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1996b) “Civilizations in World Political Economy,” New Political Economy 1 (2), pp. 141–156. ——— (1996c) “Global Perestroika,” reproduced in Robert W. Cox with Timothy J. Sinclair, Approaches to World Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 301–302. ——— (1996d) “A Perspective on Globalization,” in James H. Mittelman (ed.), Globalization: Critical Reflections. Boulder: Lynne Reinner, pp. 21–30. ——— (ed.) (1997) The New Realism: Perspectives on Multilateralism and World Order. London: Macmillan for the UN University Press. Curle, Adam (1971) Making Peace. London: Tavistock. Curtis, Grant (1994) “Transition to What? Cambodia, UNTAC and the Peace Process,” in Peter Utting (ed.), Between Hope and Insecurity: The Social Consequences of the Cambodian Peace Process. Geneva: UN Research Institute for Social Development, pp. 41–69. Dalby, S. (1990) Creating the Second Cold War: The Discourse of Politics. London: Pinter. Davidson, Paul (1996) “Reality and Economic Theory,” Journal of Post-Keynesian Economics 18(4), pp. 479–508. Davies, Robin (1993) “UNTAC and the Cambodian Economy: What Impact?” Phnom Penh Post, January 29–February 11, pp. 4–5. De Certeau, Michel (1988) The Practice of Everyday Life. Berkeley: University of California Press. Der Derian, James (1987) On Diplomacy: A Genealogy of Western Estrangement. Oxford: Blackwell. ——— (1992) Antidiplomacy: Spies, Terror, Speed and War. Oxford: Blackwell. ——— (1994) “Fathers (and Sons), Mother Courage (and Her Children), and the Dog, the Cave and the Beef,” in James Rosenau (ed.), Global Voices: Dialogues in International Relations. Boulder: Westview Press, pp. 83–96. Der Derian, James, and Michael Shapiro (eds.) (1989) International Intertextual Relations: Postmodern Readings of World Politics. Lexington: Lexington Books. Derrida, Jacques (1992) The Other Heading: Reflections on Today’s Europe, translated by Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael B. Naas. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. ——— (1994) Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning and the New International. London: Routledge. ——— (1996) “Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism,” in Chantal Mouffe (ed.), Deconstruction and Pragmatism, translated by Simon Critchley. Routledge: London and New York, pp. 77–88. Devetak, Richard (1995) “The Project of Modernity and International Relations Theory,” Millennium 24(1), pp. 27–51. ——— (1996a) “Postmodernism,” in Scott Burchill, Andrew Linklater, et al. (eds.), Theories of International Relations. London: Macmillan, pp. 179–209.
References
231
——— (1996b) “Critical Theory,” in Scott Burchill, Andrew Linklater, et al. (eds.), Theories of International Relations. London: Macmillan, pp. 145–178. Doyle, Michael W. (1995) UN Peacekeeping in Cambodia: UNTAC’s Civil Mandate. Boulder: Lynne Rienner. Doyle, Michael W., and Nishkala Suntharalingam (1994) “The UN in Cambodia: Lessons for Complex Peacekeeping,” International Peacekeeping 1(2), pp. 117–147. Dubiel, Helmut (1985) Theory and Politics: Studies in the Development of Critical Theory, translated by Benjamin Gregg. Cambridge: MIT Press. Dworkin, Ronald (1988) “Foundations of Liberal Equality,” in The Tanner Lectures, Vol. 11. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press. Edelman, Gerald M. (1994) The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory of Consciousness. New York: Basic Books. Elshtain, Jean Bethke (1987) Women and War. New York: Basic Books. ——— (1994) “Bringing It All Back Home Again,” in James Rosenau (ed.), Global Voices: Dialogues in International Relations. Boulder: Westview Press, pp. 97–116. Elster, Jon (1983) Sour Grapes. New York: Cambridge University Press. Elster, Jon, Claus Offe, and Ulrich Preuss (1998) Institutional Design in PostCommunist Societies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Eng, Peter (1992) “Little Sympathy for Vietnamese Victims,” Phnom Penh Post, August 7, p. 4. Enloe, Cynthia H. (1980) Police, Military and Ethnicity Foundations of State Power. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books. ——— (1989) Bananas, Beaches and Bases. London: Pandora. ——— (1993) The Morning After: Sexual Politics at the End of the Cold War. Berkeley: University of California Press. Falk, Richard (1995) On Humane Governance. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Falk, Richard, Robert Johansen, and Samuel Kim (eds.) (1993) The Constitutional Foundations of World Peace. Albany: State University of New York Press. Fallows, James (1994) Looking at the Sun: The Rise of the New East Asian Economic and Political System. New York: Pantheon. Fishkin, James (1990) Democracy and Deliberation. New Haven: Yale University Press. ——— (1991) Remarks on Marx: Conversations with Duccio Trombadori, translated by R. James Golstein. New York: Semiotext(e). Foucault, Michel (1991) Remarks on Marx: Conversations with Duccio Trombadori. Translated by R. James Goldstein and James Cascaito. New York: Semiotest. Fox, Byron (1964) “The Emerging International Society,” in Irving L. Horowitz (ed.), The New Sociology: Essays in Social Science and Social Theory in Honor of C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 476–490. Frank, André Gunder (1967) Capitalism and Underdevelopment in Latin America. New York: Monthly Review Press. ——— (1997) “Review of Stephen Gill and James Mittelman, Innovation and Transformation in International Studies,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 26(2), pp. 471–477. Fraser, Nancy (1989a) “Introduction,” in Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse and Gender in Contemporary Social Theory. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 1–13.
232
References
——— (1989b) “What’s Critical About Critical Theory? The Case of Habermas and Gender,” in Nancy Fraser, Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse, and Gender in Contemporary Social Theory. Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press, pp. 113–143. ——— (1992) “Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the Critique of Actually Existing Democracy,” in Craig Calhoun (ed.), Habermas and the Public Sphere. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 109–142. ——— (1995) “From Redistribution to Recognition? Dilemmas of Justice in a ‘Post-Socialist’ Age,” New Left Review 212 (July-August), pp. 68–93. Frazer, Elizabeth, and Nicola Lacey (1993) The Politics of Community: A Feminist Critique of the Liberal-Communitarian Debate. London: Harvester. Friere, Paulo (1983) Pedagogy of the Oppressed. New York: Continuum. Frost, Mervyn (1994) “The Role of Normative Theory in IR,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 23(1), pp. 109–118. Gallarotti, Giulio (1991) “The Limits of International Organization,” International Organization 45(2), pp. 183–220. Gay, Peter (1974) Weimar Culture: The Insider as Outsider. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Geoghan, Vincent (1995) Ernst Bloch. London: Routledge. George, Jim (1994) Discourses of Global Politics: A Critical (Re)Introduction to International Relations. Boulder: Lynne Rienner. Giddens, Anthony (1985) The Nation-State and Violence. Cambridge: Polity Press. ——— (1993) The Consequences of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press. ——— (1998) The Third Way. Cambridge: Polity Press. Gilbert, Margaret (1989) On Social Facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Goodin, Robert (1985) “Laundering Preferences,” in Jon Elster (ed.), Foundations of Rational Choice Theory. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 75–101. ——— (1995) “Political Ideals and Political Practice,” British Journal of Political Science 25(1), pp. 37–56. ——— (ed.) (1996) The Theory of Institutional Design. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gordon, Colin (1991) “Governmental Rationality: An Introduction,” in Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller (eds.), The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality. London: Harvester, pp. 1–51. Grant, Rebecca, and Kathleen Newland (eds.) (1991) Gender and International Relations. Milton Keynes: Open University Press. Haber, Honi Fern (1994) Beyond Postmodern Politics: Lyotard, Rorty, Foucault. London: Routledge. Habermas, Jürgen (1971) Knowledge and Human Interests, translated by Jeremy J. Shapiro. Boston: Beacon Press. ——— (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 1, Reason and the Rationalization of Society, translated by Thomas McCarthy. London: Heinemann. ——— (1987) The Philosophical Discourses of Modernity: Twelve Lectures. Cambridge: Polity Press. ——— (1989a) The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 2, Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason. London: Heinemann. ——— (1989b) The New Conservatism. Cambridge: MIT Press. ——— (1990a) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge: Polity Press.
