Nominalism, Empiricism and Universals-I

  • 100 17 1
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up

Nominalism, Empiricism and Universals-I

Nominalism, Empiricism and Universals--I Arthur Pap The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 9, No. 37. (Oct., 1959), pp. 330-3

1,021 15 293KB

Pages 12 Page size 595 x 792 pts Year 2007

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD FILE

Recommend Papers

File loading please wait...
Citation preview

Nominalism, Empiricism and Universals--I Arthur Pap The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 9, No. 37. (Oct., 1959), pp. 330-340. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8094%28195910%299%3A37%3C330%3ANEAU%3E2.0.CO%3B2-I The Philosophical Quarterly is currently published by The Philosophical Quarterly.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/philquar.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

http://www.jstor.org Sat May 12 00:17:58 2007

XOMINALISM, EMPIRICISM AND UNIVERSALS-I I t is a curious paradox that the empiricist principle that only what is, directly or indirectly, observable in some sense can meaningfully be said to exist, has been used in support of both nominalism and realism. Nominalists have repudiated universals as " fictions " or " abstractions ", accusing realists who believed in the real existence of universals of a crude misinterpretation of the generality of language. Only particulars exist, said the British empiricists, and from the fact that several particulars resemble each other i t does not follow that there exists a further entity which is somehow present in all of them. But what is a particular ? The very same nominalist Berkeley who argued acutely against " abstract ideas ", i.e. ideas of universals, rejected the notion of a substratum which somehow carries what we call the qualities " o f " the thing as literally meaningless. Accordingly particulars turned for Berkeley into what Russell has metaphorically called " bundles of qualities ". Yet, is i t not logically possible for any given complex of qualities to be repeated ? If so, has not the particular been transformed into a universal through the very empiricist distrust of abstractions that led Berkeley to poke fun a t the notion of an unobservable " support " of observable qualities ? Our problem may be stated as follows : how can ure reconcile the dismissal of substrata with (a) the very notion of unique, unrepeatable particulars, (b) the nominalists' denial of the existence of universals ? This old problem, which I have deliberately formulated in more or less traditional terms in order t o make i t recognizable as a time-honoured (or time-dishonoured) problem of metaphysics, will forthwith be discussed in the far more precise terminology of analytic philosophy. Since analytic philosophy is widely reputed to aim a t a dissolution of insoluble pseudoproblems of traditional metaphysics, it will be appropriate to begin by raising the logical positivist's question : is there a genuine question ? Specifically, is there more than a verbal issue between the nominalists who deny that there are universals and the realists who affirm that there are ?

I. VAGUENESS A ND RUSSELL'SEARLYARGUMENT AGAINSTNOMINALISM Is there any difference in meaning between (a) ' x colour-resembles y ' and (b) ' x has the same colour as y ' ? Or, to be more specific, is there any difference in meaning between (a') ' x red-resembles y ' and (b') ' x and y both have the attribute of being red ' ? Admittedly, ordinary English does not contain such specific resemblance predicates as ' red-resembles ' ; one speaks of two objects resembling each other in a determinable respect (colour, shape, size, weight, etc.) and uses the predicative idiom when specify-

