Logical Possibility

  • 71 106 5
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up

Logical Possibility

George Seddon Mind, New Series, Vol. 81, No. 324. (Oct., 1972), pp. 481-494. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?si

1,272 73 352KB

Pages 16 Page size 595 x 792 pts Year 2007

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD FILE

Recommend Papers

File loading please wait...
Citation preview

Logical Possibility George Seddon Mind, New Series, Vol. 81, No. 324. (Oct., 1972), pp. 481-494. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0026-4423%28197210%292%3A81%3A324%3C481%3ALP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-X Mind is currently published by Oxford University Press.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/oup.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

http://www.jstor.org Sun Jul 22 18:44:12 2007

VOL. LXXXI NO. 3241

[October, 1972

MIND

A QUARTERLY REVIEW

PSYCHOLOGY A N D PHILOSOPHY I.-LOGICAL

POSSIBILITY

ISit logically possible that a bar of iron should float on water, or that there should be carnivorous rabbits on Mars? If the category of logical possibility is set up by exclusion, so that any state of affairs that is not logically impossible illust be regarded as logically possible, and ' logically impossible ' is defined in terms of self-contradictions of the form ' p and not-p ', then either we must show that there are contradictions here or the answer will be that it is logically possible that a bar of iron should float on water. That statement is not obviously self-contradictory. Yet we all know that it is not possible for a bar of iron to float on water, or that there be carnivorous rabbits on Mars, and if we insist that it is nonetheless logica2ly possible, we invite the comment that we are using the word ' possible ' in a very odd way, and that we will need good reasons for such a striking departure from ordinary usage. I doubt that good reasons are forthcoming. I believe that ' logical possibility ' has become a debilitating term because it blurs the distinction between science and pseudoscience, one variant of science fiction. I am no foe of science fiction, but see no reason why what can be imagined or what can be conceived should be confused with what " is possible. Although I am not sure that I can do so myself, many claiin that they can imagine a bar of iron floating, and we can certainly talk about it ( I do not want to say that such talk is meaningless: but I do want to say that it is impossible-short of a miracle, which we svill come to later). An important part of education is the acquiring of a sense of the possible; it comes slowly, with difficulty, and it must be nourished by a feeling for

482

G. SEDDON:

inter-relation, tho knowledge that in nature one can never do only one thing. Talk of ' logical possibility ' may weaken this sense, I think, although at no time in our history has it been so important to distinguish between what we can and cannot do, and to foresee the consequences of what we do. The negative term, ' logically impossible ' is also confusing. I can recognize a contradiction of the form ' p and not-p ', but no one goes around saying " p and not-p ". My local newspaper had the headline: " Floating crane sinks ", and we all knew quite well that it was still a floating crane, even on the bottom of the harbour. JJ7e knew not to reduce to the form ' p and notp '. A Hungarian friend of mine once remarked t h a i there are 110 husbands in Australia, only unmarried and married bachelors. This we recognize as a paradox rather than contradiction: we certainly do not reply: " That is logically impossible." ' Logical impossibility ' has nothing to do with what we ordinarily understand by ' possible ' and ' impossible '; it has to do with logic. Problems arise so soon as we ask whether the category of the ' logically impossible ' is supposed to exclude statements or states of affairs. f hat does it exclude them from? Clearly, from 'the possible '. But that does refer to states of affairs. So ' logically impossible ' must also refer to a state of affairs. But there are, and can be, no logically impossible states of affairs. These problems stem from a prior assumption, which we need not make, that some statements in a natural language can be known to be true, and others false, solely by inspecting the meaning of the constituent terms. But when apparent contradictions arise in a discussion, we never say: " That's a logical impossibility " (although we might say: " You are contradicting yourself "). Suppose the unlikely case that we hear someone say that a man gave birth to a child (or: " That man is a mother "). JTe reulv that ' he ' must in fact be a woman, because men do not bear children, and our linguistic distinctions have been devised expressly to reflect this reality. I can think of onlv two circumstances in which a statement such as ' that man is a mother ' might " be made. One is the case of someone who is learning the language, ant1 to him we would say, not " That's a logical inlpossibility ", but " Don't you mean ' father ' 2 " i.e. we would sav that he did not understand the words. The other is the case where we might say " That man has been both a mother and a father to his child " meaning that he has played both parental roles in its upbringing, and not that he fathered the child upon himself. The question of ' logical impossibility ' here could not arise unless we know that the A