References
233
——— (1990b) “What Does Socialism Mean Today?” New Left Review 183, pp. 3–21. ——— (1992a) Autonomy and Solidarity: Interviews with Jürgen Habermas, edited and introduced by Peter Dews. London: Verso. ——— (1992b) “Further Reflections on the Public Sphere,” in Craig Calhoun (ed.), Habermas and the Public Sphere. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 421–461. ——— (1993) Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics. Cambridge: Polity Press. ——— (1994a) The Past as Future. Cambridge: Polity Press. ——— (1994b) “Three Models of Democracy,” Constellations 1(1), pp. 1–10. ——— (1996a) “The European Nation State: Its Achievements and Its Limitations,” Ratio Juris 9(1), pp. 125–137. ——— (1996b) Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, translated by William Rehg. Cambridge: Polity Press. ——— (1997) “Kant’s Idea of Perpetual Peace, with the Benefit of Two Hundred Years’ Hindsight,” in James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann (eds.), Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant’s Cosmopolitan Ideal. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 113–153. Hale, J. R. (1996) “Machiavelli and the Self-Sufficient State,” in David Thomson (ed.), Political Ideas. London: Penguin, pp. 22–33. Halliday, Fred (1987) “Vigilantism in International Relations,” Review of International Studies 13(3), pp. 163–175. ——— (1994) Rethinking International Relations. London: Macmillan. ——— (1996) “The Future of International Relations: Fears and Hopes,” in Steve Smith, Ken Booth, and Marysia Zalewski (eds.), International Theory: Positivism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 318– 327. Hampson, F. O. (1997) “Third Party Roles in the Termination of Intercommunal Conflict,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 26(3), pp. 727–750. Harries-Jones, Peter, Abraham Rotstein, and Peter Timmerman (1992) “Nature’s Veto: UNCED and the Debate over the Earth,” unpublished paper. ——— (1998) “A Signal Failure: Ecology and Economy After the Earth Summit,” in Michael Schechter (ed.), Future Multilateralism: The Political and Social Framework. London: Macmillan for the UN University Press, pp. 101–135. Harrington, Michael (1977) The Vast Majority: A Journey to the World’s Poor. New York: Simon and Schuster. Harrington, Mona (1981) The Dream of Deliverance in American Politics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Harrod, Jeffrey (1980) “The Evolution of the Subject of International Political Economy 1967–1977,” in R. Kent and G. Nielson (eds.), The Study and Teaching of International Relations. London: Pinter, pp. 78–98. ——— (1987) Power, Production and the Unprotected Worker. New York: Columbia University Press. ——— (1997) “Social Forces and International Political Economy: Joining the Two IRs,” in Stephen Gill and James H. Mittelman (eds.), Innovation and Transformation in International Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 105–115. Hayek, Friedrich (1945) “The Use of Knowledge in Society,” American Economic Review 35(4), pp. 519–530. ——— (1973) Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 1, A New Statement of the Liberal
234
References
Principles of Justice and Political Economy. Rules and Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ——— (1979) Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 3, A New Statement of the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy. The Political Order of a Free People. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Heine, Christian, and Benno Teschke (1996) “Sleeping Beauty and the Dialectical Awakening: On the Potential of Dialectic for International Relations,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 25(2), pp. 399–423. Heiner, Ronald (1983) “The Origin of Predictable Behavior,” American Economic Review 83, pp. 560–595. Heininger, Janet E. (1994) Peacekeeping in Transition: The United Nations in Cambodia. New York: Twentieth Century Fund Press. Held, David (1980) Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas. Berkeley: University of California Press; Cambridge: Polity Press. ——— (1991) “Democracy and the Global System,” in David Held (ed.), Political Theory Today. Stanford: Stanford University Press, pp. 197–235. ——— (ed.) (1992) Prospects for Democracy: North, South, East, West. Cambridge: Polity Press. ——— (1995) Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance. Cambridge: Polity Press. Helleiner, Eric (1996) “International Political Economy and the Greens,” New Political Economy 1(1), pp. 59–77. Hirst, Paul, and Graham Thompson (1996) Globalisation in Question. Cambridge: Polity Press. Hobsbawm, E. J. (1994) The Age of Extremes: A History of the World, 1914–1991. New York: Pantheon. Hobson, J. A. (1965) Imperialism: A Study. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Hodgson, Geoffrey (199la) “Hayek’s Theory of Cultural Evolution,” Economics and Philosophy 7(1), pp. 67–82. ——— (1991b) “Evolution and Intention in Economic Theory,” in P. Paolo Sowiotti and J. Stanley Metcalfe (eds.), Evolutional Theories of Economic and Technological Change. Melbourne: Harwood Academic Press. Hoffman, Mark (1987) “Critical Theory and the Inter-Paradigm Debate,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 16(2), pp. 231–249. ——— (1988) “Conversations on Critical International Relations,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 17(1), pp. 91–95. ——— (1991) “Restructuring, Reconstruction, Reinscription, Rearticulation: Four Voices in Critical International Relations Theory,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 20(2), pp. 169–185. ——— (1992) “Third-Party Mediation and Conflict Resolution in the Post–Cold War World,” in John Baylis and N. J. Rengger (eds.), Dilemmas of World Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 261–286. ——— (1993) “Agency, Identity and Intervention,” in Ian Forbes and Mark Hoffman (eds.), Political Theory, International Relations and the Ethics of Intervention. London: Macmillan, pp. 194–211. ——— (1995) “Defining and Evaluating Success: Facilitative Problem-Solving Workshops in an Interconnected Context,” Paradigms: The Kent Journal of International Relations 9(2), pp. 150–167. Hoffmann, Stanley (1968) Gulliver’s Troubles or the Setting of American Foreign Policy. New York: McGraw Hill.
References
235
Hohendahl, Peter Uwe (1991) Reappraisals: Shifting Alignments in Postwar Critical Theory. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Hollis, Martin (1994) The Philosophy of Social Science: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Holsti, Ole R. (1962) “The Belief System and National Images: A Case Study,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 6(3), pp. 244–252. Holub, Renate (1992) Antonio Gramsci: Beyond Marxism and Postmodernism. London: Routledge. Honderich, Ted (ed.) (1995) The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Honneth, Axel (1982) “Work and Instrumental Action,” New German Critique 25, pp. 31–54. ——— (1985) Kritik der Macht: Reflexions-stufen einer kritischen Gesellschaftstheorie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag. ——— (1992a) Kampf um Anerkennung. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag. ——— (1992b) Cultural-Political Interventions in the Unfinished Project of Enlightenment. Cambridge: MIT Press. ——— (1994) “The Social Dynamics of Disrespect: On the Location of Critical Theory Today,” translated by John Farrell, Constellations 1(2), pp. 255–269. ——— (1995a) “The Other of Justice: Habermas and the Ethical Challenge of Postmodernism,” in Stephen K. White (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Habermas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 289–323. ——— (1995b) The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts, translated by Joel Anderson. Cambridge: Polity Press. Hopf, Ted (1998) “The Promise of Constructivist International Relations Theory,” International Security 23(1), pp. 171–200. Horkheimer, Max (1968) “Die gesellschaftliche Funktion der Philosophie,” in Alfred Schmidt (ed.), Kritische Theorie: Eine Dokumentation. Frankfurt: S. Fischer Verlag, pp. 292–312. ——— (1972) “Traditional and Critical Theory,” in Max Horkheimer, Critical Theory: Selected Essays, translated by Matthew J. O’Connell et al. New York: Seabury Press, pp. 188–243. Horowitz, Donald (1991) A Democratic South Africa? Constitutional Engineering in a Divided Society. Berkeley: University of California Press. Hoy, David Couzens, and Thomas McCarthy (1994) Critical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell. Husseini, Faisal (1991) “Palestinan Politics After the Gulf War,” Journal of Palestine Studies 20(4), pp. 95–110. Hutchings, Kimberly (1994) “The Personal Is International: Feminist Epistemology and the Case of International Relations,” in K. Lennon and M. Whitford (eds.), Knowing the Difference: Feminist Perspectives in Epistemology. London: Routledge, pp. 149–163. ——— (1995) Kant, Critique and Politics. London: Routledge. ——— (1997) “Foucault and International Relations Theory,” in M. Lloyd and A. Thacker (eds.), The Impact of Michel Foucault on the Social Sciences and Humanities. London: Macmillan, pp. 102–127. Hutton, Will (1995) The State We’re In. London: Cape. Ikenberry, John (1998) “Constitutional Politics in International Relations,” European Journal of International Relations 4(1), pp. 147–177. Jackson, Robert H. (1993) Quasi-States: Sovereignty, International Relations and the Third World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
236
References
James, Alan (1995) “Peacekeeping in the Post–Cold War Era,” International Journal 50(2), pp. 241–265. Jameson, Frederic (1990) Late Marxism: Adorno, or, the Persistence of the Dialectic. London: Verso. Jay, Martin (1973) The Dialectical Imagination. Boston: Little, Brown. ——— (1984a) Adorno. London: Fontana. ——— (1984b) Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukács to Habermas. Los Angeles: University of California Press. Jennar, R. M. (1994) “UNTAC: ‘International Triumph’ in Cambodia?” Security Dialogue 25(2), pp. 145–156. Jones, R. E. (1994) “The Responsibility to Educate,” Review of International Studies 20(3), pp. 299–311. Kant, Immanuel (1929) Critique of Pure Reason, edited by N. Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan. ——— (1970) “Perpetual Peace,” in M. Forsyth, H.M.A. Keens-Soper, and P. Savigear (eds.), The Theory of International Relations: Selected Texts from Gentili to Treitschke. London: Allen and Unwin, pp. 200–244. ——— (1991) “An Answer to the Question: ‘What Is Enlightenment?’” in Hans Reiss (ed.), Kant: Political Writings, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 54–60. Kaplan, Caren (1994) “The Politics of Location as Transnational Feminist Critical Practice,” in Inderpal Grewal and Caren Kaplan (eds.), Scattered Hegemonies: Postmodernity and Transnational Feminist Practices. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 137–152. Karsh, Efraim (1994) Peace in the Middle East: The Challenge for Israel. Ilford, Essex: Frank Cass. Katzenstein, Peter J., Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner (1998) “International Organization and the Study of World Politics,” International Organization 52(4), pp. 645–685. Keane, J. (1990) “The Modern Democratic Revolution: Reflections on Lyotard’s The PostModern Condition,” in A. Benjamin (ed.), Judging Lyotard. London: Routledge, pp. 81–98. Kegley, Charles W., and Robert W. Bretall (eds.) (1956) Reinhold Niebuhr: His Religious, Social and Political Thought. New York: Macmillan. Kegley, Charles W., Jr., and Gregory Raymond (1994) A Multipolar Peace: Great Power Politics in the Twenty-first Century. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Kellner, Douglas (1999a) “Critical Theory, Poststructuralism, and the Philosophy of Liberation,” http://www.uta.edu/human/illuminations/kell7.htm. ——— (1999b) “Boundaries and Borderlines: Reflections on Jean Baudrillard and Critical Theory,” www.uta.edu/human/illuminations/kell2.htm. Kelsey, D., and J. Quiggin (1992) “Theories of Choice Under Ignorance and Uncertainty,” Journal of Economic Surveys 6(2), pp. 133–153. Keohane, Robert (1988) “International Institutions: Two Approaches,” International Studies Quarterly 32(4), pp. 379–396. ——— (1989) “International Relations Theory: Contributions of a Feminist Standpoint,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 18(2), pp. 245–251. Kirshenbaum, Gayle (1994) “Who’s Watching the Peacekeepers?” Ms. (May-June). Klintworth, Gary (1993) “United Nations: A Poor Job in Cambodia,” International Herald Tribune, February 2. Knight, Frank (1921) Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. New York: Houghton Mifflin.