NOMINALISM, EMPIRICISM AND UNIVERSALS

33 1

ing the determinate form of the resemblance. But let us assume that ordinary English had been reformed by nominalists who insist that we find in the world resemblances, not qualities, and t h a t a philosophically adequate language ought t o reflect this feature of the world. If a and b are blue patches, and c and d are red patches, then both pairs (a, b) and (c, d) exhibit colour resemblance, but a bears a more specific resemblance to b which differs from the more specific resemblance t h a t c bears t o d. And for such more specSc resemblances a nominalist might invent the terms ' red-resembles ', ' blue-resembles ', etc. Now, reliance on a superficial version of the positivistic ' principle of verification ' may lead one to suspect that there is merely a verbal difference between (a') and (b') ; for, surely i t would be impossible to verify by inspection of x and y that one of these sentences about x and y is true and the other false. However, the claim that they are synonymous is initially unplausible because (a') ascribes a symmetrical relation to the pair consisting of x and y, whereas (6') invokes a third entity t o which x and y bear the asymmetrical relation ' being an instance of '. But secondly, apart from considerations of conceptual economy, we can prove that the two sentences are not logically equivalent because qualitative resemblance relations are not transitive whereas identity is, of course, transitive. Thus, imagine a series of red patches continuously verging toward orange in such a way that any two neighbouring patches red-resemble each other but a clear colour difference emerges between the first and last member of the series. This is a situation of the form : aRb. bRc. . . . . yRz. not -(aRz). But if the same perceptual facts were described in the realistic language, the description would involve the contradiction that the same patch both has and does not have the attribute Red. For the realist infers from ' a redresembles b ' a conjunction of subject-predicate statements ' a is red and b is red ' where the two tokens of ' red ' are supposed to designate the same quality. The nominalistic language of resemblance, therefore, seems to be more suitable for the description of perceptual experience. It is not just a personal dislike of a certain way of speaking that motivates the nominalist t o deny that a meaningful descriptive predicate designates (or ' connotes ', in the language of Mill) a universal. For if the predicate is vague in the sense t h a t the positive instances are not sharply demarcated from the negative instances, then the realistic way of speaking can actually lead to contradiction. I n The Problems of Philosophy (chap. 9) Russell argued that a radical nominalism is inconsistent since a t least ,one relational universal must be admitted : resemblance itself. Now, the nominalist certainly need not admit that universal. H e may say t h a t ' x resembles y ' does not mean anything t h a t is empirically verifiable, unlike ' x colour-resembles y ', ' x pitch-resembles y ', ' x shape-resembles y ?, etc. Indeed, ' x resembles y ' would seem to be, not a descriptive statement verifiable by perception or some other mode of experience, but just the abstract statement ' x and y have a t least one property in common ' which begs the question raised by

332

ARTHUR PAP

the nominalist. Nevertheless, Russell was right in arguing t h a t the nominalists' argument against the admission of qualities as universals has no force against relational universals. Formally, i t seems, a radically nominalistic language equipped with specific resemblance predicates instead of monadic qualitative predicates could still be constructed, Russell's argument notwithstanding, by distinguishing levels of resemblance. Instead of admitting that the pairs (x, y) and (y, z) are a t any rate instances of an identical universal, call it ' red-resemblance ', we might say that they in turn stand in a relation of ' R-resemblance '. And instead of admitting that some pairs of pairs of particulars are instances of R-resemblance, we might say that they stand in a relation of R2-resemblance, and so oil. But there is no motive for such an enforcement of the language of resemblance except the unworthy one of winning an argument. For we would have to explain these resemblance predicates of higher levels in such a way that the argument from vagueness against the realistic way of speaking 7%-ouldbreak down. Colour resemblance, shape resemblance, etc., are relations that can be directly perceived, hence the predicates designating them are ostensively definable. But even if it be held that R-resemblance in turn can be directly perceived, the analogous claim for R2-resemblance already becomes highly unplausible. At any rate there is some value of n such that the meaning of Ru-resemblance, as well as of all higher resemblance predicates, can be explained only by the definition : (x, y)Rn(y, z) = xRU-ly. yRu-lz. But according to this definition, which involves the admission of RW1as a genuine relational universal, R" is demonstrably transitive. This shows that the nominalists' argument against universals from the vagueness of descriptive predicates (a feature of language which, of course, is due to the nature of the designated qualities, i.e. their being members of continuous series) cannot be indefinitely repeated on the higher levels. Besides, this very argument could not even be stated 7%-ithoutassuming relational universals : to say that R is not transitive is to assert the possibility of x R y and yRz and not-(xRz), hence the possibility of two pairs being instances of the same relation is already admitted (and the moment values of ' x ', ' y ' and ' z ' are specified which satisfy the conjunction, the possibility is asserted to be actual).