d

LOGICAL POSSIBILITY

483

latter sense is not intended, or something like it: we must be sure that the man is saying " p and not-p "; that is, we must be sure that he really has failed to understand the words. And if we are sure, why say more than that? What further clarification is achieved by talk of ' logical impossibility '? Now for ' logical possibility '. What should we say about the statement that it is logically possible that a bar of iron float on water? (' Bar ' is intended to exclude the needle, supported by surface tension, and the new ' Queen ', Q4, floated on Zurich capital.) One move is to argue that although the statement that ' A bar of iron floats on water ' is not explicitly self-contradictory, it is implicitly so, for we are saying that a mineral with a specific gravity of less than one (i.e. it floats), has a specific gravity in the range 7.3-7.8 (i.e. it is iron), and this is a contradiction, and is therefore logically i~npossible. This move retains the category of logical impossibility and removes the absurdity of supposing that a bar of iron might float. But the debate now shifts to whether or not a s.g. of 7.317.8 is to be regarded as a defining characteristic of iron. There is no doubt that the mineralogist regards it as one; when an unknown mineralogical sample comes up for assay, one of the first tests performed is to determine its s.g., and if this falls outside the range of Fe, then the possibility that it be a fairly pure sample of metallic iron is totally excluded. However, the philosopher might argue that it is merely a contingent fact that Fe has a s.g. about 7 ; this may be true of all the iron encountered to date, but new forms might be discovered in the future with an s.g. less than 1. " Defining characteristics ", says the philosopher, " have not been constant in science. Look, for instance, a t wood. In the eighteenth century it might confidently have been asserted that wood floats (if it doesn't float, it's not wood). But this assumed that all wood has an s.g. less than 1, which proved not to be the case. Jarrah (Eucalyptus marginata) from the Swan River Colony in Western Australia and several of the ironwoods from eastern Australia, are considerably heavier than water. ' This makes it impossible to handle logs by floating, and has on occasion caused trouble in overseas ports, logs dumped from the ship into the water to be floated to their final destination finally sinking to the bottom ' (RIcLuckie and JlcKee, 1955, p. 599). So how can we say that iron must have a specific gravity greater than 72 " The philosopher may offer another illustration nearer home, discovery of isotopes: the term was introduced to apply to so called ' atomic species ' having the same atomic number but different nuclear structure, as indicated by different atomic

weight or different type of radioactivity. Thc physical and chemical properties of hydrogen, for example, were known with assurance, but our account of them was subsequently modified to accommodate deuterium, with a mass approxinlately double that of ordinary hydrogen, and with quite distinctive physical and chemical properties. For example, the heat of vaporization of D20, or heavy water, is about 260 cal. per gram greater than that of H,O. The point of the example, says the philosopher, is this: " We might, before the discovery of deuterium, have claimed a heat of vaporization of 540 cal. per gram as a defining characteristic of water, and argued from this that any subsequent statement that water has a heat of vaporization of 540 cal. per gram would be analytic (because we have already implied its heat of vaporization of 540 cal. per gram in calling it ' water '). We might then have argued that to deny that water has a heat of vaporization of 540 cal. per gram would be self-contradictory; therefore it is logically impossible for water to have a heat of vaporization of, say, 800 cal. per gram. Yet we would have been wrong. I t turns out that heavy water has such a heat of vaporization after all, and we have had to change our defining characteristics." But two simple points emerge from this discussion. One is that we have been discussing a language shift. The physical properties of H 2 0 have not changed. To the student who suggests that it is, after all, possible that water have a heat of vaporization of 800 cal. per gram we say, " Oh, you mean heavy water ". The ordinary language word ' water ' may be used by a physical chemist until such problems arise, but as soon as they do, it is abandoned: we must speak of H,O and D,O. If the student persists, saying " No, I just mean ' water ' ", we say that he does not understand the way these words are used in physical chemistry, like the man who did not know how to use the word ' father '. Questions of ' logical possibility ' would not normally be raised here at all. The second point, however, is that if a question does arise about the possibility that water have a heat of vaporization other than what we now think it to be, because perhaps of the discovery of further isotopes of hydrogen (tritium?) or oxygen, we are certainly not talking about logical possibility, we are talking about the possibility of a language shift plus some sort of empirical possibility (' empirical ' is at least a conventional philosophical term here, although scientists in fact talk about ' physical ' and ' theoretical ' possibilities, for reasons that I shall turn to presently). A similar story can be told about the bar of iron. As any