References
237
Kolakowski, Leszek (1978) Main Currents of Marxism, Vol. 2, The Golden Age. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kratochwil, Friedrich V. (1987) “Rules, Norms, Values and the Limits of ‘Rationality,’” Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 73, pp. 301–329. ——— (1989) Rules, Norms, Decisions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1995) “Sovereignty as Dominium: Is There a Right of Humanitarian Intervention?” in Gene M. Lyons and Michael Mastanduno (eds.), Beyond Westphalia? State Sovereignty and International Intervention. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 21–42. Krause, Keith, and Michael C. Williams (eds.) (1997) Critical Security Studies: Concepts and Cases. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Kristeva, Julia (1991) Stranger to Ourselves, translated by Leon Roudiez. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Kymlicka, Will (1989) Liberalism, Community and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (1995) Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Langlois, Richard (1985) “Knowledge and Rationality in the Austrian School: An Analytical Survey,” Eastern Economic Journal 9(4), pp. 309–330. Langlois, Richard, and Michael Everett (1992) “Complexity, Genuine Uncertainty, and the Economics of Organization,” Human Systems Management 11(1), pp. 67–75. Lasswell, Harold D. (ed.) (1934) “World Politics and Personal Insecurity,” reprinted in Harold D. Lasswell (ed.), A Study of Power. Glencoe: Free Press. Lavoie, Don (1985) National Economic Planning: What Is Left? Cambridge, MA: Ballinger. Lawson, Tony (1988) “Probability and Uncertainty in Economic Analysis,” Journal of Post-Keynesian Economics 11(1), pp. 38–65. ——— (1995) “Economics and Expectations,” in S. Dow and J. Hillard (eds.), Keynes, Knowledge, and Uncertainty. Aldershot: Edward Elgar, pp. 77–106. Ledgerwood, Judy L. (1994) “UN Peacekeeping Missions: The Lessons from Cambodia,” Analysis from the East-West Center 11. Honolulu: East-West Center. LeFeber, Walter (1963) The New Empire: An Interpretation of American Expansion. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Leonard, Stephen (1994) Critical Theory and Political Practice. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Ling, Lily (1996) “Hegemony and the Internationalizing State: A Post-Colonial Analysis of China’s Integration into Asian Corporatism,” Review of International Political Economy 3(1), pp. 1–26. Linklater, Andrew (1990a) Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations. London: Macmillan. ——— (1990b) Beyond Marxism and Realism: Critical Theory and International Relations. London: Macmillan. ——— (1992a) “The Question of the Next Stage in International Relations Theory: A Critical Theoretic Point of View,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 21(1), pp. 77–98. ——— (1992b) “What Is a Good International Citizen?” in P. Keal (ed.), Ethics and Foreign Policy. Sydney: Allen and Unwin, pp. 21–43.
238
References
——— (1993) “Community, Citizenship and Global Politics,” Oxford International Review 5(1), pp. 6–9. ——— (1995a) “Neo-Realism in Theory and Practice,” in K. Booth and S. Smith (eds.), International Relations Theory Today. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 241–262. ——— (1995b) “Community,” in Alex Danchev (ed.), Fin de Siècle; The Meaning of the Twentieth Century. London: I. B. Tauris, pp. 177–197. ——— (1996a) “Citizenship and Sovereignty in the Post-Westphalian State,” European Journal of International Relations 2(1), pp. 77–103. ——— (1996b) “The Achievements of Critical Theory,” in S. Smith, K. Booth, and M. Zalewski (eds.), International Theory: Positivism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 279–298. ——— (1998) The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the Post-Westphalian Era. Cambridge: Polity Press. Lipschutz, Ronnie, with Judith Mayer (1996) Global Civil Society and Global Environmental Governance: The Politics of Nature from Place to Planet. Albany: State University of New York Press. Long, David (1996) Towards a New Liberal Internationalism: The International Theory of J. A. Hobson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Luhmann, Niklas (1997) “Limits of Steering,” Theory, Culture, and Society 14(1), pp. 41–57. Lynch, Marc (1999) State Interests and Public Spheres: The International Politics of Jordan’s Identity. New York: Columbia University Press. Lyotard, Jean-François (1993) “The Other’s Rights,” in S. Shute and S. Hurley (eds.), On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures. New York: Basic Books, pp. 135–147. Lyotard, Jean-François, and Jean-Loup Thebaud (1985) Just Gaming. Manchester: Manchester University Press. MacCormack, N. (1996) “Liberalism, Nationalism and the Post-Sovereign State,” Political Studies 44(3), pp. 553–567. Macedo, Stephen (1990) Liberal Virtues. Oxford: Clarendon. Madeuf, Bernadette, and Charles-Albert Michalet (1978) “A New Approach to International Economics,” International Social Science Journal 30(2), pp. 253–283. Manin, B. (1987) “On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation,” Political Theory 15(3), pp. 338–368. Mann, Michael (1986) The Sources of Social Power, Vol. 1, A History of Power from the Beginning to A.D. 1760. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1996) “Authoritarian and Liberal Militarism: A Contribution from Comparative and Historical Sociology,” in S. Smith, K. Booth, and M. Zalewski (eds.), International Theory: Positivism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 221–239. Mazen, Abu (1995) Through Secret Channels. Reading: Garnet. Marcuse, Herbert (1972a) Negations. Harmondsworth: Penguin. ——— (1972b) One-Dimensional Man. London: Abacus. Marx, Karl (1968a) “The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte,” in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Selected Works in One Volume. London: Lawrence and Wishart, pp. 96–179. ——— (1968b) “A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy,” preface, in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Selected Works in One Volume. London: Lawrence and Wishart, pp. 180–184.
References
239
——— (1973) “On the British Rule in India,” in David Fernbach (ed.), Marx’s Political Writings, Vol. 2. Harmondsworth: Penguin, pp. 301–307. McCarthy, Thomas (1978) The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas. Cambridge: MIT Press. ——— (1994) “Philosophy and Critical Theory: A Reprise,” in David Couzens Hoy and Thomas McCarthy, Critical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 5–100. McCaughey, Robert A. (1984) International Studies and Academic Enterprise: A Chapter in the Enclosure of American Learning. New York: Columbia University Press. McCormick, Thomas J. (1967) China Market: America’s Quest for Informal Empire, 1893–1901. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. McIlwain, Charles (1940) Constitutionalism Ancient and Modern. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. McLean, Ian (1991) “Forms of Representation and Systems of Voting,” in David Held (ed.), Political Theory Today. Stanford: Stanford University Press, pp. 172–196. Mearsheimer, John (1994–1995) “The False Promise of International Institutions,” International Security 19(3), pp. 5–49. Meehan, Elizabeth (1993) Citizenship and the European Community. London: Sage. Merkeley, Paul (1975) Reinhold Niebuhr: A Political Account. Montreal: McGillQueen’s University Press. Mertens, Thomas (1996) “Cosmopolitanism and Citizenship: Kant Against Habermas,” European Journal of Philosophy 4, pp. 328–347. Metz, Johann Baptist (1969) Political Theology, translated by William GlenDoepel. New York: Herder & Herder. Millennium (1997) Special section: On Dialectic and IR Theory 26(2), pp. 403–470 Miller, David (1992) “Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice,” Political Studies 40, Special Issue, pp. 54–67. ——— (1995) On Nationality. New York: Oxford University Press. Miller, J.B.D. (1995) “Norman Angell and Rationality in International Relations,” in David Long and Peter Wilson (eds.), Thinkers of the Twenty Years’ Crisis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 100–121. Mills, C. Wright (1951) White Collar: The American Middle Classes. New York: Oxford University Press. ——— (1959) The Sociological Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mitzen, Jennifer (1999) “Managing Anarchy: The Emergence and Consolidation of the International Public Sphere.” Ph.D. dissertation, University of Chicago. Mohanty, Chandra Talpade (1991a) “Cartographies of Struggle: Third World Women and the Politics of Feminism,” in Chandra Talpade Mohanty, Ann Russo, and Lourdes Torres (eds.), Third World Women and the Politics of Feminism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 1–47. ——— (1991b) “Under Western Eyes: Feminist Scholarship and Colonial Discourses,” in Chandra Talpade Mohanty, Ann Russo, and Lourdes Torres (eds.), Third World Women and the Politics of Feminism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 51–80. Moltmann, Jürgen (1967) Theology of Hope. London: Student Christian Movement. Moon, Donald (1991) “Constrained Discourse and Public Life,” Political Theory 19(2), pp. 202–229. Morgenthau, Hans Joachim (1967) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 4th ed. New York: Knopf. Morris, William (1986) Three Works. London: Lawrence and Wishart.