I n contemporary discussions of the problem of universals a distinction has been drawn between ' x is red ' and ' x has the attribute (quality) Redness '. Predicates, the contemporary nominalists contend, are not names a t all, hence it is illegitimate to pass from ' x is red ' to ' there is an attribute, redness, which x exemplifies (instantiates) '. And i t must be conceded that in rejecting such existential inferences modern nominalists are not committed to the untenable resemblance theory according to which a statement of the form ' x is red ' is synonymous with a statement of the form ' x redresembles y '. That no resemblance is asserted by ' x is red ', has been pointed

NOR;IINALISM, EMPIRICISM AND UNIVERSALS

333

out by Ayer, in the context of a recent discussion of basic propositions1 : it is logically possible that there should exist only one red particular, but a resemblance statement could not be true unless a t least tm-o particulars existed. To be sure, i t would be very difficult for a colour predicate to acquire if a meaning if only one particular to mhich it is applicable existed-and the particulars in question are transient sense-impressions this may even be impossible. But the question how a sentence acquired its present significance should not be confused with the question what its present significance is. I t may well be that the statement ' ' red ' is a simple, ostensively defined descriptive predicate ' entails ' there are, a t some time, a t least two red particulars ' ; yet it 7%-ouldnot be self-contradictory t o suppose that there existed only one red particular, or indeed no red particular a t all. Let us, therefore, separate nominalism from the resemblance theory considered in I , and take i t to assert that predicates are syncategorematic, not names of universals ; that i t is legitimate to infer from a true statement of the form ' x is f ' that there is a particular x such that x is f, but illegitimate to infer from the same statement that there is a universal, f-ness, such that x is an instance of it. This modest minimum of nominalism is justifiable in terms of Occam's razor. Indeed, if we had no better reason for saying that there are universals than the argument ' there are meaningful predicates, but in order for a predicate to be meaningful there must be an entity which is its meaning ; and if that entity were a particular, the predicate would be a proper name, not a predicate ; so the meaning of a predicate must be a universal ', then realism would be just a metaphysical creed bred by a naive theory of meaning. The verb ' to mean ' is syntactically transitive because we can talk of meant meanings. But so is ' to dream ', since we can properly say ' I dreamt a lovely dream ', yet i t would be queer to suppose that there might be dreams which are not dreamt by anybody (or any mind). Yet, while one who is satisfied with the subject-predicate form as irreducible to something more intelligible can say ' this apple is red ' without admitting that there is such a thing as redness, can he really justify his ontological abstinence by showing that any apparent name of a universal can be contextually eliminated ? The modern nominalists are committed to this daring thesis,2 but a good empiricist, I contend, ought t o reject i t on inductive grounds. I n the following, I shall discuss a small sample of descriptive statements that refer irreducibly t o universals and are intelligible to everybody except philosophers with a nominalistic prejudice. 1" Basic Propositions ", in Philosophical Analysis ed. &I. Black (Ithaca, 1950) ; reprinted in A. J. Ayer, Philosophical Essays (London 1953). I t seems to me that H. H. Price's analysis of ' x is red ' as meaning ' x resembles specified standard objects as closely as they resemble one another ' ( T h i n k i n g and Experience, pp. 20-21) is clearly open to Ayer's objection (among others).

%Fora precise formulation of what is here called ' modern nominalism ' see W. V. Quine's paper " Designation and Existence ", reprinted in H. Feigl and W. Sellsrs, Readings in Philosophical Analysis (New York, 1949).

334

ARTHUR PAP

(a) Red resembles Orange more than Blue.-Clearly this does not mean the same as ' for any x, y, z : if x is red and y is orange and z is blue, then x resembles y more than z ', for x may resemble z more than y in other respects though x is red and y orange and z blue. The nominalist will reply that the translation can easily be corrected by replacing ' resembles ' with ' resemblesin-colour '. A triadic second-level-predicate is thus reduced to a triadic predicate of the earthy first level. But the realistic way of speaking here is the more natural or ordinary one ; if the analysans of an illuminating analysis must be clearer than the analysandum was before analysis, then nominalists cannot claim to have supplied an illuminating analysis. Secondly, the analysis is obviously incorrect if the universal conditional is extensional. For, the corresponding analysis of the false statement ' Red resembles Blue more than Orange ' would read ' for any x, y, z : if x is red and y is orange and z is blue, then x colour-resembles z more than y ', and both of these universal conditionals would in extensional interpretation be true if there existed either no red or no blue or no orange particulars. Only a subjunctive and modal formulation would preserve logical equivalence with the statement in the realistic language, but notoriously nominalists frown on subjunctives and modalities as much as on names of attributes. Indeed, the languages favoured by nominalists are extensional (though an extensional language need not be nominalistic), i.e. only truth-functional statement operators occur in them, hence neither modal operators nor the subjunctive ' if-then '. How this preference for extensional languages is connected with the dread of intensional entities, will be seen presently.