LOGICAL POSSIBILITY

485

first-year chemistry student knows, iron is tetramorphous, arid the four crystal forms differ slightly in physical properties. However, below temperatures of 760°C, iron is found a t equilibrium only in the u-form (' ferrite '). Ferrite is a soft, tough, grey-white metal with a cubic body-centred crystal lattice. Let us then discuss ferrite. It has an atomic number of 26 and four stable isotopes; 54, 56, 57 and 58, the atomic weight of a typical sample being 55.84, with a s.g. at 20°C of 7.87. It does not, therefore, float in water. The four isotopes are separable, and we might have a bar of each of them; the four bars would differ very slightly in s.g., but none of then1 would float in water either. (Note that the range of s.g. 7.317.8 given earlier in this discussion is now imprecise: it allows for minor impurities in what, a t a crude level of analysis, we were still prepared to call iron.) Specific gravity is dependent on density, being the ratio of the mass of a " given volume of a substance to the mass of an equal volume of water at a specified temperature and one atmosphere pressure. But density is not an independent property either: the density of a pure substance with a fixed chemical composition and crystabzing in a specific structure (in this case, body-centred cubic) is constant at a stated temperature and pressure. Quartz, for instance, which is practically invariable in composition, has a density of 2.65 g/cm3 at ordinary temperature and pressure. The other polynlorphs of SiO,, which crystallize in different structures, have different densities, that of cristobalite being 2.32 g/cm3 and of tridymite 2.26 g/cm3. For a " given substance. if the dimensions of the unit cell have been measured and the number and kinds of atoms in the unit cell are known, it is possible to calculate the density. I n point of fact this is standard ~rocedure. Densities determined from x-ray measurements provide a most useful independent check on densities as traditionally measured (e.g. by direct weight measurement, and volume determination via Archimedes principle); and converselv. ,. , densities so measured can be used to check the correctness of a proposed structure or chenlical formula. Any change in the density of an element would therefore, not be accompanied by, but in fact be either a change in the size of the unit cell or in the number or kind of atoms of which it is built up. If the latter, a change in atomic species is involved, by definition -and if the former, the physical properties which are determined by the lattice structure (e.q. crystal habit, cleavage, optical properties and so on) w ~ u l dalso change in such a way that we could no longer be talking about ferrite. None of this is in any way novel or surprising: it is thoroughly well known that the