240
References
Munthit, Ker (1993) “Akashi: Election ‘Free and Fair,’” Phnom Penh Post, June 6–12, p. 3. Murphy, Craig N. (1994) International Organization and Industrial Change: Global Governance Since 1850. Cambridge: Polity Press; New York: Oxford University Press. ——— (1998) “The Functional Approach, Organisation Theory and Conflict Resolution,” in David Long and Lucian Ashworth (eds.), New Perspectives on International Functionalism. London and New York: Macmillan and St. Martin’s Press, pp. 84–104. Murphy, Craig N., and Roger Tooze (eds.) (1991) The New International Political Economy. Boulder: Lynne Rienner. Najman, Maurice (1997) “Le grand virage des zapatistes,” Le Monde Diplomatique (January). Nardin, Terry, Chris Brown, and N. J. Rengger (1998) Texts in International Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nehru, Jawaharlal (1985) The Discovery of India. Delhi: Oxford University Press. Nelson, Benjamin (1973) “Civilisational Complexes and Inter-Civilisational Relations,” Sociological Analysis 74(1), pp. 79–105. Neufeld, Mark (1994) “Who’s Afraid of Meta-Theory?” in Millennium: Journal of International Studies 23(2), pp. 387–393. ——— (1995) The Restructuring of International Relations Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1995–1996) “Critical Interventions: New Directions in IR Theory,” International Journal 51, pp. 148–154. ——— (1996) “The State in/of International Relations Theory,” Mershon International Studies Review 40(2), pp. 262–265. ——— (1997) “Reformulating Realism: The ‘Tradition’ Strikes Back,” Mershon International Studies Review 41(2), pp 327–329. Neumann, Iver, and Ole Wæver (1997) The Future of International Relations: Masters in the Making. London: Routledge. Nove, Alec (1983) The Economics of Feasible Socialism. London: Allen and Unwin. Offe, Claus (1992) “Binding, Shackles, Brakes: On Self-Limitation Strategies,” in Axel Honneth, Thomas McCarthy, Claus Offe, and Albrecht Wellmer (eds.), Cultural-Political Interventions in the Unfinished Project of Enlightenment. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 63–94. Ong, Aihwa (1988) “Colonialism and Modernity: Feminist Re-Presentations of Women in Non-Western Societies,” Inscriptions 3(4), pp. 79–93. Onuf, Nicholas (1989) World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social Theory and International Relations. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press. ——— (1997) The Republican Legacy in International Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Orwell, George (1984) “Politics and the English Language,” in The Penguin Essays of George Orwell. London: Penguin, p. 352. Outhwaite, William (1994) Habermas: A Critical Introduction. Cambridge: Polity Press. Palmieri, Patricia Ann (1995) In Adamless Eden: The Community of Women Faculty at Wellesley. New Haven: Yale University Press. Parsons, Stephen (1991) “Time, Expectations and Subjectivism,” Cambridge Journal of Economics 15(4), pp. 405–423.
References
241
Patai, Daphne (1994) “Sick and Tired of Scholars’ Nouveau Solipsism,” Chronicle of Higher Education 40(25), p. A52. Peach, Katrina (1993) “HIV Threatens to Claim UNTAC’s Highest Casualties,” Phnom Penh Post, October 22–November 4, p. 4. Peres, Shimon (1995) Battling for Peace. London: Orion. Perkin, Harold James (1996) The Third Revolution: Professional Elites in the Modern World. London: Routledge. Peterson, V. Spike (ed.) (1992a) Gendered States: Feminist (Re)Visions of International Relations Theory. Boulder: Lynne Rienner. ——— (1992b) “Security and Sovereign States: What Is at Stake in Taking Feminism Seriously,” in V. Spike Peterson (ed.), Gendered States: Feminist (Re)Visions of International Relations Theory. Boulder: Lynne Rienner, pp. 31–64. Pettit, Philip (1993) The Common Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pettman, Ralph (1995) “Review of The Empire of Civil Society,” New Zealand International Review 20(3), pp. 28–29. Phillips, Anne (1993) Democracy and Difference. Cambridge: Polity Press. Picciotto, Sol (1991) “The Internationalisation of the State,” Capital and Class 43, pp. 43–63. Pogge, Thomas (1994) “Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty,” in Chris Brown (ed.), Political Restructuring in Europe. New York: Routledge, pp. 89–122. Polanyi, Karl (1944) The Great Transformation. Boston: Beacon Press. Polanyi, Karl, et al. (1957) Trade and Market in the Early Empires. Chicago: Henry Regnery. Popper, Karl (1961) The Poverty of Historicism. New York: Harper. Porter, Brian (1995) “David Davies and the Enforcement of Peace,” in David Long and Peter Wilson (eds.), Thinkers of the Twenty Years’ Crisis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 58–78. Postone, Moishe (1993) Time, Labor, and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marx’s Critical Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Postone, Moishe, and Barbara Brick (1993) “Critical Theory and Political Economy,” in Seyla Benhabib, Wolfgang Bonß, and John McCole (eds.), On Max Horkheimer: New Perspectives. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 215–256. Price, Richard, and Christian Reus-Smit (1998) “Dangerous Liaisons? Critical International Theory and Constructivism,” European Journal of International Relations 4(2), pp. 259–294. Prisching, M. (1989) “Evolution and Design of Social Institutions in Austrian Theory,” Journal of Economic Studies 16(2), pp. 47–62. Rabinow, P. (1986) The Foucault Reader. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Randall, Mercedes Moritz (1964) Improper Bostonian: Emily Greene Balch, Nobel Peace Laureate, 1946. New York: Twayne. Rapoport, Anatol (1962) Fights, Games and Debates. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. ——— (1964) “The Scientific Relevance of C. Wright Mills,” in Irving L. Horowitz (ed.), The New Sociology: Essays in Social Science and Social Theory in Honor of C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 94–107. ——— (1972) Conflict in Man-Made Environment. Harmondsworth: Penguin. ——— (1988) “A Possible Role for Universities in the Preservation of Peace,” in Janis Alton et al. (eds.), The Name of the Chamber Was Peace. Toronto: Samuel Stevens.
242
References
Ratner, Steven R. (1995) The New UN Peacekeeping. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Reich, Robert B. (1991) The Work of Nations: A Blueprint for the Future. London: Simon and Schuster. Reiss, Hans (ed.) (1970) Kant’s Political Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rengger, N. J. (1988) “Going Critical? A Response to Hoffman,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 17(1), pp. 81–89. ——— (1996) “Clio’s Cave? Historical Materialism and the Claims of Substantive Social Theory in World Politics,” Review of International Studies 22(2), pp. 213–231. ——— (1999) International Relations, Political Theory and the Problem of Order. London: Routledge. Rengger, Nick, and Mark Hoffman (1992) “Modernity, Postmodernism and International Relations,” in Joe Doherty, Elspeth Graham, and Mo Malek (eds.), Postmodernism and the Social Sciences. London: Macmillan, pp. 127–147. Report of the National Women’s Summit, Phnom Penh, March 5–8 (1993) Phnom Penh: UNIFEM. Resnick, P. (1992) “Isonomia, Isegoria and Isomoiria and Democracy at the International Level,” Praxis International 12(1), pp. 35–49. Riley, Patrick (1992) Leibniz Political Writings, revised and expanded. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1996) Leibniz’ Universal Jurisprudence: Justice as the Charity of the Wise. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996. Roderick, Rick (1986) Habermas and the Foundations of Critical Theory. Basingstoke: Macmillan. Rorty, Richard (1989) Contingency, Irony and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1991) Objectivity, Relativism and Truth: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rose, Gillian (1978) The Melancholy Science: An Introduction to the Thought of Theodor W. Adorno. London: Macmillan. ——— (1992) The Broken Middle. Oxford: Blackwell. Rosenau, James N. (1997) Along the Domestic-Foreign Frontier. New York: Cambridge University Press. Rosenau James N., and Ernst-Otto Czempiel (eds.) (1992) Governance Without Government: Order and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rosenberg, Justin (1991) “Review of Andrew Linklater’s Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations,” British Journal of Sociology 42(4), pp. 635–636. ——— (1994a) The Empire of Civil Society: A Critique of the Realist Theory of International Relations. London: Verso. ——— (1994b) “The International Imagination,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 23(1), pp. 85–108. ——— (1995) “Hobsbawm’s Century,” Monthly Review 47, pp. 139–157. ——— (1996) “Isaac Deutscher and the Lost History of International Relations,” New Left Review 215, pp. 3–15. Rosenberg, Justin, and Simon Bromley (1988) “After Exterminism,” New Left Review 168, pp. 66–94. Rothman, Jay (1992) From Confrontation to Cooperation. London: Sage.