(b) Red is a colour, colour-similarity is a symmetrical relation.-Here nominalistic translation seems to be quite easy : ' anything which is red, is coloured ', ' for any x and y, if x colour-resembles y, then y colour-resembles x '. But as in the case of (a), these conditionals are inadequate translations if they are extensional. If, for example, no two particulars were similar in colour, then the same pattern of translation would justify the assertion that colour-similarity is an asymmetrical relation. And if we replace ' if . ., then . . .' with ' if . ., then necessarily . . .', we leave the nominalist profoundly dissatisfied, for modal talk is closely, perhaps inseparably, bound up with intensional talk. I n order to see the connection, we only need to note that ' if p, then necessarily q ' means ' i t is necessary that (if p, then q) '. Entailment-statements, as contrasted with material conditionals, are therefore reducible to the form ' it is necessary that p ', where ' p ' represents a conditional. I t is natural to construe ' that p ' here as a variable for which names of propositions, hence names of intensional entities, are to be substituted. Certainly such an interpretation is inevitable if one holds that every statement that might conceivably be made is about some entity or other. Even ' there are no unicorns ' is about something according to this semantical principle, viz., the null class (which is identical with the class of unicorns if ' there are no unicorns ' is true). The term ' about ' is widely used in

NOMINALISM, EMPIRICISM A N D UNIVERSALS

335

philosophical discourse, and the inconclusiveness of many philosophical disputes in which it is a key term (for instance, ' are logically true statements about the world ? ') is due to its obscurity. But on the basis of ' is a name o f ' i t can be satisfactorily defined for the present purpose : a sentence ' p is about an entity A if and only if ' p ' is extensional with respect to ' A ' (where ' A ' is a name of A), i.e. if ' q ' has the same truth-value as ' p ' if ' q ' results from ' p ' by substituting for ' A ' a different name of the same entity. Consider, now, a statement of assertion like ' X asserted that the present president of USA likes to play golf '. And let P be a property, other than that of being present president of USA, which Eisenhower and no other individual has. Then the truth of the above statement of assertion is clearly compatible with the falsehood of ' X asserted that the individual with property P likes to play golf' (for X may not know that the two descriptions appiy to the same individual). Therefore i t is not about the present president of USA but about an intensional entity, called by Frege the sense of the description ' the present president of USA ' and by Carnap the individual concept3 expressed by the latter. Considerations of this sort led Frege to say that the subordinate sentence in a statement of assertion or belief, or generally in a statement of ' propositional attitude ', functions as name of a proposition (a ' thought '), not as name of a truth-value. JIutatis mutandis, the same criterion of aboutness entails that if ' i t is necessary t h a t p ' is construed as ascribing a property, viz. necessity, to something, i t must be construed as ascribing i t to a proposition : the truth-value of the modal statement is necessarily preserved only if for ' p ' a sentence expressing the same proposition, not just one having the same truth-value, is substituted. There are two ways in which nominalists have attempted to interpret modal statements so as t o be able t o avoid intensional talk : (1) by a metalinguistic interpretation, according to which ' i t is necessary that p ' is a quasi-syntactic, or a t any rate quasi-semantic, statement form that should be replaced by something like ' ' p ' is analytic in L ',4 (2) by saying that modal sentences are expressions of linguistic rules and hence are not really used to make statements about anything. Whether either of these ways of avoiding propositions, as subjects of modal predicates, can succeed, is a long and complex story which cannot be told here and For my present purpose it suffices to have shown t h a t the nominalist cannot hope to dispense with such names as ' the quality Red ' unless he can do without names of propositions as well. (c) I like the smell of roses.-Does this mean ' for any particular x, if x smells like a rose, then I like x ' ? No, for a thing may in addition to its 3G. Frege, " On Sense and Nominatum ", in Feigl and Sellars, Readings ; R. Carnap, Meaning and Xecessity (Chicago 1947). 4See R. Carnap, Logical S y n t a x of Language, esp. sec. 63-71 ; and Meaning and Necessity, ch. 5. =Theproblem is discussed in some detail in my book Semantics and Necessary T r u t h (Yale University Press 1958), esp. ch. 5 and 7.