486

G. SEDDON:

physical properties of a given nzineral are interdependent. Locke said that there is no connection betmeen the colour of gold and its malleability, but Locke was wrong. A glance at the Periodic Table shows that iron is one of the transition metals. all with related physical properties, and among them, density, which increases steadily from scandium (3.1 g/cm3) to copper (8.91 g/cm3); iron has as its immediate neighbours, manganese (7.21 g/cm3) below, and cobalt (8.70 g/cm3) above, and this alone indicates the possible density range for iron, which must fall between these two values. If by some oddity iron had not yet been discovered as a naturally occurring element, all of its major physical properties, including its density and specific gravity, could have been success full^^ predicted from its position in the Periodic Table. as was the case with hafnium. But here the weary logical possibilist may break in impatiently and say: " Yes. we all know that iron does not in fact float in water, but you persist in talking about factual consequences ant1 empirical possibility, which is not the point at issue. It is still true that the specific gravity of iron is a contingent fact: it is not self-contradictory to conceive that it might have been different." My problem, of course, is to conceive what this ' might ' might possibly mean when it clearly has no meaning in the linguistic context in which terms such as ' specific gravity ' are applicable. Moreover, I would contest the claims that I have been talking about ' empirical ' possibility, or rather, I would suggest that this, too, is an inadequate term for the purposes of this discussion. We are, by philosophical convention, offered three categories, technical, empirical and logical possibility, of which the first is a proper subset of the second, and the second of the third. There is no serious difficulty about understanding what is meant by ' technical possibility ' (within the range of present technology), although the difficulties commonly encountered in estimating it are worth brief investigation. We ask a firm of engineers to determine whether of not it is technically possible to build a single-span bridge fro111 Point A to Point B, across the Swan River. They may be able at once to point to a bridge built under circumstances which are similar in all relevant respects, in which case we are talking of actualities rather than possibilities, provided their professional judgment of the circumstances is sound. Failing this, they do some calculations, on the basis of which they will either say that the bridge is technically possib1e.l or demonstrate fro111 engineering theory that it What the engineers are nlore likely to say is that the bridge is feasible. I t would usually be called ' technically possible ' only if this were being

487

LOGICAL POSSIBILITY

is not possible, or ask for a second opinion. Let us suppose that they choose the first and go ahead and build the bridge. Eithcr it stands, in which case they were right in claiming that it was technically possible, or it falls don-n. If it falls down, there is an enauirv. and a firm of consultant engineers with an international reputation is called in. They give evidence: there are again three conclusions available. Either the bridge was technically possible, but something (specifiable) went wrong. Or they will show that the bridge is after all a theoretical impossibility. Or they will say that they do not know whether such a bridge is technically possible or not, i.e. engineering theory is not sufficiently developed to make a firnl prediction frorn the available evidence. Several points emerge from the discussion of this example. One is that possibility claims are, in general, predictive-a clairtl is being made about the future. Kext, possibility clainls can only be assessed relative to the evidence. As thc word is most commonly used-some exceptions will be noted-possibility is a form of probability. ( I t is true that we sonletimes say " that is possible, but not probable " but by this we mean only that we are assigning a lour probability.) Now the meaning of the word ' probable ' is incomplete without specification of the evidence. We can no more say (other than elliptically) " that is probable " than we can say " that is equal " or " that is relative ". Probability claims are predictions based on evidence. A precliction is not a guess: if a nlan claims to make a prediction, but can give no evidence for it, and denies that he has any, we say that he is guessing: he doesn't know whether the event is probable or not. The only honest answer to many questions in science is " we don't know ". But it is trivial to claim that when we do not know whether something is possible or not, we cannot exclude its being possible, and therefore it is possible. In this situation, neither can we exclude its being impossible, and we should speak of ignorance rather than possibilities. This, in my view, is how vie should talk about extrasensory perception: we don't know whether it is possible or not, because there is not enough evidence, or theory, to form a reasonable basis for estimating probabilities. It is possible only in the trivial sense that we do not know it to be inlpossible-but then neither do we kno1~-it to be possible. I am now in a position to n~akea final point about the bar of I

d

L

contrasted with other aspects of the total situation, e.g. tecllnically possible, b ~ c et rorionlic;~llpnrlnouq, or ~ ~ o l ~ t ~ ccil~bio~ls, ally or aestl~eticallyundesirable.

458

G.