References
243
Rouhana, Nadim N., and Herbert C. Kelman (1994) “Promoting Joint Thinking in International Conflicts: An Israeli-Palestinian Continuing Workshop (Constructive Conflict Management: An Answer to Critical Social Problems?),” Journal of Social Issues 50(1), pp. 157–179. Ruddick, Sara (1990) Maternal Thinking: Towards a Politics of Peace. London: Women’s Press. Runde, Jochen (1995) “Risk, Uncertainty and Keynesian Decision Theory: A Keynesian View,” in Sheila Dow and John Hillard (eds.), Keynes, Knowledge, and Uncertainty. Aldershot: Edward Elgar, pp. 197–210. Rupert, Mark (1995) Producing Hegemony: The Politics of Mass Production and American Global Power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Said, Edward (1979) The Question of Palestine. London: Vintage. ——— (1994) Culture and Imperialism. London: Chatto and Windus. ——— (1995) Peace and Its Discontents. London: Viking. Schelling, Thomas (1984) “Self-Command in Practice, in Policy, and in a Theory of Rational Choice,” American Economic Review 74 (Papers and Proceedings), pp. 1–11. Schmidt, Brian C. (1997) “Further Ahead or Further Behind? The Debate over Positivism,” Mershon International Studies Review 41(1), pp. 107–112. Schwarzenberger, Georg (1951) Power Politics: A Study of International Society, 2nd ed. London: Stevens. Scruton, Roger (1997) The Aesthetics of Music. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Setterfield, Mark (1995) “Historical Time and Economic Theory,” Review of Political Economy 7(1), pp. 1–27. Shapcott, Richard (1994) “Conversation and Coexistence: Gadamer and the Interpretation of International Society,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 23(1), pp. 57–83. Shapiro, Michael J. (1997) Violent Cartographies: Mapping Cultures of War. Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press. Sharoni, Simona (1995) Gender and the Israeli-Palestinian Conflict. New York: Syracuse University Press. Sinclair, Timothy J. (1994) “Passing Judgement: Credit Rating Processes as Regulatory Mechanisms of Governance in the Emerging World Order,” Review of International Political Economy 1(1), pp. 133–159. ——— (1997) “Global Governance and the International Political Economy of the Commonplace.” Paper presented to the Annual Conference of the International Studies Association, Toronto. Singer, David, and Melvin Small (1975) “War in History and the State of the World Message,” in William D. Coplin and Charles W. Kegley Jr. (eds.), Analyzing International Relations: A Multimethod Introduction. New York: Praeger. Smart, Barry (1985) Michel Foucault. London: Tavistock. Smith, Hazel (1996) “The Silence of the Academics: International Social Theory, Historical Materialism and Political Values,” Review of International Studies 22(2), pp. 191–212. Smith, Steve (1992) “The Forty Years Detour: The Resurgence of Normative Theory in International Relations,” Millennium: Journal of International Relations 21(3), pp. 489–506. ——— (1995) “Self Images of a Discipline: A Genealogy of International Relations,” in Ken Booth and Steve Smith (eds.), International Relations Theory Today. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 1–37. ——— (1996) “Positivism and Beyond,” in Steve Smith, Ken Booth, and Marysia
244
References
Zalewski (eds.), International Theory: Positivism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 11–44. Smith, Steve, Ken Booth, and Marysia Zalewski (eds.) (1996a) International Theory: Positivism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1996b) “Introduction,” in Steve Smith, Ken Booth, and Marysia Zalewski (eds.), International Theory: Positivism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–8. Sobel, Russell (1994) “The League of Nations Covenant and the United Nations Charter: An Analysis of Two International Constitutions,” Constitutional Political Economy 5(2), pp. 173–192. Soltan, Karol, and Stephen Elkin (eds.) (1996) The Constitution of Good Societies. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Spegele, Roger (1996) Political Realism in International Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stacey, Judith (1991) “Can There Be a Feminist Ethnography?” in Sherna Berger Gluck and Daphne Patai (eds.), Women’s Words: The Feminist Practice of Oral History. New York: Routledge, Chapman and Hall, pp. 111–119. Strange, Susan (1995) “ISA as a Microcosm,” International Studies Quarterly 39(3), pp. 289–295. Sugden, Robert (1993) “Thinking as a Team: Towards an Explanation for Non-selfish Behavior,” Social Philosophy and Policy 10(1), pp. 69–89. Sunstein, Cass (1988) “Beyond the Republican Revival,” Yale Law Journal 9(8), pp. 1539–1590. ——— (1991) “Preferences and Politics,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20(1), pp. 3–34. Swain, Jon (1992) “UN Losing Battle for Cambodia in the Brothels of Phnom Penh,” Sunday Times, December 27. Sylvester, Christine (1994) Feminist Theory and International Relations in a PostModern Era. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, C. (1985) “Connolly, Foucault and Truth,” Political Theory 13(3), pp. 377–385. Thayer, Nate, and Rodney Tasker (1993) “Voice of the People,” Far Eastern Economic Review, June 3, p. 10. Thompson, E. P. (1977) William Morris. London: Lawrence and Wishart. Thompson, K. (1979) “Morgenthau, Hans J.,” in Bibliographical Supplement: International Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences. New York: Free Press, pp. 544–548. Tickner, Ann (1991) “Hans Morgenthau’s Principles of Political Realism: A Feminist Reformulation,” in Rebecca Grant and Kathleen Newland (eds.), Gender and International Relations. Milton Keynes: Open University Press, pp. 27–40. ——— (1992) Gender in International Relations. New York: Columbia University Press. ——— (1997) “You Just Don’t Understand: Troubled Engagements Between Feminists and IR Theorists,” International Studies Quarterly 41(4), pp. 611–632. Tooze, Roger (1988) “The Unwritten Preface: ‘International Political Economy’ and Epistemology,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 17(3), pp. 285–294. Tooze, Roger, and Craig N. Murphy (1996) “The Epistemology of Poverty and the
References
245
Poverty of Epistemology in IPE: Mystery, Blindness and Invisibility,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 25(3), pp. 681–707. Tsuru, Shegeto (1993) Japan’s Capitalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Turner, Bryan S. (1993) Citizenship and Social Theory. London: Sage. Turner, Jonathan (1998) “Must Sociological Theory and Sociological Practice Be So Far Apart?: A Polemical Answer,” Sociological Perspectives 41, pp. 243–258. Ullmann-Margalit, Edna (1978) “Invisible-Hand Explanations,” Synthese 39, pp. 263–291. UNDP (1999) Human Development Report 1999. New York: Oxford University Press. Unger, Roberto Managebeira (1987) Politics in Three Volumes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. UNICEF (1995) The Trafficking and Prostitution of Children in Cambodia: A Situation Report. Phnom Penh: UNICEF. Urquidi, Victor (1992) Can the United Nations System Meet the Challenges of the World Economy? John W. Holmes Memorial Lecture, 1991. Providence: Academic Council on the UN System. Utting, Peter (ed.) (1994) Between Hope and Insecurity: The Social Consequences of the Cambodian Peace Process. Geneva: UNRISD. Vale, Peter (1995) “Engaging the World’s Marginalized and Promoting Global Change: The Challenges for the United Nations at Fifty,” Harvard International Law Journal 36(2), pp. 283–294. Vanberg, Viktor (1986) “Spontaneous Market Order and Social Rules,” Economics and Philosophy 2(1), pp. 75–100. ——— (1994a) Rules and Choice in Economics. London: Routledge. ——— (1994b) “Cultural Evolution, Collective Learning, and Constitutional Design,” in David Reisman (ed.), Economic Thought and Political Theory. Boston: Kluwer Academic, pp. 171–204. Van Dyke, Vernon (1977) “The Individual, the State, and Ethnic Communities in Political Theory,” World Politics 29(3), pp. 343–369. Vasquez, John A., and Marie T. Henehan (eds.) (1992) The Scientific Study of Peace and War. New York: Lexington Books. Vibert, Frank (1995) Europe: A Constitution for the Millennium. Aldershot: Dartmouth. Vico, Giambattista (1970) The New Science of Giambattista Vico, translated from the third edition by Thomas Goddard Bergin and Max Harold Fisch. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Vincent, R. J. (1986) Human Rights and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Walker, R.B.J. (1984) “East Wind, West Wind: Civilizations, Hegemonies and World Orders,” in R.B.J. Walker (ed.), Culture, Ideology, and World Orders. Boulder: Westview Press, pp. 2–22. ——— (1989) “History and Structure in the Theory of International Relations,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 18(2), pp. 163–183. ——— (1993) Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1994) “Review of Justin Rosenberg’s The Empire of Civil Society: A Critique of Realist Theory of International Relations,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 23(3), pp. 770–772.