336

ARTHUR PAP

pleasant smell have so many unpleasant qualities that I dislike it as a whole. Can we provide for this possibility by the amendment : for any x, if x smells like a rose and has more pleasant than unpleasant qualities, then I like x ? No, for apart from the consideration that this statement looks suspiciously like a tautology, it clearly is not nominalistic since it mentions qualities and uses ' pleasant ' as a predicate applicable to qualities. Generally speaking, does not phenomenological inspection disclose that what one primarily likes or dislikes are qualities and that particulars are but derivative objects of likes and dislikes, i.8. are liked or disliked insofar as they are believed t o have qualities one likes or dislikes ? ' I like honesty ' does not entail ' I like honest people ', and for the stated reason it is small consolation for the nominalist that it does entail ' I like honest people provided their honesty is not outweighed by qualities I dislike '. The illustrated limitation of nominalistic language is a fact of greater philosophical significance than may be apparent a t first glance. Thus frank acceptance of the realistic mode of speech, as corresponding to facts disclosed by unprejudiced phenomenological inspection, may lead to clarification in ethical analysis. The primary object of a moral sentiment or attitude seems to be a repeatable characteristic of particular acts, not the particular acts themselves. I think it is a hazy recognition of this which is expressed by the use of the word ' tendency ' (and its derivatives) in the formulation of what have been called prima facie duties : for example, " any act of promise-keeping tends as such to be right ".'j What is meant by ' tends as such ' ? It is easy to explain by illustrations. A man who in a state of prosperity promises to make a sizable contribution to a charitable organization thereby incurs a " p r i m a facie " duty to act that way, but it may subsequently come into conflict with another prima facie duty, say, that of supporting his family. The function of the expression ' tends to be right ' here is to reconcile the moral rule with the fact that in these specific circumstances promise-breaking is the right thing to do. But what precisely is then asserted by the moral rule ? What does it mean to say that an act of kind A tends t o be right ? Usually a statement of the form ' a thing of kind A tends to be a thing of kind B ' means that most things of kind A are things of kind B. But ' acts of promise-keeping tend as such to be right ' hardly means that most acts of promise-keeping are right. We can conceive social life to be such that usually after a promise has been made circumstances arise which justify a breach of promise, yet the moral rule formulating a prima facie duty would still be valid in whatever sense moral rules can be called valid. Without, however, entering the controversy, on this occasion, about tlle meaning of ' (morally) right ', I suggest the logical point that ' tends as such ' may here be used to indicate that ' right ' is used as a secondlevel-predicate, i.e. as a predicate directly applicable to the kind of act connoted by ' promise keeping ', not to particular acts of that kind. When 6This formulation of the moral rule occurs in W. D. Ross's writings. See, for example, The Right and the Good, p. 28.