SEDDON:

iron. Suppose that I have said all that I have about the specific gravity of iron and its place in the Periodic Table. illy persistent questioner then asks: " But what would you say, if you had done all the tests, including a specific gravity test, and got all the right answers, and then put the bar in water, and it floats? " My answer, of course, is that I would say i t was a miracle, and I nox define ' miracle ' as an event of zero probability. This should dismay neither those who believe in miracles, nor those who reject them, since their probability could only be estimated from the evidence of observed regularities, whereas nliracles by definition run contrary to these regularities. When we are discussing possibilities we are not discussing the possibility of miracles. I would like to think with Sir Thomas Brou-ne that miracles are impossible, and believe in them because of that (credo quia impossibile est). Have I then conlrnitted myself to the viem- that there is only empirical and technical possibility? Not quite. I11 discussing the bridge we passed from technical to theoretical possibility. The latter category needs discussion, and perhaps one should explain why scientists rarely discuss empirical possibilities. However, I have also noted above that there are some legitimate uses of the word ' possible ' that do not fall within the present framework of discussion, and perhaps we should give an example, for contrast. I ask a friend whether he is going skiing over the week-end. He says: " I doubt it, I have a lot of work on hand. Still, I guess it's a possibility." This is a conlmon use of the word, but a specialized one, because the ' possibility ' referred to has little to do with physical possibility-we know our friend has skis, can ski, and often does so during the week-end. TVe also know that if the snow conditions deteriorate-if there is a quick thaw, for instance-the whole conversation is cancelled. TTTetake all that for granted. " It's a possibility " here translates: " I haven't made up my mind: I haven't definitely decided against it." In this and similar cases, we do not ask for evidence, but in talking of technical, empirical, and theoretical possibility, we do, and to these I return. The term ' empirical ' has sonlewhat derogatory overtones in science. For instance, hydraulic engineers make use of a streamflow velocity equation, known as the Manning equation. Here is a discussion of the Manning equation from a recent book on hydraulic theory: " It is truly surprising that engineering practice has depended to such an extent on a fornlula as enlpirical as this one, derived nearly a century ago " (Leopold, Wolnlan and Miller, 1964, p. 158).

LOGICAL POSSIBILITY

489

Discussing problems of sediment transport, it is later (p. 129) argued that " The number of empirical equations itself testifies to the continuing need of a more fundamental knowledge of the basic processes governing sediment movement. Because of the variables involved, it appears likely that major advances will be made primarily through advances in theory and critical experiments rather than by amassing volumes of additional data." Comments such as this are commonplace in any branch of science which is just emerging from the pre-theoretical phase. For exanlple, tidal prediction was so scandalously empirical in the early nineteenth century that the British Association for the Advancement of Science, founded in 1831, devoted 10 per cent of its budget in the first decade of its life to tidal research. And rightly so : the empirically derived tidal tables, like the Manning equation, have limited explanatory power, and also limited predictive power in the sense that the range of their application cannot be fully grasped without a theoretical basis. But crystallography and mineralogy have not been empirical in this sense for many years, and it would be profoundly misleading to say that the specific gravity of iron is a mere empirical fact. The specific gravity of iron, the place of iron in the Periodic Table, and its physical, cheniical and atorilic character can be discussed only in the context of a highly integrated and coherent physical theory, and this is why one wants to say that it is theoretically impossible that the bar should float, and not merely empirically impossible. hIuch more is a t stake than a series of observations on the behaviour of iron bars in water. I t is true that there appear to be degrees of theoretical impossibility-some things seen1 to be more impossible than others -but this need not puzzle us. Our confidence in the assertion of theoretical impossibility will depend on two things; first, the completeness and precision of the demonstration of impossibility from theory; and second, our confidence in the theory itself. Science does not deal in certainties, and no assertion of theoretical impossibility can claim to be incorrigible. But the only residue of possibility here is of the trivial kind already discussed. What scientists can do is to clairn that a given event has zero probability relative to the evidence, or is incorilpatible with a given theory. I t used to be argued, for instance, that it is irilpossible to exceed the velocity of light (c) within the special theory of relativity, for within that theory a body accelerated from a speed less than c to one greater than c would acquire energy and inonlenturn expressed by an imaginary number-and this does not seem to have any physical meaning. It is curious that Pap,