246
References
——— (1999) “The Hierarchicalization of Political Community,” Review of International Studies 25(1), pp. 151–156. Wallace, W. (1994) “Rescue or Retreat? The Nation-State in Western Europe,” Political Studies 42(1), pp. 52–76. ——— (1996) “Truth and Power, Monks and Technocrats: Theory and Practice in International Relations,” Review of International Studies 22(3), pp. 301–321. Wallerstein, Immanuel (1974) The Modern World System, Vol. 1. New York: Academic Press. ——— (1979) The Capitalist World Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1980) The Modern World System, Vol. 2. New York: Academic Press. ——— (1989) The Modern World System, Vol. 3. New York: Academic Press. Walt, Stephen (1996) Revolution and War. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Waltz, Kenneth N. (1979) Theory of International Politics. New York; Random House. Walzer, Michael (1994) Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad. London: University of Notre Dame Press. Warren, Bill (1980) Imperialism: Pioneer of Capitalism. London: Verso. Weber, Cynthia (1994a) “Good Girls, Little Girls, and Bad Girls: Male Paranoia in Robert Keohane’s Critique of Feminist International Relations,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 23(2), pp. 337–349. ——— (1994b) “Something’s Missing: Male Hysteria and the U.S. Invasion of Panama,” Genders 19, pp. 171–197. ——— (1995) Simulating Sovereignty: Intervention, the State and Symbolic Exchange. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Weber, Max (1948) “Politics as a Vocation,” in H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (eds.), From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, pp. 77–128. Weiler, Joseph (1997) “The Reformation of European Constitutionalism,” Journal of Common Market Studies 35(1), pp. 97–130. Wellmer, Albrecht (1983) “Reason, Utopia, and the Dialectic of Enlightenment,” Praxis International 3(2), pp. 83–107. Wendt, Alexander (1987) “The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory,” International Organization 41(3), pp. 335–370. ——— (1992) “Anarchy Is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics,” International Organization 46(2), pp. 391–425. ——— (1994) “Collective Identity Formation and the International State,” American Political Science Review 88(2), pp. 384–396. ——— (1995) “Constructing International Politics,” International Security 20(2), pp. 71–81. ——— (1996) “Identity and Structural Change in International Politics,” in Yosef Lapid and Friedrich Kratochwil (eds.), The Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory. Boulder: Lynne Rienner, pp. 47–64. ——— (1999) Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. West, D. (1993) “The Contribution of Continental Philosophy,” in R. Goodin and P. Pettit (eds.), A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy. London: Blackwell, pp. 39–71. Whitworth, Sandra (1995) “Where Is the Politics in Peacekeeping?” International Journal 50(2), pp. 427–435.
References
247
——— (1998) “Gender, Race and the Politics of Peacekeeping,” in Edward MoxonBrowne (ed.), A Future for Peacekeeping? London: Macmillan, pp. 176–191. Wiggershaus, Rolf (1994) The Frankfurt School. Cambridge: Polity Press. Wight, M. (1977) System of States. Leicester: Leicester University Press. Wilke, Helmut (1992) “Societal Guidance Through Law?” in G. Teubner and A. Febbrajo (eds.), State, Law, and Economy as Autopoietic Systems. Milan: Giuffre, pp. 354–387. Williams, Raymond (1988) Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society. London: Fontana Press. Williams, William Appleman (1959) The Tragedy of American Diplomacy. New York: World. Witt, Ulrich (1994) “The Theory of Societal Evolution: Hayek’s Unfinished Legacy,” in J. Bimer and R. van Zijp (eds.), Hayek, Coordination, and Evolution. London: RKP, pp. 178–189. Wolf, Diane L. (1996) “Situating Feminist Dilemmas in Fieldwork,” in Diane L. Wolf (ed.), Feminist Dilemmas in Fieldwork. Boulder: Westview Press, pp. 1–55. Wolf, Margery (1996) “Afterword: Musings from an Old Gray Wolf,” in Diane L. Wolf (ed.), Feminist Dilemmas in Fieldwork. Boulder: Westview Press, pp. 215–221. Wright, Erik Olin (1997) Class Counts: Comparative Studies in Class Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wyn Jones, Richard (1999) Security, Strategy and Critical Theory. Boulder: Lynne Rienner. ——— (Forthcoming) “Emancipation: On Necessity, Capacity and Concrete Utopias,” in Ken Booth (ed.), An Introduction to Critical Security Studies: Security, Community and Emancipation. Boulder: Lynne Rienner. Young, Iris (1989) “Polity and Group Difference,” Ethics 99(2), pp. 250–274. Young, Oran (1994) International Governance. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Zehfuss, Maja (1997) “Constructivisms in International Relations: The Approaches of Wendt, Onuf and Kratochwil,” in Knud Erik Jørgensen (ed.), The AarhusNorsminde Papers: Constructivism, International Relations and European Studies. Aarhus: Aarhus University, pp. 151–167. Zimmerman, Cathy, Sar Samen, and Men Savorn (1994) Plates in a Basket Will Rattle: Domestic Violence in Cambodia. Phnom Penh: Asia Foundation. Zuidervaart, Lambert (1991) Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory: The Redemption of Illusion. Cambridge: MIT Press.
The Contributors
Kenneth Baynes is associate professor of philosophy at the State University of New York at Stony Brook. He is author of The Normative Grounds of Social Criticism: Kant, Rawls, and Habermas and coeditor, with James Bohman and Thomas McCarthy, of After Philosophy: End or Transformation? His latest work, Discourse and Democracy: Essays on Habermas’s “Between Facts and Norms,” coedited with Rene von Schomberg, is forthcoming. He has also translated several key texts in contemporary critical theory, including Axel Honneth’s The Critique of Power. Chris Brown is the author of International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches and Understanding International Relations, and some two dozen papers in the 1990s on various aspects of contemporary international political theory. He is past chair of the British International Studies Association and, after holding posts at the Universities of Kent and Southampton, is now professor of international relations at the London School of Economics. Robert W. Cox is professor emeritus of political science at York University, Toronto. He is author of Production, Power, and World Order: Social Forces in the Making of History and a collection of essays prepared with Timothy J. Sinclair, Approaches to World Order. Jeffrey Harrod is currently senior research fellow at the Research Centre for International Political Economy, University of Amsterdam. He is professor emeritus from the Institute of Social Studies in The Hague, Netherlands. Among his publications are Power, Production and the 249
250
The Contributors
Unprotected Worker; Industrialisation and Labour Relations; and “Social Forces and International Political Economy: Joining the Two IRs,” in Stephen Gill and James H. Mittleman (eds.), Innovation and Transformation in International Studies. Kimberly Hutchings is senior lecturer in politics at the University of Edinburgh. She is author of Kant, Critique and Politics; International Political Theory; and Cosmopolitan Citizenship (coedited with Roland Dannreuther). She is currently writing a book on Hegel and feminist philosophy. Deiniol Lloyd Jones is lecturer in international studies at the University of Leeds. His research interests center on the third-party initiatives in processes of conflict resolution and questions of cosmopolitan international theory. He is the author of Cosmopolitan Mediation? Conflict Resolution and the Oslo Accords, and articles on political theory and international conflict, and he is winner of the Lord Bryze Prize for Comparative and International Politics. Currently, he is writing a book on ethics and the individual in postconflict societies. Andrew Linklater is the Woodrow Wilson Professor of International Politics at the University of Wales, Aberystwyth. His latest books are The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the PostWestphalian Era and Theories of International Relations. Craig N. Murphy is M. Margaret Ball Professor of International Relations at Wellesley College and president of the International Studies Association. His teaching and research interests include international political economy, North-South relations, and international organization. He is editor of the journal Global Governance. Mark Neufeld teaches in the Department of Political Studies at Trent University in Peterborough, Canada. He is the author of The Restructuring of International Relations Theory and has published articles in Millennium, Review of International Studies, and Global Society. He is presently completing a book on globalization. N. J. Rengger is professor in international relations at the University of St. Andrews. He is author of International Relations, Political Theory and the Problem of Order and Political Theory, Modernity and Postmodernity: Beyond Enlightenment and Critique.
The Contributors
251
Alexander Wendt is associate professor of political science at the University of Chicago. He has taught previously at Yale University and Dartmouth College. He is the author of several articles on international relations theory as well as the recently published book Social Theory of International Politics. Sandra Whitworth is associate professor of political science and women’s studies at York University in Toronto, Canada, and research associate at the Centre for International and Security Studies, York University. She is author of a number of journal articles and book chapters, as well as Feminism and International Relations. Currently, she is writing a book on gender, race, and the politics of peacekeeping for the Lynne Rienner Critical Security Studies series. Richard Wyn Jones is senior lecturer in the Department of International Politics at the University of Wales, Aberystwyth. He is author of Security, Strategy and Critical Theory and editor of the journal Contemporary Wales. He is currently writing a book on Welsh nationalism.