NOMINALISM. EMPIRICISM A N D UNIVERSALS

337

I say ' the taste of grapes is pleasing t o me ' I ascribe the predicate to a repeatable taste quality. The statement is not synonymous with ' every one of my grapes-testing-experiences is pleasant ', for there may be other components in an experience including such a taste sensation which are unpleasant (e.g. unpleasant sounds, or painful sensations in the mouth). Similarly, the object of the moral pro-emotion expressed by ' right ' is a repeatable feature of particular acts. To use Broad's well chosen terminology, to compute the total moral value of a particular act, we must weigh its " right inclining " characteristics against its " wrong inclining " characteristics. The characteristic itself, I suggest, may be called right or wrong, because it is the primary object of a moral sentiment or attitude ; and in saying with caution that it is " right inclining " we mean that from the fact that a particular act has that characteristics and the fact that the latter is right it does not follow that the particular act itself is right (that the same predicate expression of ordinary language is used on different type levels is a, philosophically misleading, defect of ordinary language). Second-levelpredicates must, of course, be banished from nominalistic discourse since they call for the names of attributes (or qualities, universals). But I do not see how the concept of a right-inclining (or wrong-inclining) characteristic could be analysed a t all by a nominalist. He might begin by translating ' f-ness is a right-inclining characteristic ' into ' for any particular act x, if x is f, then x tends t o be right ', but for the above reason I doubt that he could adequately explain the meaning of ' tends to be right '. Whether one is willing t o construe the verbs ' to like ', ' to dislike ',7 ' to (morally) approve ', ' to (morally) disapprove ' as designating dyadic relations whose converse domains consist of qualities, is connected with one's position on the old question whether it is qualities or particular instances of qualities that are perceived. A philosopher who holds that it does not even make sense to suppose that one perceives qualities-unless this be short for ' perceiving particular instances of qualities '-is likely to take the analogous position with respect to all mental states or dispositions that are characterized by " objective reference ". But what exactly is the difference between, say, seeing redness and seeing a red particular '2 I suppose that when I see a red particular I see redness conjoined with other qualities, specifically a shape and a size (' I saw a small, red, round patch '). But then it is perfectly proper t o describe the object seen as a complex of qualities which, by the criterion of repeatability, is itself a quality. The nominalist is likely to reply that what one sees is nevertheless a particular characterizable as red, round and small because a complete description of the object of perception would have to include a time and place, either phenomenal or physical. But I submit that this reply would reveal the linguistic nature of the dispute and that as a dispute about linguistic propriety i t is to be resolved in favour of realism. We might ask, in the formal 'TO be sure, we speak of our likes and dislikes of particulars, like particular persons, but it is always proper to ask ' what do you like (dislike) about him ? ', which question is answered by mentioning qualities.

338

ARTHUR PAP

mode of speech, what sort of expressions are properly substitutable for ' x ' in the function ' A sees x ' if the resulting sentences are to describe visual perceptions without commitment as to the existence of corresponding physical objects. Undoubtedly the answer is : (indefinite) descriptions referring to visual qualities, like ' a red, small, round patch '. Is there any objection to calling such an object a complex of qualities ? There is, of course, the suggestion that the patch is something in which the qualities inhere and that i t is the patch which is the object of perception. But if we allow ourselves to be misled by the predicative form in this manner, we shall end up with the contention that the perceived object is a place-time characterized by visual qualities. And a translation of this contention into linguistic terms yields : an accurate and complete description of a perceptual object must include names of a time and of a place. Now, in the first place, it is surely doubtful whether a person who described a seen object without mentioning a physical time and place could properly be accused of having described i t incompletely. If to the phenomenological description ' I saw a round, small, red patch ' I add ' and this happened in my study at 4 p.m. ', I do not thereby render my description of the seen object more complete ; I rather locate the event of seeing such an object in a physicalistic framework. Secondly, the perceptual object is indeed described more completely if one describes its position in the visual field (' a t the right upper corner of my visual field ') and its temporal relations to other perceptual objects (' I saw it immediately after I heard a loud noise of high pitch having the tonal quality of sounds emitted by trumpets '). But it may be held that phenomenal places and times are just as much qualities as colours, shapes and sizes ; and if they are, then the nominalist thesis concerning the objects of perception is not supported by the above argument (see IV f ) ). According to Quine's well known and frequently discussed criterion of ontological commitment, the speaker of a language L is committed to the existence of those entities to which the bound variables (in the primitive notation of L) must refer in order for the general statements of L to be true. For example, if a logician introduces the symbol of identity into his system by means of the Leibnizian definition [ (x = y) = (f) (fx fy) 1, he presupposes, according to Quine, the existence of attributes (of a given type). Accordingly, the problem of ' constructive ' nominalism, as conceived by Quine and G o ~ d m a n is , ~ the problem,of finding ways of transcribing classical mathematics and the platonistic logic of Principia Mathematics into a nominalistic language, i.e. a language whose variables (in the primitive notation) range only over particulars. But almost exclusive attention has been given to the nominalist's tough problem of making formal science live up to his austere standards of intelligibility. There is a tendency to assume 8W. Goodman and W. V. Quine, " Steps toward a constructive nominalism ", Journal of Symbolic Logic, Dec. 1947.