490

G. SEDDON:

who spells out this exan~plein detail as an example of logical impossibility (1962, p. 54), prefaces his discussion thus: " Is it meaningless to suppose that there occur, or may occur, motions exceeding the velocity of light? I t seems to be a perfectly meaningful supposition, for even if it be true that the velocity of light is the upper limit for all physically possible velocities, this is a physical fact; in other words, what we suppose to be the case is a t most empirically impossible, not logically impossible, hence it must be allowed to be a significant supposition." He then goes on to show that the supposition is nonetheless ' meaningless ' within the context of the special theory of relativity. But why suppose that it is possible when no context is specified, no theory indicated or evidence cited, without which the probability of the supposition cannot be assessed at all? This is to talk no language (other than philosophy!) Perhaps Pap's question was intended to mean : " Does this supposition have meaning within the context of subatomic physics? " This question has been revived by physicists (Torsten Alviiger and Michael N. Kreisler, 1968: The Physical Review, vol. 171, no. 5, pp. 1357-1361; Gerald Feinberg, 1967: The Physical Review, vol. 159, pp. 10891105; 1970: Scienti$c American, vol. 222, no. 2, pp. 68-77). But they have not asked the question as Pap does. First, Feinberg argues that the now classical objections hold only in the case of bodies that are accelerated though the speed of light. But " we now know t h a t . . . subatomic particles can easily be created or destroyed, and that in their mutual interactions their energies and other properties change discontinuously . . . therefore one can imagine the creation of particles already travelling faster than light, and so avoid the need for accelerating them through the ' light barrier ' with the attendant expenditure of infinite energy " (Peinberg, 1970, p. 69). This might suggest that Feinberg is arguing, in the philosopher's way, that velocities greater than c are after all logically possible within relativistic theory. But of course he is not doing that, as we see from what follows. Having shown that such particles are not ruled out by theory, he goes looking for them. He has not found any yet, and there may not be any: " The . . . possibility is . . . that nature has not filled the niche that is allowed by the theory of relativity " (1970, p. 77). But this is not accepted as a ' brute fact '; that is, such particles could exist, but just happen (' contingently ') not to. If they do not exist, then this immediately calls for further explanation, although " we may not understand why it sliould be so until we reach a much deeper understanding of the nature of elementary particles than now

LOGICAL POSSIBILITY

49 1

exists " (1970, p. 77). Thus in no context is it adequate to speak of the velocity of light's being an upper limit as a " physical fact ", as Pap does, and then to consider the logical possibilities beyond this " fact ". What about the carnivorous rabbits on Mars? Is this a possibility of any sort? I say that it is not, that it is theoretically impossible, and if we admit that it is not quite so impossible as the bar of iron's floating, t h s is not because of a residue of possibility, but because of a residue of ignorance. We could, of course, again turn the trick of showing that it is logically impossible, in that in saying that they are carnivorous it can be shown that they are not rabbits, because ' herbivorous ' is a defining characteristic of ' rabbit '. But this does not satisfy me; there is more to it than that. So let us anatomize. Is life of any sort possible on Mars? This is a matter on which scientists disagree, but their disagreement can be explored from a prior agreement as to what-at least roughly-is to count as evidence. For instance, the white polar caps, which wax and wane with the seasons, are thought to be areas covered with dry ice to a thickness probably not exceeding an inch. The seasonal changes in the polar caps are accompanied by changes in the dark surface markings on Mars: with the shrinking of each cap the region around the cap darkens: the dark areas become more distinct, and some of them take on a greenish hue. It is just possible that these changes are vegetational changes in lowly plants like our hardy mosses and lichens. But when we say that it is just possible, we mean that there is some positive evidence, not merely that we do not yet know it to be impossible. There is also much negative evidence: the mean temperature for the entire planet is about 60" below zero F, compared with 60" above zero for the earth. Free oxygen is generally estimated as much less than 1 per cent and water vapour only a tenth of 1 per cent of our supply. Are rabbits possible on Rlars? Clearly not. For one thing, they would be frozen for most of the year (this is not meant, however, to raise the possibility that there are frozen rabbits on Mars). Are carnivorous rabbits possible, anywhere? No, this is a theoretical absurdity. Rabbits belong in the order Lagomorpha, and the lagomorphs have a place in the infra-class of eutherian mammals which is admittedly not as tightly structured as that of iron in the Periodic Table; nevertheless certain characteristics are grouped in a theoretically necessary way. Rabbits have the dentition of a herbivore- they could not rcrt meat as they have no canines to tear it with. They have a