Index
Aberystwyth. See University of Wales, Aberystwyth abuse, sexual, 154. See also prostitution Adorno, Theodor, 4, 5, 7, 8, 9, 11, 14–15, 23, 94–96, 99, 100–102, 104, 105, 128, 202–203 agency, 55–59, 171, 173, 180–183, 196, 211, 213, 219. See also agentstructure problem agent-structure problem, 208–213. See also agency AIDS, 154–155 Akashi, Yasushi, 155 Alker, Hayward, 68 Amin, Samir, 93 Anderson, Perry, 194 Angell, Norman, 64, 65 Annan, Kofi, 50 Apel, Karl-Otto, 5, 30, 41 Arafat, Yasir, 181 Armstrong, Louis, 203 Aron, Raymond, 37 Ashley, Richard, 80, 83 Bakhtin, Mikhail, 28 Bakunin, Mikhail, 26 Banks, Michael, 176 Baran, Paul, 195 Barber, Benjamin, 161, 162 Bartleson, Jens, 80, 82 Baudrillard, Jean, 141
Beitz, Charles, 99, 161 Benhabib, Seyla, 28, Benjamin, Walter, 5, 9, 94, 128 Bernstein, Jay, 100–102, 105 Bhaskar, Roy, 132 biosphere, 51–52. See also environmental degradation Blair, Tony, 55. See also New Labour Party Bloch, Ernst, 96 Booth, Ken, 7–8, 96 Boulding, Elise, 68, 69 Boulding, Kenneth, 68 Boutros-Ghali, Boutros, 50, 152, 155 Brailsford, Henry, 193 Bronner, Stephen Eric, 7, Brown, Chris, 10 Buchanan, James, 223 Bull, Hedley, 40, 168 Bush, George, 52 Buzan, Barry, 115, 174 Cambodia, 151–157 Campbell, David, 199 Camp David agreements, 174. See also Israeli-Palestinian dispute; Palestine Liberation Organization (PLO) Canada, 57 capitalism, forms of, 54 Carr, E. H., 46–47, 61, 66, 72, 114 Chase-Dunn, Christopher, 93
253
254
Index
Checkel, Jeffrey, 12 Cheysson, Claude, 48 China, 55; ancient, 34 Chomsky, Noam, 67, 173 citizenship, 34–35, 38–41 civilization, 53 civil society, 52, 57, 59, 164, 165, 169, 205, 221; global, 39, 161, 169, 214–215, 221. See also public sphere class, concept of, 49, 137 Cold War, 46, 68, 69 communicative action, theory of, 98, 172, 198. See also Habermas Communist International, 193 conflict resolution, 172–175, 185 Connolly, William, 199 constructivism, vii, 3, 4, 10, 12–15, 16, 93, 98, 103, 108, 131–134, 196, 202, 223 consumerism, 52, 53, 161 corporate elites, 122. See also transnational corporations (TNCs) cosmopolitanism, 92, 109, 166, 180, 184, 185, 215. See also democracy, cosmopolitan counterhegemony, 56, 57, 59 covert world, 56–57 Cox, Robert W., 2, 5, 14, 18, 37, 63, 70, 80, 81–85, 96, 120, 122, 150, 192, 195, 205 critical social theory, 6, 9, 24, 35, Curle, Adam, 73, 74 Curtis, Grant, 155 Darwin, Charles, 197 Davidson, Paul, 217 Dialectic of Enlightenment, 7, 95, 194 de Certeau, Michel, 104–106 deliberative politics, 163–165 Delors, Jacques, 57 democracy: cosmopolitan, 39, 169, 195; deficit, 214; procedural, 162–163, 169; theory of, 18 Der Derian, James, 80, 82, 199 Derrida, Jacques, 11, 24, 40, 80 de St. Pierre, Abbe, 91 Deutsch, Karl 68 Devetak, Richard, 98, 99 Dilthey, Wilhelm, 116 discourse ethics, 98–99, 198. See also Habermas
Dulles, John Foster, 68 Durkheim, Émile, 104 Earth Summit, 52 economics, 115, 118, 194, 217, 223; rethinking, 52. See also hyperliberalism; international political economy; market mentality; neoliberalism Egeland, Jan, 184 Ellington, Duke, 203 Elshtain, Jean, 80, 84 emancipation, 3, 9, 10, 11, 13, 14, 15, 16, 19, 30, 70, 84, 89, 92, 98, 99, 131, 133–134, 151, 197, 205, 208, 212 emancipatory: change, 6–7, 23; potential, 18, 139, 200–201; project, 24, 26, 43, 83, 92, 100–106, 194; theory, 96, 206 English School, 43 Enlightenment, the, 24, 25, 45, 92, 98, 104, 138, 178, 194, 197, 200, 201, 210 Enloe, Cynthia, 69, 80, 84, 150–151, 156 environmental degradation, 51, 125. See also biosphere episteme, 130, 132, 133 equal rights, 28 EU. See European Union Eurocentrism, vii, 197, 198 European Union (EU), 167, 186, 207, 210, 213, 214, 223 facilitation, 175–178, 179; Norwegian, 183–184 Falk, Richard, 92, 161, 162 feminism, 25, 26, 28, 34, 53, 70, 71, 79, 80, 83–85, 89, 93, 96, 121, 132, 137, 138, 141–143, 149–159 fieldwork, 156–157. See also research Fishkin, James, 163 Follet, Mary Parker, 67 Foreign Affairs, journal of, 69 foreign policy, critical analysis of, 42, 43 Foucault, Michel, 11, 24, 28, 80, 83, 140, 141 Frankfurt School, 4, 5, 6, 7, 9, 23, 25, 32, 79, 80, 93–97, 127, 129, 137,
Index 138, 191, 194–200, 202, 208; early, 14; influences on, 34 Fraser, Nancy, 17, 32, 144, 164, 165 Freud, Sigmund, 94, 104 Friere, Paulo, 93 Fromm, Eric, 5, 94, 95 Frost, Mervyn, 137 G7. See Group of Seven Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 28, 176 Galtung, Johan, 68 Gershwin, George, 203 Giddens, Anthony, 32, 132 Gill, Stephen, 96 globalization, 47–49, 52, 58, 122, 127, 161, 167, 168; of production, 48 Gramsci, Antonio, 5, 6, 9, 75, 129, 195, 201. See also Gramscian tradition; neo-Gramscian approach Gramscian tradition, 8, 11, 15, 17, 93, 137. See also Gramsci, Antonio; neo-Gramscian approach Grant, Rebecca, 80 Greece, ancient, 33, 34 Greene Balch, Emily, 63, 65, 66, 70, 75 Green Movement, 55 Grotius, Hugo, 91 Group of Seven (G7), 50, 56, 213 Gunder Frank, André, 93 Habermas, Jürgen, 3, 5, 7, 8, 9, 11, 14, 17, 18, 24, 27, 28, 29, 30, 32, 40, 41, 62, 68, 80, 82, 85, 96, 97, 101, 103, 106, 108, 161, 162–166, 169, 170, 176–179, 180, 183, 186, 194, 198, 199, 201. See also communicative action; discourse ethics Halliday, Fred, 93 Hampson, F. O., 179, 180 Harding, Sandra, 141 Harrington, Michael, 67 Harrington, Mona, 71 Harrod, Jeffrey, 5 Hayek, Friedrich, 208, 223 Held, David, 99, 161, 166–169, 178, 180, 195 Hegel, G. W. F., 2, 24, 34, 94, 104 Hegelian-Marxist tradition, 5, 9, hegemony, 56, 57 Heine, Christian, 196 Heiner, Ronald, 219
255
Hilferding, Rudolf, 193 Hindu nationalists, 201 historical materialism, 18, 24, 97, 134, 135, 137, 200 historicism, 81, 89 Hobbesian tradition, 46, 218 Hobsbawm, Eric, 59 Hobson, John A., 61, 62, 64, 66, 70, 72, 193, 194 Hoffman, Mark, 3, 7, 10, 73, 96, 99, 108, 176 Hoffmann, Stanley, 71 Holsti, Ole, 68 Honneth, Axel, 5, 18, 194 Hopf, Ted, 3, 12 Horkheimer, Max, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 14, 17, 94, 95, 131, 144, 197 human rights, 38, 50, 161, 206, 212, 215 Hurst, Paul, 196 Husseini, Faisal, 185 Hutton, Will, 196 hyperliberalism, 48, 54. See also neoliberalism IMF. See International Monetary Fund immanent critique, 88 immutability thesis, 25, 174 imperialism, 64, 65, 72, 118, 200 India, 201 inequality, global, 74 International Monetary Fund (IMF), 50, 56, 192, 196 international political economy, 2, 15, 72, 93, 120, 123, 192; critical, 195, 196. See also economics international society, 33, 34, 36, 42, 98, 103, 113, 118, 215; Hellenic, 33, 36 international system, 49–51, 91, 92, 97, 174 intersubjectivity, 52–55 intervention, discourse on, 140 Islam, 55, 201 Israeli-Palestinian dispute, 175–177, 181–186. See also Camp David agreements; Palestine Liberation Organization (PLO) Jackson, Robert H., 76 James, Alan, 151 Japan, 57
256
Index
Jay, Martin, 9 Jennar, Raoul, 154 Jospin, Lionel, 55 Kaplan, Caren, 152, 159 Kant, Immanuel, 34, 37, 79, 91–92, 104, 116, 195, 197 Kantian tradition, 5, 38–41, 86–87, 166, 178 Karsh, Efraim, 182 Kellog-Briand Pact (1928), 114 Kennan, George, 67 Keohane, Robert, 3, 31, 69, 108, 141–142, 149 Keynes, John-Maynard, 194, 217 Khmer Rouge, 153–154 Kissinger, Henry, 69, 174 Korea, war, 120 Korsch, Karl, 94 Kratochwil, Friedrich, 12, 14, 202 labor, concept of, 18 land mines, 206 League of Nations, 65, 66, 72, 120, 210 Ledgerwood, Julie, 154 Lenin, Vladimir Illich, 195, 198, 201 Liebnitz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 91 Linklater, Andrew, 2, 3, 4, 5, 8, 10, 11, 13, 18, 80, 82–85, 93, 97, 98, 99, 102–103, 106, 108, 174, 178, 180, 195, 198, 206 Lippmann, Walter, 67 Lowenthal, Leo, 94 Luhmann, Niklas, 211 Lukács, Georg, 94 Luxemburg, Rosa, 193 Lyotard, Jean-François, 11, 28, 29, 41 Machiavelli, Niccoló, 113. See also Machiavellian Machiavellian, 37. See also Machiavelli, Niccoló Madeuf, Bernadette, 47 MAI. See Multilateral Agreement on Investment Mann, Michael, 32 Mannheim, Karl, 113 Marcuse, Herbert, 5, 94, 95, 127, 194 market mentality, 51–52, 124. See also economics; hyperliberalism;