NOiVIINALISM, EMPIRICISM AND UNIVERSALS

339

that empirical discourse would not be seriously handicapped by a nominalistic renunciation of " abstract entities ". Yet, there are significant empirical statements involving attribute variables whose translation into nominalistic language is by no means obvious. Consider the example used by Whitehead and Russell, in the introduction to Principia ~Vathematica,to illustrate the concept of a second order function, i.e. a function defined in terms of a totality of first order functions : ' Napoleon had all the attributes of a great general '. This statement may be analyzed as follows : for any attribute f, if, for any individual x, x is a great general implies x has f, then Napoleon had f. I t ascribes, then, to Napoleon a complex property which is defined in terms of a universal quantifier ranging over attributes. The authors proceed to explain how one might get rid of the second order function here ; and though their purpose was not to give aid and comfort to nominalism but to make the axiom of reducibility seem plansible, their argument will be gratefully accepted by nominalists since it purports to show that attribute variables are in principle eliminable. Let a, b, c . . . n be all the great generals there are (at any time). Each one of them has some unique property, e.g. of being born a t a specified place and time. Let f, g, h . . . be such properties of which a, b, c . . . are unique instances. Then, according to their argument, the second order function, ' x has all the attributes of a great general ' is formally equivalent to, i.e, satisfied by the same entities as, the predicative function ' fx v gx v hx v . . .'. Now, this amounts to extensional translation-which is translation in a Pickwickian sense. It amounts to " translating " a statement which we understand without the historical knowledge of which are all the great generals (ex-en those as yet unborn) into a disjunction which could be formed only by a historian who is not only omniscient of the facts of past military history but even has foreknowledge of the birth-dates and birthplaces of the great generals of the future. Apart from this consideration, such a translation turns the translated statement into a statement that is formally deducible from any statement ascribing to Napoleon a unique property (like the combined place and time of his birth), since surely Napoleon himself must occur in the complete set of great generals. It is true that nominalists tend to be suspicious of any talk about meanings and relations of synonymy. But even the " constructive " nominalist arrives a t his reductive translations in no other way than by reflecting on the meanings of the statements t o be translated. There is no other way of discovering that ' the number of cats is greater than the number of dogs ' -to take an example from the paper cited in footnote 8-might be rendered nominalistically as ' either there are no dogs and a t least one cat, or there arc: a t least two cats and less than two dogs, . . . or there are a t least n cats ar d less than n dogs ' than to reflect on meanings. I n fairness to the nominalist i t should be pointed out, though, that there is a more plausible way of eliminating the attribute variable in ' Napoleon had all the attributes of a great general '. After all, the use of the locution

340

ARTHUR PAP

' all the attributes of a great general ' reflects one's uncertainty as to the meaning of ' great general '. If that meaning were quite clear, one could enumerate the great-general-making attributes, and then one would obtain a straightforward conjunction ' Napoleon was f, and f, and . . . f, ' where f,, f, . . . f,,, are all the attributes connoted by ' great general '. Yet, this method of elimination of quantifiers does not always work. Consider ' A has the same virtues as his father ' : it is not any more credible that the meaning of this sentence is unclear until the virtues are actually enumerated than that ' A and B have the same friends ' is unclear until A's and B's common friends are actually specified. Such a standard of clarity would confuse unclarity with generality. I am not denying that the second-levelpredicate ' is a virtue ' is t o some degree vague, since it means ' is (a human attribute which is) generally admired '. I am denying that a detailed listing of A's virtues with the comment that A's father has just the same virtues is an analysis of the meaning of the general statement. The latter asserts ' for every f : if f is a virtue, then A has f if and only if A's father has f ', and there is no way of expressing such a general proposition in a nominalistic language. For a similar reason the general, but perfectly precise proposibion that A and B have a t least one common colour (where A and B are multi-coloured things) cannot be nominalistically analyzed. A nominalist would, of course, attempt a reductive translation of the following kind : A and B are both (partly) f,, or they are both (partly) f,, or . . . or they are both (partly) fn, where f,, f, . . . f, are all the colours. But the essential comment ' where f,, f, . . . f, are all the colours ' transgresses again the boundaries of nominalistic discourse, since it means : for any quality f, if f is a colour, then f = f, v f = f, v . . . v f = f,.9 (To be continued) ARTHURPAP Yale University. 9Note that the nominalist o m o t get out of this difficulty by substituting the metalinguistic locution, ' where ' f, ', ' f, ', . ' f n ' are all the colour predicates ', for he would have to assume that overy colour is designated by some predicate of the given language.

..