492

G.

SEDDON:

herbivorous digestive system, and could not digest meat. Rabbits have the Rabelaisian habit of coprophagy: the stomach and intestinal system are adapted for the ingestion of large quantities of vegetation quickly, resulting in the production and excretion of capsules (soft pellets) rich in bacteria, and of high nutritive and digestive value. which are swallowed whole (reingested) a t leisuz in the safe& of the underground burro;. d carnivorous rabbit would get a nasty shock in the burrow. It follows from the Principle of Natural Selection that any biologically successful species is broadly adapted to its environmental niche. Rabbits are prey rather than predators, but they are well adapted to this role. Their very high birth rate, for instance, would be disastrous in a predator, which would rapidly outstrip food supplies. Even the familiar white scut and the long ears are functional: the scut is a social alarm signal which protects the group; it would be inappropriate in a stealthy predator. The eye socket is large to support the large crepuscular eye. The powerful feet are adapted to bounding escape flight, and to digging and shovelling earth during excavation. These characteristics are not, admittedly, logically entailed by each other, or by some essence-of-rabbit. But they cannot be treated entirely independently within biological theory either. To make a rabbit a successful carnivore we should have to restructure him so thorouehlv that no one-leave alone the zoou < logists-would want to call him a rabbit any more. We would also, incidentally, have to rewrite the evolutionary history of the lagomorphs, which is already fairly well known. This demonstration of theoretical impossibility may be less convincing than that of exceeding the velocity of light within the context of the special theory of relativity used to seem. If so, it is because the rabbit demonstration cannot be eiven in mathematical form. and perhaps because the theory o f v ~ a t u r aSelection l may seek to some less fully articulated or less well founded than the special theory of relativity. But there is no room here for loyical possibility. The only way in which we could come to call a carnivorous animal a rabbit is that we could, after all, conle one day to use the word ' rabbit ' to refer, for example, to the animal we now call a tiger. But this has no bearing on the category ' logical possibility '. Perhaps we are most tempted to think that there are possibilities that survive demonstrations of theoretical impossibility in cases like the following: I take my wife to the doctor. He says she has cancer, and that it is impossible that she live for more than six months. I think: " XTell,I won't buy the coffin L L