international political economy; neoliberalism Marx, Karl, 34, 92, 94, 104, 192–196, 197, 199, 200, 201. See also Marxism Marxism, 8, 23, 25, 26, 27, 30–31, 37, 42, 43, 49, 53, 79, 80, 81, 97, 104, 129, 132, 134, 135, 137, 145, 178, 196, 221. See also Marx, Karl Mazen, Abu, 183 McCarthy, Thomas, 127 mediation, 171–175, 178–181, 182, 184, 185, 186 Mexico, 57–58. See also Zapatista rebellion Methuen, treaty of, 116 Metz, Johann Baptist, 93 Michalet, Charles-Albert, 47 Mill, John Stuart, 196 Mills, C. Wright, 134, 135, 136, 138 Mitchell, Chris, 176 Mitrany, David, 67 Mohanty, Chandra, 152 Moltmann, Jürgen, 93 Moon, Donald, 170 Morgenthau, Hans J., 111, 112–114, 117–121, 125 Morris, William, 191, 192, 193, 196, 199, 200, 201 Multilateral Agreement on Investment (MAI), 50 Murphy, Craig, N., 1, 16, 191 NAFTA. See North American Free Trade Agreement NATO. See North Atlantic Treaty Organization nébuleuse, 56 Nehru, Jawaharlal, 67 Nelson, Benjamin, 29, 32 neo-Gramscian approach, 31, 70, 80, 85. See also Gramsci, Antonio; Gramscian tradition neoliberalism, 17, 49, 50, 53, 72, 76, 123, 192, 196. See also economics; hyperliberalism; international political economy; market mentality neorealism, 23, 25, 32, 42, 45, 46, 47, 66, 67, 76, 80, 81, 83, 88, 112–120, 133, 180–181, 192, 206
Index Neufeld, Mark, 7, 8, 10, 149, 150, 198, 224 New Deal, Roosevelt’s, 194 New Labour Party (UK), 201. See also Blair, Tony Newland, Kathleen, 80 Niebuhr, Reinhold, 61, 66, 67 nihilism, 100–102 Nixon, Richard, 69 normative theory, 1, 2, 5, 161 North, Robert, 68 North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA), 57–58 North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO), 167, 207 Nove, Alec, 196 Ong, Aihwa, 152 ontology, 45–46, 59 Onuf, Nicholas, 14 Orwell, George, 173 Oslo peace process, 175–178, 181–185 Palestine Liberation Organization (PLO), 175, 181, 185. See also Camp David agreements; IsraeliPalestinian dispute Paris Peace Agreement (1991), 153 Pati, Daphne, 158 peace research, 68, 72–73 Peres, Shimon, 182 Perkin, Harold James, 123 Peterson, V. Spike, 80, 84 Plato, 103–105 PLO. See Palestine Liberation Organization Pogge, Thomas, 161, 168, 169 Polanyi, Karl, 51, 54, 66 Popper, Karl, 116 Porter, Cole, 203 positivism, 1, 2, 3, 14, 15, 70, 71, 81, 83, 84, 97, 115, 116, 130, 132, 135, 136, 138–139, 150, 157, 173, 198, 205–208, 212, 214, 215, 219–221 post-Fordism, 48 post-Marxist approach, 25, 27, 30 postmodernism. See poststructuralism Postone, Moishe, 18 postpositivism, vii, 12, 31, 32, 40, 97, 106, 171, 223; problems of, 36–37 poststructuralism, vii, 3, 4, 10–12, 15,
257
16, 23–24, 25, 26, 31, 34, 59, 74, 79, 80, 82–85, 93, 106, 132, 137, 138, 141, 143, 178, 198, 201, 208 praxeology, 36–42, 222 Price, Richard, 12–14, 15, 16, 224 prostitution, 153–154. See also abuse, sexual public sphere, 164–165, 170, 215; transnational, 213. See also civil society Pufendorf, Samuel, 91 Rabin, Yitzshak, 172, 181 rape, 154 Rapoport, Anatol, 68, 72, 73 rationality, 11, 120–125, 130, 201, 207, 211, 212, 216, 218–219, 221 Ratner, Steven, 151 realism. See neorealism Reich, Robert, 123 Rengger, N. J., 4, 10 research, 149–160, 198 Reus-Smit, Christian, 12–14, 15, 16, 224 Rhodes, Cecil, 63 Ricardo, David, 116 Rorty, Richard, 28, 29 Rose, Gilian, 105 Rosenau, James, 161, 162 Rosenberg, Justin, 93, 131, 134–139, 141, 145, 191 Ruggie, John Gerard, 12 Russell, Bertrand, 113 Russett, Bruce, 68 Russia, 55. See also Soviet bloc, former Said, Edward, 93, 174, 177 Sakamoto, Yoshikazu, 57 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 113 Schumpeter, Joseph, 113, 118 Schwarzenberger, Georg, 111, 112–115, 117–120 scientific-objectivism, 1, 2 Scruton, Roger, 202 security studies, 2, 31, 96 Shapiro, Michael, 199 Sharoni, Simona, 157 Shawcross, William, 152 Singer, J. David, 68, 69 Small, Melvin, 68, 69 Smith, Steve, 71, 149, 150
258
Index
socialism, scientific, 194 Socialist International, 193 social movements, 57, 58, 61, 70, 73, 74, 89–90 society, European, 34 Socrates, 105 South Africa, 223 sovereignty, 88, 140, 143, 162, 165, 166–170 Soviet bloc, former, 223. See also Russia Stacey, Judith, 157 state: concept of, 139–140; personification of, 117, 120 Strange, Susan, 74 Sunstein, Cass, 162 Sylvester, Christine, 80, 199 Taylor, Charles, 31 telecommunications technology, 169 Teschke, Benno, 196 Thatcher, Margaret, 57. See also Thatcherism Thatcherism, 55. See also Thatcher, Margaret Tickner, Ann, 80, 96, 141–142 Töennies, Ferdinand, 114 Tooze, Roger, 72 TNCs. See transnational corporations transnational corporations (TNCs), 48, 111–112, 123, 167. See also corporate elites Trilateral Commission, 50, 56 truth, concept of, 62, 68, 71, 81, 130, 132, 135, 141, 197–199, 202, 221 UN. See United Nations United Nations (UN), 50, 51, 119, 120, 166, 168, 172, 185, 207, 210; peacekeeping, 149, 151–157 UNDP. See United Nations Development Programme Unger, Roberto Managebeira, 93 UNIFEM. See United Nations Development Fund for Women United Nations Development Fund for Women (UNIFEM), 152
United Nations Development Programme, 74 United Nations Transitional Authority in Cambodia (UNTAC), 151–157, 160 United States, 57, 64, 67, 186, 207, 209; imperialism, 65 universalism, ethical, 26–27, 30, 43 University of Wales, Aberystwyth, viii, 46, 65 UNTAC. See United Nations Transitional Authority in Cambodia Urquidi, Victor, 72 Vale, Peter, 71–72 Verfassungspatriotismus, 162 Vietnam, war, 120 von Vattel, Emmerich, 91 Wales, 17 Walker, R.B.J., 11, 80, 83 Wallerstein, Immanuel, 93 Waltz, Kenneth, 2, 69 Walzer, Michael, 30 Warren, Bill, 195 Webb, Beatrice, 197 Webb, Sydney, 197 Weber, Cynthia, 131, 139–143, 145, 191 Weber, Max, 37, 53, 58, 104, 113 Wellesley College, 63 Wellmer, Albrecht, 5 Wendt, Alexander, 12–13, 14, 131–134, 135, 141, 149, 191, 202 WHO. See World Health Organization Wight, Martin, 92 Williams, Raymond, 171 Wilson, Woodrow, 65 Wolf, Margery, 158 World Bank, 50 World Economic Forum, 50, 56 World Health Organization (WHO), 154 World Trade Organization (WTO), 50, 207, 213 Wright, Eric Olin, 123 WTO. See World Trade Organization Zaire, 58 Zapatista rebellion, 57. See also Mexico Zimbabwe, 201
About the Book
This book represents the first attempt to bring together the leading critical theorists of world politics to discuss both the promise and the pitfalls of their work. The authors range broadly across the terrain of world politics, engaging with both theory and emancipatory practice. Critiques by two scholars from other IR traditions are also included. The result is a seminal statement of the critical theory approach to understanding world politics, an essential point of reference for future work in the field. Richard Wyn Jones is senior lecturer in international politics at the University of Wales, Aberystwyth. He is author of Security, Strategy, and Critical Theory.
259