LOGICAL POSSIBILITY

493

yet, anyway." Or the balm example in a slightly different form: I have a friend who tells me that he took his wife to the doctor five years ago, was told that she had an incurable disease and could not possibly live more than six months. " Then I took her to all the specialists and the clinics, no expense spared, and they all said the same thing. Not a chance." But there she sits on the sofa opposite you, beaming testimony to the triumph of motherhood and femininity over the laws of medical science. What do we say here? If we are prudent, we do not say anything, but we doubt that the doctors did say just what was attributed to them. Good doctors are not much given to unconditional prediction. But suppose they did: then they were wrong. A claim that a given event is theoretically impossible from a medical point of view may be falsified either because the demonstration is defective: the doctors got the theory wrong, or applied it incorrectly: or because the theory itself is defective or inadequate. nledical science is highly pragmatic. Any doctor admits that there is much that we do not know about health or sickness, and he usually prefaces his conclusion with ' so far as we know ', and he means it. One runs beyond the boundaries of medical science into sheer ignorance fairly quickly. But there is still no room here for logical possibility. What there may seem to be room for is a weak but non-trivial form of a theoretical possibility of the form: we cannot be quite sure that it is theoretically impossible because the theory is not good enough-but we cannot say for sure that it is impossible, so I guess you can say that there is some possibility here. The doctor says: " All the evidence is against it, but you never know." But he does not really mean that all the evidence is against it, but only the specific and immediately relevant evidence. He reads this against background evidence (called ' professional experience ') of the form: " Doctors make mistakes; patients we would not give a nickel for sometimes just mysteriously do get better." So his concession is based on evidence, and the possibility here is a weak form of empirical possibility, assigning a low probability to an event he thinks unlikely. Yet before I conclude I must make an admission: I am conscious of seeming to beg a qnestion throughout this paper. When I say that the density of iron must fall between the values for manganese and cobalt: when I say that rabbits must be herbivorous: what is the force of this ' must '? This is the question that I cannot quite answer. Are these necessary truths? Only if we claim that with the help of definitions, the denial of these propositions can be shown to be self-contradictory.

494

G. SEDDON : LOGICAL POSSIBILITY

yet I claim that there is more at stake than this. So I must be talking about the world, about contingent truths, about statesof-affairs that might have been different. But a rabbit cannot be a carnivore; and so we go round again. Waismann (1951: 'Analytic-Synthetic 111'' Analysis, 11 (3): 49-51) discusses a comparable dilemma, of which he says: " The reason for this wavering between opposite poles is that this is a case in which the philosophical antithesis ' contingent-necessary ' loses its edge." Yet his examples (" time is measurable ", " space has three dimensions "), are much more rarified than mine. Iron sinks in water, but it could have been otherwise. Perhaps: but how much else are we allowed to know ? I t couldn't if it i s still to be one of the transition metals with a place in the Periodic Table. But the Periodic Table could have been otherwise: it toas not inscribed on the underside of the Mosaic tablets. Perhaps it could be otherujise: and perhaps there could be a world in which organisms are not functionally adapted to their environment. Well, perhaps: yozc never know: anything can happen. Nature is bountiful, and full of surprises, and there's plenty more where that came from. Think cornucopian.

University of Western Australia

AfcLuckie, J. and McKee, H. S. (1955). Australian and New Zealand Botany. Associated General Publications, Sydney. 758 pp. Leopold, Luna B., \fTolman, Gordon W.and Miller, John P. (1964). Pluvial Processes i n Geomorphology. W . H . Freeman & Co., San Francisco. 522 pp. Pap, Arthur (1962). A n Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. The Free Press of Glencoe, h-ew Pork. 444 pp. Alvager, Torsten and Kreisler, Michael N. (1968). ' Quest for faster than light particles '. The Physical Review, 171 ( 5 ) : 1357-1361. Feinberg, Gerald (1967). ' Possibility of faster-than-light particles '. The Pl~ysicalReaieu,, 159 (5): 1089-1105. Feinberg, Gerald (1970). ' Particles that go faster than light '. Scienti$c American, 222 (2): 68-77. Waismann, Friedrich (1951). ' Analytic-Synthetic, I11 '. Analysis, 11 (3): 49-51.

http://www.jstor.org

LINKED CITATIONS - Page 1 of 1 -

You have printed the following article: Logical Possibility George Seddon Mind, New Series, Vol. 81, No. 324. (Oct., 1972), pp. 481-494. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0026-4423%28197210%292%3A81%3A324%3C481%3ALP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-X

This article references the following linked citations. If you are trying to access articles from an off-campus location, you may be required to first logon via your library web site to access JSTOR. Please visit your library's website or contact a librarian to learn about options for remote access to JSTOR.

References Analytic-Synthetic III F. Waismann Analysis, Vol. 11, No. 3. (Jan., 1951), pp. 49-61. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0003-2638%28195101%2911%3A3%3C49%3AAI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Z